145
146
adhering to certain fundamental metaphysical stipulation*
Both for the Visistadvaitins as well as the Prabhakaras
the nature of judgement is such that it must be revela
tory in character. It must point at something beyond
itself. And so far as this pointing at something beyond
is concerned the judgement cannot be falsified. Truth,
in this sense, is intrinsic to all judgements. The
ordinarily called false judgements are so interpreted :i
that the fundamental claim that all judgements are true
remains, in all eases, unaffected. . I
In Buddhism, on the other hand, the
fundamental claim which is universally accepted is that
judgement is such that it cannot faithfully represent
or describe the referent and consequently all judgements I
are intrinsically invalid (auramanya). This claim for
universal error in case of all judgements puts the
Buddhists in the opposite eamp. The negative attitude
towards judgement gives rise to a different analysis
of error.
147
(1) ATMKHYln
The Vaibhasika, the Sautrsntika and the
Vi;jnana~vada are known as the advocates of a widely
1 .
known theory of error, l,fe*T Afenakhyatl* However this
theory of itsakhyati is explained differently in each o.
these schools* The Vaibhasikas are identified as Sarv&sti
vadins who emphasis the Buddhistic proposition, 1sarvam
atl* (everything exists)* By sarvam' only the dharaas a$4
not the imdgalas are really meant. The term dharma in
this context may mean those characteristics which
2
characterise the uniquely particular (sva~3.skSana).
1* Vide: B.K*Ben.guptas The Problem of Nacre-Silver
(Sykti-Rupya) in Indian Philosophy, The Indian
. Historical Quarterly* Vol.XXVlIX, June, 1952, No*2,
pp*I5?-l?6, and A.XChewdhury j The Doctrine of Mayi,
2M*9M.*, pp,38-36*
2. * Pharma11 is often translated as elements- by many
'writers on Buddhism. But I have ignored this rendering
because element* in English language has a substantive
use while Buddhism, In general, is opposed to any
j&ubgtnntlve approach* It is primarily attributive
which gives more importance to characteristics than
149
149
is concerned, the Yaibhasikas seem to emphasize the point
that all such knowledge is, by natural implication, not
of the bare referent. Those are rather from the very
start involved with universal!sation or conceptualisation
Any ordinary judgement, though its prime objective is to
refer the bare particular, fails to attain this objective;
because it, besides referring or pointing at the particul ar,
is also, responsible for attributing the concept of aggref,
gate,whole or composite upon the real dharma. This
postulation of a whole or the attribution (Samarona) of
//, . , , , r '
pudgala upon dharma is due to what is known as
/, /
1 1 "
Satkayaj drsti.
To put it in other words, the
Yaibhasikas are committed to accept all judgements to be
!,, . v\
erroneous because judgements, by definition, refer to a
hi
"/ ; Y\
determinate object Csavikalaaka vastu) which is not a
bare unrelated simple particular but a universalised
complex^i
. ,'i ; /> I , '
characterised by itself is termed as svalaksana.; "iSvam
asadhdrianam laksanam tattvam svalaksanam" i Hyajk -
bin'du y bika tul5. ' rr \
1. A .K/Ohatter jee. The Yogdcara Idealism. Banara^ Hindu
150
Here a point may be raised. If all judge
ments are doomed to be false then how one is to account
the ordinarily accepted distinction between a true and
a false judgement? It is pointed out that the Vaibhasikas
hold the doctrine of Atmakhyati. According to a general
version of &t.mflkhvatiT Error consists in regarding the
internal object as external, the mental as the extra-
mental (Jnanakarasyaiva bahiravabhaso vibhramaljt) This
would suggest that in case of a false judgement like.,
*This is silver* it is the silvery predicate, which is
surely subjective and in no way belongs to the externally
given referent, i.e.. this*. This silvery predicate is
wrongly predicated of the given. This* as the bare
referent of the erroneous judgement is, however, real.
Only when it is characterised as silver error results.
Error is, no doubt, due to mischaracterisation. Only,
the characteristic, which is attributed of the given,
is something internal or subjective and does not in
any sense belong to .the given, From this explanation of
1. A.K.Roy Chowdhurr: dp.cit., p.33.
151
Atmakhyati, it may at best mean that for the Vaibhasikas
the ordinarily called false judgement refers something
mental as extra-mental or internal as external whereas
the so called true judgement takes something in the same
way in which it actually is. It is only in error, something
internal, is being judged as external.
But this explanation on close scrutiny
appears to be no more than a pseudo-explanation. Because
as we have discussed earlier, for the Vaibhasikas who
hold the reality of dharmas alone as against pudgalas
the real must stand ,for the bare particular (svalaksana)
I
which is not characterised from without but from within.
This bare particular thus is not different from the uniqii.^
referent in any situation. In any judgement this unique
particular is necessarily referred and in that sense all
judgements point at something beyond. But no judgement,
by its very nature, is confined to the bare given,rather
each judgement always qualifies the given by means of
some generic features (samanya laksana) which do not
belong to it. It is only In this sense, all judgements
152
are declared as erroneous since they do not merely-
refer the mere * that1 but necessarily ^attribute Certain
brel gtl- 'tCathres ;t!o 'that'.
Now if it is conceded that in any
judgement there is every possibility (logical possibility)
of falling short of the bare given and of the inclusion
of certain foreign characteristics, then the false judgej-
ment alone need not be distinguished from the true ones
by this mode of reasoning* If, in the case of a false
judgement *This is silver1 the silver-characteristics
are said to be something internal and are said to have
been wrongly applied to Jthis; then, in a right judge
ment too (i*e, while silver is actually judged as silvefl)
the silvery characteristics, in so far as they actually
describe this* (the non-descriptive unique individual),
there is the same logical possibility of error. Because
the this1, by its very nature, is devoid of any
universalisation. The very attempt of grouping it as a Jff k-r
r
member under the universal, i.e.. silverhood is surel|- f
to put something more tha1?. what is actually presented.^
153
That, which is applied :over the given particular, is
surely devoid of any externality and hence may be termed
as internal. That something internal is judged as externa},
is not only applicable in ease of erroneous judgement but
it also affects equally the non-erroneous judgements?.. The
dharmas are never known as they really are but always as
somewhat different.
This shows that the theory of Atmakhvati as
rendered by the Vaibhasikas cannot logically aim at
explaining the empirical distinction between true and falfee
perceptual judgements. The theory, from this point of vlejrj,
can easily be seen as not really explaining the empiric
illusion and erroneous perception. It actually is not mead
to account for the distinction between Empirically true apjd
false judgements. So far it points out that in error
something (mental) is wrongly judged as something differep
(extra-mental), there is no logical inconsistency. It is
the very nature of error under all circumstances that a
thing when judged differently than what it is, confusion
starts. Thus far the Atmakhyativadins are not to be
seriously opposed by any rival theorists.
154
But the differences between these
several theories become explicit when from the morale
of this logical distinction between truth and error
certain philosophical view is drawn. The Vaibhasikas
being Buddhists adopt the conclusion that all judgements,
since those are not confined to the svalaksanas, are
fundamentally false (svatah apramanva) This conclusion
is, no doubt, based on a logical argument, viz., all
descriptions carry the possibility of misdescriptions.
1
Since no judgement can be framed without describing
and can exclusively refer the pure individual, each
i , ;
judgementj therefore^ falls short of the real. If the
real is taken as bare dharma then this conclusion regard!ng
the invalidity of all judgements inevitably follows. As
all judgements necessarily distort the dharma. by attri
buting pudgala on it.
The Sautrantikas agree with the
Vaibhasikas in so far as they admit the svalaksanas.
1, Vide: Kalpana hi buddhi-visesah quoted by Hiriyanna,
op.cit., p.204.
In this sense both of them belong to one camp. But while
the Vaibhasikas bluntly admit the direct perception of
the svalaksanas, the Sautrantikas hesitate to admit the
direct perception of such data. The difference between till
two schools have been summed up as ones acceptance of tljije
doctrine of direct perception of the external object
(faaiiya-pratyaksa-vada) and others acceptance of the
\
inferability of the external object (bahya-anumeva-vada)
The main difficulty that the Sautrantikas bring against
the Taibhasikas is that since the fundamental Buddhistic
doctrine of momentariness (Ksana-bhahga-vada) suggests
that everything remains only for a moment, and then it is'
succeeded by another; it is difficult to admit in this
context that the object is perceived directly. For the
object to be perceived, at least two moments are necessary.
At one moment, the object serves as the cause of perception
and at the other, it is actually perceived. But this could
suggest that the object must remain for both of these two
1
moments. And this is exactly which is rejected by the
ft o
1* 11 varttamanalambanagraharie ca ksanabhangabadhah.
Madhyantavibha ga-sutrabhasyatIka by Sthiramati,
Part I, ed. V.Bhattacharya and G.Tuccl, Luzac & Co,
1932, p.21.
156
doctrine of momentariness. If objects are really
momentary, it is only a past object that is perceived.
Hence, what is apprehended in:. perception, though exists
is not apprehended at the moment when it exists.
Here the object being momentary
stands for a particular svalaksana. The Sautrantikas
argue that the svalaksanas alone are real. They are
not directly perceived but are merely inferred from
the past impressions. It is the impression (samskara)
which is known and through impression alone the
svalaksana is inferred. Some have taken the Sautrantiks
* 1
view point as resembling the Lockean representationism.
But the difficulty in such a rendering is that while
the Sautrantikas only infer the svalaksanas to be
external the Lockean representation!sm postulates a
substance-in-itself as the source of all ideas. The
Sautrantika, as a Buddhistic school, is opposed to all
forms of substantive approach.
But whether the svalaksanas are
9 *
. , P r3?T-
157
directly perceived or are inferred, nothing significant
seems to he gained so far as the discussion of error is
concerned. For both these schools of Buddhism adhere to
the position that any judgement, in so far as it involves
kalj?anas is bound to be erroneous. It characterises the |
given more than what actually it has. Since knowing is j
judgemental there is no escape from conceptualision. It ^
is this subjective attribution or conceptualisation which
always distorts the real. The view as to whether the
object (artha) is known directly or indirectly does not I
at all affect the account of error. Both agree that all
judgements, carrying the possibility of misjudging, are '
fundamentally falling short of the given.
Dr.Sengupta writes that the
Sautrantikaand the Vaibhasika, however, recognise
the externality of the substratum of super -
imposition. In the nacre-silver, the nacre,
according to this interpretation,
15S
is said to be the substratum of the erroneous cognition
of silver. This isj thereforej called Sadhisfchianabhrama
vada. Tho piece of silver falsely cognised on a piece of
nacre is existent only in knowledge and the error arises
only when we falsely suppose it to be present outside
1
the knowledge.
This rendering of the Sautrantlka-
Vaibhasika position suggests that their view on error is
actually about the instances of erroneous perception.
While nacre, for instance, is misperceived as silver it
is argued that silver is real as something > mental and
nacre Is real as something objective.Error arises in
identifying the internal as the external* But if the
argument of these Buddhists is carried to its logical
end in thway indicated above, then under no ground of
comprehensibility din can be asserted that the nacre is
to be accepted as really existing outside. The ground
on which silver is argued to be 'mental "or sub jective^ ojr. the
Op*cit., pp*157-162*
159
sam ground too nacre can be said to be -subjective.*;. If the
svalaksanas or the bare particulars are accepted as
only real, then under no logical ground nacre can be
said to be real, Nacre is plainly not svalaksana but is
already involved with samanyalaksanas. To put it in
other words, to judge the given, both as silver as well
as nacre5from this point of view, becomes erroneous* It
is the very nature of judgement that when it judges the
thing, it judges it not as it is,but as something more
than what it actually is. To that extent any judgement
carries the possibility of giving a distorted picture
of the real.
So not only one perceptual judgement
is favoured in preference to another but all judgements
whether perceptual or inferential are clearly declared
to be erroneous. Atmakhya tivada precisely stands as a
critique of all judgements. There is absolutely no point
in emphasizing the theory of Atmakhvati as a theory
about illusion or erroneous perception. Here the Buddhist
philosophers are not engaged in a psychological problem
160
about erroneous perception, but are involved in a logical
problem of analysing and determining the concept of error
The theory is not meant to explain the empirical distinction
between a true and a false judgement. The theory rather
concludes, by way of revising the meaning of term real
as bare particulars, that all judgements, being involved
with concepts and classifications are intrinsically false
Hence the critic ism**- that Buddhism fails to distinguish
an empirically true judgement from a false one becomes
simply outside the point. By accepting the test of truth
in terms of arthakriya the Sautrantikas distinguish
between a true and a false judgement.
The Vijnanavadins who are also
identified as Yogacaras accept the doctrine of Atmakhvati
2
in a slightly different manner. They, however, subscrib^
.This d-S-thS line of criticism advanced by Karl lUPotter
against Buddhism in - general. op.cit., pp,187-195,
2, The school is called Yogacara since it declares that
the absolute truth (Bodhi) is attainable only by thos^
who practice yoga and 'acara1. Yogacara is known
to have brought out the practical side of the
philosophical teachings of Buddhism while Vijhana-syadh
brings out its speculative or argumentative aspects.
Ib'l
to the general version of this theory of error, viz;
in all cases of falsity it is the mental''?,! which is
mistakenly judged as extra*mental4h While! kpilining the
theory in terms of a specific illusory perception of
snake-rope, it is argued that it is the subjective idea
of snake which is mistakenly thought to be present
outside. Thus far, there is, of course, no genuine
difference between these Vijnana-vadins and the Vaibhasl
kas and the Sautrantikas. The difference lies in some
minute details when the Vi'jnana-vadin denies with emphasi^
the reality of the external given. The theory is not
prepared to interprete the referent of the judgement
in an objective mode as opposed to the subjective mode.
Let me explain my point of view in further details
For both the Vaibhasikas as well
as the Sautrantikas reality consists of the unique
particulars in the sense of bare referents for logically
proper names. Both the schools adhere to this point so
far as the plane of logical reasoning is concerned. The
^ijnanavadins too adopt this point for the purpose of
162
their own logical argument. In this sense,all these
schools accept a view common to the Buddhistic philosop hy
in general. However, the differences between the
Vaibhasika - Sautrantika view point on the one hand
and that of the ijnana-vada on the other, is found to
be very much explicit when these schools seem to draw
different metaphysical conclusions from this coupon
f ..
logical point. The Vaibhasikas and the Sautrantikas
interprete the logical referent of the judgement not
merely as bare particular but also as somewhat nou-
-objective?- (arthaO) and hence external to subjective
V: i
sphere. This way of elucidating, though is not /de&ianded,
by the nature of their own logical analysis, yet i^
accepted because of a specific realistic mbia>s^;-'
The Vi jnana-vadins, on the other hand, take thes^e
bare unique particulars, which initially are the; outcome^
of a logical analysis of the nature of judgements, as
something subjective and as such term them as vi.ihanas
(ideas) It is the idea and not the element (dhdrma)
which is accepted as real. Whilerstatingetherpolition
163
of the Vijnanavada, Vasuband.hu accepts the mere awareness
(viinaotlmatra) as the only sat and thereby repudiates all
forms of externality and objectivity.
These different schools in Buddhism seem to
have dram divergent conclusions from the common logical
account of the bare particular and thereby become distin
guished from each other. The Vaibhasikas assert that the
given referent of the judgement is directly known or
perceived from without. As such they are identified as
direct realists who assert the direct acquaintance of th
object of perception. But while for a direct realist the
object is as it is perceived, for the Vaibhasika the
object, though is acquainted in all knowledge, yet it is
distorted because of its involvement with the conceptual
characters of the judgement, i_.ji., generality (Jati).
quality (guna). action (karma), name (narna) and substanc^
(dravya) The Sautrantikas, though agree with the
Vaibhasikas about the reality of the external given,
yet, instead of granting the direct acquaintance of thesb,
admit an indirect knowledge. Of course, for both
164
' \
the schools the final conclusion rearning the same, viz.,,
though the real is such that it cannot be comprehended by
means of any linguistic Judgement, yet it cannot be denic
being the external referent of all Judgements.
The Vijnanavadins, so far as logical plane
is concerned, have no difference of opinion with that of
the other two schools. If the unique particulars are the
referent of all Judgements, then those can never, the
Vijnanavddins think, be something external to knowledge.
The judgement must refer to the Idea Cvl;iMna) and not
the external object (arthq) as its referent. Here it may
be marked that for this school the given real is not only
pudgala-sunya but also dharma-sunyfi. Denial bf the external
objectivity (Bahya-artha-sunvata) is the main contention
of the Vijnana-vadins. The given real is precisely of the)
nature of vi .inarm. Though taken as mere idea it is, as
usual to Buddhism, infinitely manifold^ and constantly
3
changing. To all the Buddhistic schools, "general featur^
like cow-ness have no objective reallty-and are entirely due t<
'ttMtta******'*
li anantam? quoted by Steherbatsky, op.clt.T p*5l3.
2. pratjksanaviar5ru. ibid,
UTT ii ^rn .nm n... nir* . .a.utx r- 9 ' "
165
'-th erfiature of thought.1. 2The reality of the vi.ihanas: cannot
be ordinarily grasped because the nature of the ordinarj
knowledge is such that it must know its idea in a manner
much different from what the idea actually is. The
particular vi.lnana is never know as it is, rather
always it is distorted by the application of the generi^
charactersties:so natural to the very being of the
ordinary judgement. The thought construction (kalnana)
is responsible for distorting the real vi.lhana and by
the application of the general features like Jati, etc.
it creates a misleading suggestion that as if the
yjjnanas are external bbiect.q(artha). Judgement by its
vary nature aims at static objects endowed with generic
features. Hence any judgement being incapable of
presenting:;, the unique idea.- is fundamentally erroneous..
The yogacara Buddhist clearly holds that with the only
exception of Buddhas' knowledge all other knowledge is
2
erroneous. Buddhas knowledge is declared to be free
1. M.Hiriyanna; Qp.cit.* p.,221.
2, Sarvam alambane bhrantam muktva Tathagata-.lnanam.
itl yoeaeara-matena. Nyaya-bindutika-tipnaflff
ted.by Stcherbatsky in Bibliotheca Buddhiea), p.19,
166
from error because it transcends the dichotomy of subject
and object while all other knowledges (in the sense of
ordinary judgement) are false due to the mental construction
1
of the said dichotomy. In other words, it is the mere
awareness (vi.lnaptlmatra). which is free from subject-
object polarisation, is regarded as the ultimate point of
reference in the philosophy of Vijnanavada*
For Vijhanavada, error consists in the wro
objectification of what is essentially a state of
2
consciousness. . There is really no existence of external
object. The mere apparent ascription of external objective ty
over the Internal yi.inana is sufficient to create error.
"The real in this system is the constructive activity of
consciousness which alone invests things with significance*
Independence of the subjective act of knowing is here the
very essence of the unreal 5 the 'this* (Idam) in the context
3
of the illusion, this is a snake', is false. It is the
subjective idea of snake which Is mistakenly thought.to
be presented outside.
l.Steherbatsky, op.cit., p.537,
2. An idea is mistaken for an external object (idam) *
yadantar .inevarupafa tu bahir&vad avahhasate. T.R.V.Mur
The"Central Philosophy of Buddhism. London, 1955, p.21^,
3. Ibids pp. 215-216. _____ ________
167
Many expose the Vijrfana-vadin' s view,
on error by analysing the erroneous judgement 'This is
silver' in a. peculiar., r manner.. According to this analyse
'this' is interpreted as predicate and'silver' as the
subject of the judgement at issue (unlike the realistic
interpretations as advanced by the TTaiyayikas and the
Mimamsakas^. While both the Sautrantikas and the
Vaibhasikas have to maintain the reality of the artha
and the unreality of the vijnana, the Vijhana-vadins, on !
the other hand, hold just the reverse view. They argue
for the reality of the vi.ihana and the unreality of the j
artha. 'Silver' in the judgement 'This is silver' stands
for the mental idea. It is not out there. It is, though
really a mere idea, is wrongly taken to be a non-idea.
When idea is taken to be a non-idea, error originates.
All this may not sound very much '
unpalatable even to the opponents of the Vijnanavadins,
1. Cf. Prof.S.Sens A note on the Yogacara-Sautrantika
theory of adhyasa, included in Prof.Hiriyanna1s
Commemoration Volume, Mysore, 1952, pp.175-178.
since they also insist that in error one thing is mistaken
for something else. Error, as the Naiyayikas say, is
due to taking something as something else. The only
difference lies on the matter of ontological preference
The Vijnanavada not only suggests that in error it is
the subjective idea which is wrongly thought to be
objective, but also the so called objective reality is
not real at all. To put it in other words, when the
erroneous judgement is replaced by a correcting judge
ment 'This is not silver', the negation in the correctin
judgement actually negates the 'this' and not the 'silv^jc*
It is now evident that this analysis of the erroneous
judgement is definitely unusual. Grammatically one takes
'this* to be the subject and 'silver' to be the predicap
And in the correcting judgement 'This is not silver',
not merely negates * silver' and not 'this!.
Now supposing one agrees with the
analysis of error as said to have been advanced by the
Vijhana-vadins in the aforesaid lines, a question is
still raised about the logical distinction between a
169
false judgement and a true judgement. If in ease of a
false judgement it is argued that the very idea of
externality is the root of error and 'silver* which is
merely a mental idea is mistakenly thought to be present
outside as an object* then at least by contrast from a
logical point of view it may mean that in case of a true
j
judgement, where the object is actually a piece of silve
there is actually an external referent to correspond to
the internal idea of silver* That means, in case of
valid perceptual judgement there is complete harmony
between the internal idea and the external object,
whereas in case of judgements of erroneous perception
there is lack of this harmony* All this suggests that
as if according to the ijnana*vadins the idea of
externality is denied in case of a false judgement alone
But this, by no means, seems to be a
faithful rendering of the ^ijnana-vadins* view op. error,
These philosophers do not at all maintain that objects
are nonexistent during one cognition and are existent
during another. They rather strongly hold that there
170
are only ideas and thus they are In favour of totally
dispensing with objects. Objects are not denied in case
of false judgements alone but also in case of ordinarily
called true judgements. If they would be talking about
f
the lack of externality only in cases of false judgements:
then their theory would not be different from that of tb
realists who too maintain that in error there is no harmc
between idea and the corresponding object. It is to be
clearly marked that not only the this* is denied in case
of e false judgement This is silver but also the this
Is rejected in case of a true judgement This is silver*i
In no case objectivity can ever be admissible, since the
idea is alone taken in this philosophy to be real. It
should not mean that ideas like silveriness, etc, are firmly
accepted by the Vijnanavadin. All such ideas also are
infected with conceptualisation. The vijnlna which is freje
from any sense of conceptualisation is ultimately accepto
To put it in other words, by this vl$
of the Yijnana~V8.di.ns both ordinarily called true as well
as false judgements are declared to be erroneous since in
171
hoth cases there remains a false sense of objectivity.
Since, as said earlier, no judgement either perceptual or
Inferential is possible without the implicit acceptance
of the dichotomy of subject and object, it is maintained
in the same logical tone that judgement as such is errone us-
a position quite consistent with the general Buddhistic
i
doctrinej that is* all judgements are intrinsically false
That means, the Yijhana-vadins rendering of
Atmakhyati. so far as logical nature of the argument is i
concerned, does not edsdntially become different from 'either,
the Valbhasika or the Sautrantika versions of error* To atll
these schools, all judgements are really false though
ordinarily judgements are distinguished as either true
or false* To put it in a different language, here these
Buddhist philosophers, while dealing with the problem of
error, pose themselves precisely as the critic of all
judgements* Error is declared to be due to conceptualisa
tion. Since concepts are unavoidable in an^f form
of language, language as such is rejected for
172
knowing the real. The analysis of error gives rise to
a negative attitude towards language. Thus the discussiojr.
of error though is pursued in terras of perceptual
instances like illusion, hallucination, etc., still is
not really confined to perception at all. It is rather
primarily occupied with the concept of error as such.
The empirical distinction between a true and a false
judgement is not at all to be explained by means of the
\
theory of Atmakhyatl. There is, in fact, a separate
explanation offered by them for accounting the empirical
distinction between truth and falsity.
'Now before discussing these Buddhists
explanation about the distinction between an ordinarily
called true and a false judgement one is faced with the
problem as to how at all the vi ;]nana appears, as if it
i-s 'an external object if really there is no external
object. The Buddhist philosophers, here, have a reply
saying that the so called knowledge of externality is
1
due to beginingless nescience. This seems to be a
^Aeaa******* * *
1. Appaya Diksita: Parimala. Nirnaya Sagar Edn., p.26.
173
general explanation for all errors. It is this nescience
which is responsible for the creation of concepts. The
origination of concepts gives rise to the dichotomy of
subject and object within the manifold series of ideas.
As the result of this initial confusion made due to
conceptualisation, the vl.inana which is fleeting and j
dynamic appears as if it is static (sthira) and objective
(artha) And once this conceptual look at idea is with-
drawn and judgemental x*ay of knowing by means of .iati i
etc.. is removed the vi.inana is revealed as it really j
is and perfect enlightenment or Bodhisatva is attained.
It is, from this ultimate point of view,:
argued that all judgemental way of knowing is fundamentally
defective. Both the judgements This is silver* and
This is not silver; this is shell* are equally
erroneous because of having a false sense of objectivity
and externality. Only in case of the former, the
false sense of objectivity regarding silver is
immediately admitted after the said judgement is replace:.
174
by the latter judgement. In case of the latter judgement
though the false sense of objectivity regarding 'silver
is already granted, the lack of objectivity with regard
to 'shell', here, is not realised. Because this latter
judgement is practically efficacious. It is this
practical test which decides the fate of ordinary judge
ments either as true or as false. Though all judgements
are responsible for misleading objectivity and external}.
over the vfcjnang,,in some cases of the judgements this
mispredication is at once known while in others it is
not easily known due to long predisposition Cvasana).
"The Vijnanai-vadins try to justify the distinction by
asserting that the objects of cognitions producing
practical efficiency (arthakriva) are samvrti satya
(empirically real) while the objects of illusion are
mithva (absolutely unreal), though both are equally
1
non-existent as external to cognitions.
The explanation of truth in terms of
arthakriya is found to be acceptable by the'. .Yaibhlsikajtjfce
1. G.B.Bhatt: Qp.cit.. p.103.
175
SaTrtran.tikac.'an'd'ithe'VY'oga'G'ara schools of Buddhism. This
defence may not he very much supported by science. It
is true as Samkarites sometimes put that even a false
1
judgement is quite practically efficacious. In modern
times it is already noticed about the danger of identi
fying truth with workability in the context of
pragmatism.
Now whether there is one scientifically
cogent explanation about error as distinguished from
truth seems to be immaterial for these philosophers.
Though they start discussing error by citing common
empirical instances of illusion, hallucination, etc.,
yet their main point, as it has been indicated before,
is to account for error as such, By asserting all
linguistic judgements to be erroneous the Buddhist
philosopher is not stating anything regarding matter-
of-fact. The world of concrete reality is not all at
once changed into phantasmagoria once the invalidity
of all knowledge is conceded. It is absolutely
immaterial from the point of view of fact whether one
1. VidesMadhusudana Saraswatl: Advaita Siddhi.Nirnava
------ Bagar^Bdn., p.3aa------ - --- --
176
calls the illusory silver to be objective or subjective.
The contention that *A11 judgements are erroneous" is not
_ ' 1
descriptive but prescriptive. The Atmakhyati, while
insisting for the Khyati of the vijnanas. merely advocate!^
/
for a revision of concentual framework. The changed
/ ,
conceptual framework is not to be verified either as true
or as false. Nothing is lost as a matter of fact whethei
one regards arthas to be the referent or the vijnanas to
be the referent of the judgement.
One might say that Atmakhyati is a
recommendation for alternative language. Some have indeed
thought that the prescription of vijnanas as against
artha is only to adopt a phenomenalist position of
2
advocating sense-datum language. Now whether the term
8 vijhana* can be taken to be the same as the term
1 sense-datum8 is yet a point to decide. Neither the
1. The theory of Atmakhvati is also sometimes named as
Vijnanakhvatl.
2. S.K.Mukharjee: The Problem of Error in Indian
Philosophy, Bharatl. Utkal University Journal -
Humanities, Vol. Ill, No.5, 1969.
177
language of yi.lnana nor that of sense-datum has been
yet available for a neat comparison and contrast. There
is yet much doubt about the possibility of an alternatire
1
language like that of sensedatum* Unless there is
found to be a complete and overall move for an alterna
tive. language, mere change and replacement of one or
two concepts by means of some other do not seem to be
sufficient to conclude that there is a clear move for
adopting an alternative language like that of sense-
datum. ;,
So one may ^likewise be very much
sceptical about the feasibility of this language of
vijnanas. But one thing is certain that the very attemp
i
of accounting the conceptual framework by means of
vi.inana as against 'art ha;. is surely not finding
something new or eliminating something old so far as
the facts of experience are concerned. In this sense
these theories are neither supporting nor conflicting
1. Isaiah Berlin : Empirical Propositions and
Hypothetical statements,. Mind, 1950.
178
with any facts of experience. To say that all Judgement<s
are erroneous or that the reality of vlinanas is not
revealed due to the begin^ingless nescience is surely
not to report about the world. These utterances are
primarily meant for transcending the plane of Judgements
Because that plane is considered to be the source of
all falsity.lt is the Judgemental plane which keeps
somebody away from knowing-the ideas:as ideas. Top,put
it in other form, in this theory there is a clear
indication for a revolt against the language as a tool
for knowing the real. Linguistic rendering of the real
by means of Judgement is, by no means, faithful to the
real '
Very often a charge is brought by the
rival classical as well as the modern philosophers
I - '
against the Vijnana-vadins that their account of error
179
directly conflicts with experience. These critics
argue that it is a fact that the silver in the erroneou
perception is perceived as out there. Even if one agree
the silver to be subjective?yet the very this* (idam)?
which is confused as silver cannot be denied. In other
words, the rejection of this is contrary to all
experience. One only negates silverhood wrongly applied
over * this but not * this* as such.
Here again it can be said that the
Vijnana-vddin*s account of error does not deny the
actuality of this. It does not at all suggest that
in the nacre-silver illusion inhere nacre is misperceive
as silver nacre is to be treated as an idea and not as
a concrete physical object. If the nacre is mistaken
as silver then after the mistake is revealed the nacre
has got to he accepted as a concrete physical object
1* "Sfo body perceives cognition itself as a pillar, as
a wall, and so forth. But everybody perceives them
as objects of cognition' - Samkara; VSS.<, ^I.'IP'^S,:
Vacaspati: anubhava-virodhat - BM,| Nyaya-Parisudd!hi
of Vedanta Desika, p.45
see also S.K.Maitra: db.cit., p,225 and A.Bhattacaryaj
-gp.eljh., p.251. -----
180
i8i
opponent virtually explains away the very problem of
error. The very fact of error means that -which is suppose
to be out there* is not actually there* The very fact of
illusion* etc* suggests that experience is not always
experience of something. The Yijnanavadin is here pointir.
out that normally no one would admit the .silver to be out
there while nacre is confused as .silver. He tries to
emphasize the subjective import so far as the connotation
of the term experience1 is considered. Experience
essentially connotes experiencing by some person. It does;
not warrant logically whatever ik experienced must be
out there. From-the statement! experience* it does not
logically follow that what I experience is there.
How if in the case of erroneous
apprehensions, experiences do hot warrant objectivity
then one can go little ahead and conclude that all
apprehensions including erroneous-as well as non-erroneou
ones, do1 not guarantee objectivity. It has been
pointed out before that according to these . ,
182
Buddhist philospphers in both the erroneous as well as
non-erroneous judgements the referent of the judgements
'l.
is infected with the sense of objectivity. It is maintair|<bd
that no experience is objectively significant. If in illtj^ory
perception there, is the false awareness of objectivity ti^n
in the so called valid perception too, it is, in the same
manner, maintained that there is a false sense of objectivity.
Atmakhyati-vada, like other theories, only analyses the
concept of error. Its interest is not to give a psycho- j
logical explanation regarding illusion, dreams and
hallucinations* The Vijnana-vadins accept the vi.inanas
alone to be the referent of all, judgements, But judgements*,
by their very nature, are infected with conceptualisation
and as such cannot reveal the nature of the vilhanas. HerIVe
all judgements are declared to be false. ludgements, according
to the ijnana-\7adins, claim a pseudo-sense of objectivity,
(alambaria).
Hence from all these it is evident that
the Yijhana-vadins, by advocating all judgements to be
erroneous, do not put forth an empirical proposition
183
whose validity can be measured scientifically. The claim
that ideas alone are real is a typically metaphysical
utterance* It is therefore' irrelevant to say that such
metaphysical utterance directly conflicts with experience
Hence the charge against the Vi jnana-vadins that they
greatly conflict with experience does not mean much.
One of the popular criticisms levelled
against the Vijriana-vadins* account of error is that its
denial of the external basis of error is most absurd. Thi
criticism is, in a way, a specjte of the previous criticism
that/this account of error conflicts with experience. The
. / : ' ' i
Atmakhyati-vadins suggest that after the error is rectifi
only'the external objectivity of silver is withdrawn. It
; . . ;
is said, only thisness! Cidanta) is denied but not silver.
/r'k". '
Her^;/the critics argue that in such a case the sublating
judgement would be of the form of *1 am silver* instead of
' all ' i '
the form This is not silver*. In this criticism it is
. 4 , . ;>
implied that the judgement This is not silver not only
r. r.
fees the silver* but also affirms the 'this* - the
1. /'jburovartitvena rajatasya badheahara ra.iatam iti syat%
dc^intabo^fdrika of H.mhlS,sna, Nimaya Sagar Edn., p. 0
See also Vaeaspati; p.26l and Jayanta Bhatta: HM.,
.
' s_8_'
184
185
condemning the ordinary mode of expression. The theory
appeals for a revision of the established conceptual set
up without making any violence to the nature of fact.
This appeal for a revision is, no doubt, based on a
negative attitude towards language as a trtiole.
The point that I am trying to make here
is that mere conflict with ordinary mode of expression is
not by itself a sufficient charge to undermine the position
of the Vijnana-vadins. One can, of course, challange this
theory of Atmakhvati by showing certain internal inconsi
stencies instead of attacking with a sword which does
not touch it.
To sum up the whole discussion, the
theory of Atmakhvati. as advocated by all the three schools
of Buddhism, is clearly not an empirical theory whose
conclusion can be tested by means of scientific test. The
theory is not meant to give a psychological account about;
the process of erroneous perception. Its problem is not
to find out how actually illusions, etc., occur. Its aim
is rather to face the problem of error by analysing the
186
nature of judgement from a logical point of view. While
the theory analyses the nature of judgement it has clearlj
indicated its preference for the logically significant
point that error arises due to misjudging or mispredicaticn
So far as judgement is concerned, mistake, according to
this theory also, is said to be due to predicative part
and not due to referent. Mere awareness (vijnaptimatra)
as the referent of all judgements is never denied by the
theory. Only the theory insists that judgement, because
of its very nature, never grasps the referent as it is,
but takes it as different from what it is. To take the
dynamic, fleeting vi.inana, as static conceptualised artha
is the source of all error. That error is due to generali
and conceptualisation is clearly admitted by all the thre4
versions of Atmakhyativada. It can be noticed that thus
far the theory is only interested for logically determining
the concept of error. That error is to take something as
what it is not is only to explicate the defining mark of
error. Here the problem is not to account for perceptual
errors. It is only a logical analysis of the nature of
187
judgement. The nature of judgement is such that it can new
be true of the real. It necessarily distorts the real by
attributing certain external run a on it.
. The Vaibhasikas and the Sautrantikas, apar;
from the minor doctrinal differences, agree that the logical
referent of any judgement (svalaksana) is necessarily misi-
described in all instances of judging as judging necessarily
implies misjudging and the general nature of the concept
falls short of the particular. It is, only from the logicjjl
a
point of view and never.from the factual point of view,
asserted that all judgements are intrinsically erroneous.
The argument, in this connection, is only to stress the
significant logical point and is never engaged in a
psychological analysis. The Vijninavadins, too, are not
engaged in accounting illusions, etc., but are only confin
to analyse the nature of the judgement. Judgement being
/ ;
/Conceptualised necessarily' distorts the non-conceptualise|c
ijdte experience. However, the speciality in these
philosophers is that unlike the Vaibhasikas and the
/, ; . . 1
4autrantikas, they emphasize the significant epistemological
188
point that experiencing does not ^guarantee. the nature
of the content of experience* In this way, the objectiviij;
and externality are repudiated and mere experiencing is
only asserted* As such, this analysis has given rise to
a sort of phenomenalistic epistemology. Now, to whatever
form of epistemology the V1 ;j nana va din a' view may lead to,
one thing, however, remains certain that these Buddhist
philosophers are not primarily engaged in the psycho
logical issues. Their specific;field is logic and
epistemology.
Both for the Vaibhasikas as well as the!
Sautrantikas, the judgement, by its very nature,' ever
' i' \ ,
/V, '
becomes confined to its own categoites and concept!s> It
i i /, \.
' !'}' ^
can never transcend itself (Atmakhyati) and because of
'i
I, >
this, it can never appropriately describe the baije\
referent (svalaksana). While frying to describe
/!
' '
' ' ':lpi l \.
svalaksana. the judgement, because of its inherent\nature
puts some foreign forms (rupa) .which do not belohg\ to the
i \^
referent. Hence it is.maintained that falsity of/all
judgements is only due to the .predicative (prakarata)\asp set
18 9
The Vijnanavadins, too, subscribe to the view
that the judgements by its very nature, ever becomes
confined to its own categories and concepts. It can neve
transcend its own realm. Theo only difference that can b
marked between the views of the Vaibhasika and the
Sautrantika on the one hand and the view of the Vijftana-
vadin on the other hand is that while the former schools
maintain the falsity of all judgements to be due to the
predicative aspect alone the latter school maintains the
falsity of all judgements to be both due to the predicative
as well as the subjective (idanta) aspects. The sense of
externality which is suggested by the admittance of * thi
as real is severely repudiated by the Vijnanavadins. It
is, only from this point of view, concluded that neither
something objective nor something subjective but only
the bare experience that can be asserted finally. The
yjjhana, as is already seen, transcends the dichotomy o:
both objectivity as well as subjectivity.
(2) ASATKHYATI
So far, the account of error In the
three schools of Buddhism are discussed. Besides this
account of error which is termed as Atmakhyati there
is another view named as Asatkhyati or Sunyakhyati
which is often ascribed to the Madhyamikas. Wo origins
Madhyamika treatises like Mula-madhyamika-karika or
Vigraha Vvavartatfu clearly refer this term with
explanation. Its reference is found in the writings
of the rival schools of Indian philosophies including
both the Hindu as well as the Jaina works.
Asatkhyativada, as exposed by these
works, means that in erroneous perception there is
merely the perception of something which is unreal
(asat!. In the shell-silver illusion, the silver that
is perceived is neither real as something external
nor even real as something internal. Therefore it is
absolutely unreal. If the silver would have been
externally real then there would not have been any
scope for erroneous perception If the silver would
191
have been merely an internal idea then also there woul:
have been no explanation with regard to its external
manifestation. It is, as such, asat or sfinya. To put
it in other words?it is the asat which is the object
of perception in this context. Thus the erroneous
perception is declared to be *non-being* s apprehension
One becomes aware of the non-being of silver only when
the erroneous perception is sublated by the valid
perception.
From this account of the theory of
Asatkhyati it becomes clear that the silver which is
perceived in the shell-silver illusion is really non
existent. It is neither the silver which was perceived
in a different place previously nor is it a momentary
silver exclusively limited to the moment of illusion.
It is totally nonexistent or asat. It is asat which
is falsely perceived as jsat, i.e.. silver. A totally
non-existent is apprehended as existent* The silver
in the shell-silver illusion being absolutely unreal
o***e**ti*
1. S.Kuppuswamy Sastris bp.cit.. p.123.
192
no where exists. It neither exists in the present
situation nor even anywhere else. Error arises in taking
something totally nonexistent as existent.
If the objective of Asatkhyativada is
only to expose the unreality of silver as against its
apparent reality then this theory is hardly disputable
even by its rivals Because all are to agree that In
error that which appears to be real is actually not real
The silver that appears to be real in the shell-silver
illusion is not real* This is what illusion ordinarily
stands for. But the theory of Asatkhvati. it is said,
is not simply to advocate the unreality of the silver*
alone. It is also maintained that according to this
theory, whatever is perceived as the silver1 is also
mere non-being. That means the shell* which is ordinar: iy
accepted to be real as against the silver is also
rejected by the present theory to be not really existin
Asatkhvati stands for complete void or sunva. And in
that sense, both the ordinarily accepted erroneous
perception as well as the valid?:- perception are declare
to be erroneous. Only the erroneous character of the
shell is not empirically known because of its practical',
utility. To put it in other words, while the silver*
is taken as absolutely unreal, it is also implied by
this theory that nothing real as the basis of this
unreal silver* is even acceptable* Along with the
rejection of error its locus (adhistana) is also rejected
And it is this rejection of locus which is argued to bdqtihe
distinguishing feature of the theory of Asatkhyati,
But here the Vedantins, the Naiyayikas
and many others argue that how can a totally nonexistent]
1
something at all be apprehended, An absolute naught
cannot even be conceived (e.g.$ son of a barren woman)
what to speak of its being perceived, it is a matter of
experience that shell is misperceived as silver, This
shows that something is being apprehended as something
else. So the silver characterisation of the present
o^ob-jects^''1 may be found to be wrong after later
1* Vide; "Hirupakhyanasyaparoksyabhasagocaratvanupapatt^1
Ramakrsna."'dV,cit,T 0,50 and 177-178.
194
verification but that something as the locus of silver
characterisation is positively present even at the time
of erroi*, there can be least doubt about it. Hence it
is not the absolute nothing (sunya) which is perceived
as something existent CSat) but something is apprehended
as some other thing* Shell in the form of this* remains
however, as the basis of silver-apprehension. So some
thing existent appears as silver and not that non-existe
appears as existent. Even if one agrees the point that
the silver that is perceived in illusion is unreal yet
the referent on which silver is perceived cannot be
rejected as void or sunya. The defect lies with Asat-
khyati-vada that it not only negates silver but also
the this* or the very basis of error along with error.
It is pointed out by way. of defending
the theory of Asatkhyati that when the eyes are pressed
the woody mass of substances (kesondrakas) that appear
before the eyes are without any locus. It Is possible
that a person while dreaming may have also another drean
within that range of first dream. The second dream
195
obviously does not have any real basis as that occurs
only within another dream. So also it is argued that
erroneous perception points at some unreal substance
which has no real locus. It is argued that in error
the suhya is mistaken as shell and again this unreal
shell is further taken to be silver.
But again such defence of this theory
of error, it is maintained, is without any foundation.
Because even the wocEly substances appear in a real locus
and also the original dream is possible only when there
is real consciousness. No dream can occur unless there
is the real basis of consciousness. It is this reality
of locus which is always maintained by the Advaitins
in a very forceful manner. The Post-Samkarltes, while,
elaborate the theory of Anirvacanivakhvati emphasize
a positive character of error only to contrast their
account of error from that of the Sunya-vadins
Now,leaving the Advaitins' account of
error for the present, it may be marked that even in
the classical form the theory of Asatkhyatl does not
196
stand for explaining the erroneous perception alone.
It is not a theory by means of which the ordinary
distinction between an illusory perception and a
veridical perception can be well determined. The theory
is distinctly not psychological when it recommends all
cognitions (whether perceptual or non-perceptual) to
be the cognitions of sheer non-being. The distinction
between a true and a false cognition is itself challenged
here from a logical point of view. By maintaining all
cognitions to be the cognitions of asat, the theory
logically seems to be not about illusion but about the
concept of error as such, neither the subjective knox'fei
(jnata) nor the objective known (.ineya) are acceptable
according to this theory. It is the sunya or complete
void which is the philosophical position of the
Madhyamikas.
But against such a nihilistic rendering
of Madhyaraika philosophy it is pointed out by some
modern authorities that 'Sunya-vadins like
itfagarjuna cannot be the propounders of absolute sunya.
For sunya. transcends only the four categories of
197
thought (Catus-koti-vinirmukta). Reality is neither
existent, nor non-existent, nor both existent and non
existent nor different from existent and non-existent*
This shows that Madhyamika sunva is not mere non-being
or asat and hence the Asatkhyativada as exposed by th^
classical Hindu as well as the Jaina philosophers can
never be said as the theory actually propounded by the
_ I
|
Madhyamikas. The Sunya-vada does not mean 'void1 as
1
No-reality' doctrine but merely 'No-view' about Real illy
Though both silver as well as shell
are, as argued above, said to be not ultimately real
yet from the rejection of these empirical entities the
transcendental or reality,;: :i is1 "notion r e j ected" ~ 3 r. Cj rl
as mere void. It is said as neither sat nor asat. etc
because it transcends all empirical thought construct! cns.
In this manner, the Madhyamikas are rather presented
as critics of all empirical phenomena but not as sheer
nihilists. Sunva is only significantly used in the
1. T.R.V.Murti: gto.cit.. p.313.
Vide: also S.Radhakrishnan, Indian Philosophy. Vol.I
pp. 662-666.________________________________________
19S
199
Of course, in this connection, it is to
be admitted that the Asatkhyativada as implying absolute
void is not found to be discussed and elaborated by any
Madhyamika Buddhist but by some non-Buddhist philosopher
There is, therefore, much scope for doubting about its
authenticity* Since no historical data with regard to
its Buddhistic origin are yet available there remains
much room for Imaginary speculation on this issue.
But can not the theory of Asatkhvati be
interpreted in a slightly different manner so that it
would coherently fit into the general philosophical-as
well as the logical position of the Madhyamikas? The
trouble of incoherency lies only when Asatkhvati is
meant as the apprehension of something absolutely naugh
(asat), And from this explanation of illusory phenomenon
the generalisation is framed that reality is essentially
asat (absolute non-being),. In this version the theory is
hardly intelligible. Because, as it has been pointed ou
earlier, how can the absolute void be at all apprehended
Why not Asatkhvati be meant as falsity (asat) of
200
judgement (khyati)? Grammatically there is no difficulty
in adhering to this formulation. In fact this formulatio
of the theory fits better to the philosophical position
of the Madhyamikas. It also reveals the logical structur
of the argument of the theory in a more intelligible
form. Me former formulation, l.e.. non-beings1 appre
hension seems to be giving rise to unwarranted absurdity
But in the present fprinulation the falsity being the
adjective of khyati would imply the judgement in questi:;
to be false. Let me elaborate.
Though the term khyati in a wider
context stands for knowledge in general in the philosophy
consideration of truth and falsity it only refers to the
1
judgemental aspect of it. It is the judgement in the
logical sense which is usually accepted to be either
true or false in the Indian philosophical perspective.
This significant point has been very clearly and force
fully maintained by the Hyaya logicians when they define
true knowledge as that judgement which describes the
referent in the appropriate manner and falsity as that
1. VirlPt -------------------- ------ -I
201
judgement which misdescribes the referent. This Nyaya
logical model, in a slightly different form, is also,
as it has been already shown* accepted by the Bhatta
Mimamsakas. The Visistadvaitins, though agreeable to
the philosophic discussion of knowledge in terms of
judgement yet finally redefine the referent of the judg^
ment (l.e.,real in their terminology) in such a manner
so that all judgements are shorn to be true in the
sense of correctly describing the real.
The Buddhist philosophers, in general,
take an opposite move from that of the Visistadvaitins*
According to them, all judgements are necessarily false
A true judgement is logically inconceivable. If the
model offered by the Wyaya logicians be taken to its
logical climax then the Buddhist philosophers seem to
argue that not only the ordinarily called false judge
ments but also the so called true judgements can also
be shown as false. If in ease of ordinarily called
false judgement, falsity is due to misdescribing, then
in the so called true judgement too, since describing
202
is equally involved, the logical possibility of its bein i:
false cannot be ruled out. It is from this logical
possibility of all descriptive judgements being false,
the Buddhists in general draw the persuasive negative
conclusion that all judgements are false. The Vaibhasikajs
the Sautrantikas and the Vijnanavadins, initially though!
are in complete agreement, so far as this point is
concerned, yet subsequently because of their distinctive
philosophical views, interprets the bare logical referenjt
of the judgement in such terminologies like dharma or
vijnanas. But the Madhyamikas most probably want to restrict
the whole discussion to the logical level alone and do
not want to commit to any form of positive ontology. That
is why they neither want to term the referent as object
(artha) nor as experience (vi.ihapti).
So far as error is concerned, the
Madhyamikas accept the general logical conclusion that
it is only due to mispredication. A judgement like
This is silver is false when it predicates the silver
characteristic over the referent 0 which does not
203
fit into it* But if the silver-predication is found
to.be wrong then the shell-predication is equally
vulnerable* Because it also involves description. To
describe the referent as shell also carries the logical.
possibility being' *erroneoua.1 -in-ide-sbribing ' the'ref er ont
shell, no doubt, one takes the help of concepts and
categories* The concepts.are applied by means of
classifying the referenthunder one universal or set
of. universals* There is, of course, every possibility
of misclassification*
To put it in other words, a critical
analysis of the logical nature of judgement reveals
that each judgement turns out to be corrigible in
character. It is only from this point of view and not
necessarily from the point of view of any pre-conceivejc.
ontology} the Madhyamikas are led to argue that all
judgements are false. It is this falsificatory mark ol
all judgements that accounts for an intelligible
rendering of the theory of Asatkhyati. While in the
classical version of Asatkhyativada it is said that
204
the silver* in the judgement 'This is silver, is absolutely
unreal, it should not mean that the silver as an object
is regarded to be absolutely unreal; it is only the silver
predication being applied in the present context is regarded
as false. The discussion of error which is made intelligible
in the formal plane is misleadingly thought to have some
material significance.
The Madhyamikas, quite consistent.to the genital
Buddhistic position, adopt the criticisms of concepts. While
carrying this discussion to the logical end they conclude
that the critique of concepts clearly reveals that the
referent of any judgement is beyond all conceptual categories,
and may thus be designated as catus-koti-vinirmukta. The
ijnanavadins view that bare experience free from subject
object polarization can alone be finally asserted, is not
approved by the Madhyamikas. Because the Madhyamikas point
out that even by describing the referent as bare experiences,
li
there is, in principle, the chance of falsification. From
a logical point of view it can only be consistently
asserted that all descriptions carry the sense of falsifi
cation and,as such, no judgement can be said as true. The
referent of any judgement can neither be described as artba
nor as vi.inana. It transcends all descriptions and that is
why it is said to be intrinsically empty of all contents
and is regarded to be void.