Hoff (2000), 'The Modern Theory of Underdevelopment Traps'
Hoff (2000), 'The Modern Theory of Underdevelopment Traps'
28725
Beyond Rosenstein-Rodan:
Karla Hoff
April 10, 2000
Abstract. The theme of this article is the importance and the many causes of lowlevel equilibrium traps. Rosenstein-Rodan pointed out that spillovers may cause the
return to an activity to increase with the number of others who undertake that activity. If
spillovers are strong enough, both low- and high-level equilibria are possible, with no
tendency of market forces to lead from the worse to the better state of affairs. This article
shows how modern economic theory broadened our view of the sources of spillovers that
could lead to "traps" with low innovation and inefficient institutions. Evidence from
China is consistent with local underdevelopment traps. The article argues for an
ecological perspective on development, where the influences from others in ones
environment are a critical determinant of outcomes. This perspective provides the basis
for the distinction between "deep" interventions, which change underlying forces, and
"shallow" interventions, which do not.
Karla Hoff is a research economist at the World Bank. This article draws on Hoff and Stiglitz
(forthcoming). The author would like to thank Irma Adelman for helpful comments, and Abhijit
Banerjee, Arnold Harberger, Gustav Ranis, Debraj Ray, and Joseph Stiglitz for discussions of the
issues raised in this article.
OUTLINE
1. The place of coordination failures in modern economic theory
Neoclassical theory and the Coase theorem
Institutional economics outside the 'straitjacket' of neoclassical economics
Path dependence
A radically broadened view of externalities and public goods
"Ecological economics"
2. Examples of underdevelopment traps
A low R&D trap
Self-sustaining institutions
Big Push theories of industrialization
3. An econometric test: Local poverty traps in rural China
4. Perspectives on policy
Coordinating good equilibria
Sequencing of policy reforms
A word of caution: Deep versus shallow interventions
5. Conclusion
Mathematical appendix
Table and Figures
Table 1.
Table 2
Figure 1.
Figure 2.
Figure 3.
Figure 4.
Figure 5.
the changes needed for development (Krugman, 1992, 1995, and the comment by Stiglitz,
1992).
In this article, the term neoclassical theory is used as a short-hand for models that postulate
maximizing behavior plus interactions through a complete set of perfectly competitive markets.
This narrow definition is for convenience only. There is no consensus on the scope of the term
neoclassical theory; it is sometimes (e.g., in Laffont 1989, p. 6) used broadly to include any
systematic exploration of the implications of rational behavior in economics. In that broad
sense, all the models discussed in this article, except for one evolutionary model, are examples of
neoclassical theory.
Sources include Azariadis and Drazen 1990 (low investment in human capital), Piketty 1997
(high interest rates), Murphy, Shleifer and Vishny 1993 (predation), Tirole 1996 and Bardhan
1997 (corruption), Glaeser et al. 1996 (crime), Zak and Knack 1998 (trust), Hoff and Sen 2000
(the structure of ownership),Acemoglu 1996 (training and innovation), Kranton 1996 and
Banerjee and Newman 1997 (informal exchange networks), Gale 1992 and Reding and Morales
1999 (standard securities and currency substitution), and Cooper 1999 (who provides many
applications, including business cycles and examples from experimental economics).
3
Besley and Coate (1998, pp. 151-152) provide a definition of political failure that is parallel to
that of market failure. One begins in each case by defining the set of technologically feasible
utility allocations. For the case of political failure, this reflects the available policy instruments,
e.g. taxes, transfers, and investments. Political institutions are then modeled. By analogy with
The goal of this article is to show how developments in economic theory in the
last 30 years broadened our understanding of the channels of spillovers, and made
possible a new understanding which we call the "ecological perspective" of pitfalls
and opportunities in the development process. We emphasize three developments in
modern theory: institutional economics, path dependence, and a radically broadened
view of externalities and public goods.
We were always told that such models served only as a benchmark. Neoclassical
economists recognized that their models did not take account of direct interdependencies
among individuals that were not mediated through markets (e.g., Pigou's polluting
market failures, a political failure arises when equilibrium policy choices result in an outcome
where it is technologically feasible (given available tax and transfer instruments, information,
factories). But by and large, they believed that these were relatively unimportant and that
interdependencies that were mediated through markets (pecuniary externalities) did not
have efficiency effects (for example, Mishan 1971, Cheung 1973).4
Another strand of the literature, however, recognized that markets were inherently
limited by problems of information and enforcement.5 There could never be the complete
etc.) to implement a Pareto-improving policy, but that policy will not be an equilibrium choice.
4
It is true that in an economy with a complete set of markets, it is efficient to ignore pecuniary
external effects. Such effects affect only distribution, and the distribution effects net out: gains
by agents whose prices increase are precisely offset by losses to agents who must pay higher
prices. There are no welfare losses from the allocation effects of price changes because
equilibrium prices always are equated to marginal social costs and benefits. However, in
economies with incomplete markets, pecuniary externalities generally do not net out. A general
framework is Greenwald and Stiglitz (1986). One application of that idea (Hoff 1998) shows that
in an economy where lenders cannot distinguish borrowers who differ in their probability of
default, pecuniary externalities from an improvement in technology can dissipate some, all, or
more than all of the gains from the technological change. The reason is that the marginal firm
may be the lowest quality; if so, he produces negative expected value (getting an implicit subsidy
from the lower risk , higher quality borrowers). As the technological change induces new entry
of marginal borrowers, the interest rate rises to reflect their lower average quality, which hurts all
borrowers and leaves banks, as before, just breaking even.
set of markets in goods, risks, and futures on which the efficiency results of neoclassical
theory rest. Non-market institutions arise in response to limits on markets, but there need
be no forces that ensure efficiency.
This can be put another way. Individual actions that are privately rational given
the environment that individuals are in, need not be socially rational. There might be
another set of individual actions that would create a different environment, within which
a different set of actions would be an equilibrium, and that environment might be a better
state of affairs for all concerned. There could be multiple equilibria in institutions and no
presumption that the best equilibrium was selected by market forces.
This can be illustrated in a simple way (following de Meza and Gould 1992).
Suppose that the state defines property rights, but that with respect to a certain resource
(e.g., forests), an individual must incur a fixed cost (e.g., to build a fence or hire a patrol
service) to enforce his property right. Without this private expenditure, all other
individuals will be able to freely use his private forest. The benefit to an owner from
enforcing his property right is that he can hire labor to exploit his forest and collect the
resource rents. Thus, in deciding whether to enforce his property rights, an owner
Whereas most authors are associated with one strand or the other, it is striking that North's work
helped to advance both. North's early work, which one might call "North I", was in the Coasean
tradition and pioneered its application to economic history. North's later work, which one might
call North II, disparages the prospects for understanding economic history as a more or less
inevitable movement towards more efficient institutions: Throughout most of history, the
experience of the agents and the ideologies of the actors do not combine to lead to efficient
outcomes (North 1990, p. 96; see also North 1994). I owe to North (from his comments at a
conference in May 1999) the metaphor of the straitjacket.
compares his potential rents to the enforcement cost. These rents will be larger, the lower
the reservation wage of workers. In equilibrium, the reservation wage of workers
depends on how many other owners are enforcing their property rights. As the fraction of
property owners who enforce their rights increases, the outside opportunities of workers
fall and, thus, so does the reservation wage. With lower wages, potential resource rents
rise. Two stable equilibria may therefore exist, one in which all owners enforce their
property rights, wages are low, and rents are high; and another one in which none do,
wages are high, and potential rents low, so that it does not pay any owner to enforce his
property right. See Figure 1.6
A very general insight of recent theoretical work is that while institutions may
have, as their intention, the improvement in economic outcomes, there is no assurance
that that will be the case. Institutions may be part of an equilibrium, and yet be
dysfunctional. For example, Arnott and Stiglitz [1991] consider the consequences of the
social institutions that arise as a result of the incomplete insurance provided by markets
because of moral hazard problems. They show that informal social insurance may crowd
out market insurance and lower social welfare. Developing countries may be caught in a
6
Formally, suppose each resource owner who enforces his property rights hires L workers, and
the value of their output is F(L). His rents are thus F(L) w(x)L, where w is the wage function,
which decreases with the fraction x of resource owners who enforce their property rights. Let the
enforcement cost be C. There are two equilibria if F(L) w(1)L > C > F(L) w(0).
vicious circle in which low levels of market development result in high levels of
information imperfections, and these information imperfections themselves give rise to
institutions for example, informal, personalized networks of exchange relationships
(Kranton, 1996) that impede the development of markets. Banerjee and Newman 1997
show that dualism the idea that market forces play out in one sector but not in
another can be explained as the consequence of a self-sustaining network. Dualism
may be one equilibrium among several.
Path Dependence
Recent historical accounts go beyond the observation that there are multiple equilibria
and show that economic outcomes exhibit path dependence. Moreover, temporary shocks
can have longlasting effects there is hysteresis.
The distribution of wealth in the past is one of the most important channels through
which history can have potentially large, permanent effects. The literature on this nexus
is much too extensive to cite. Here we summarize a few central ideas. One line of thought
emphasizes political influences. Engerman and Sokoloff (1997), for example, find that
the historically highly unequal distribution of wealth in the colonies of the Americas that
practiced plantation agriculture had longlasting effects through the legal, educational, and
political institutions that were adopted. Another line of thought, summarized in Hoff
(1994), shows that agency costs in credit and labor markets depend on the distribution of
wealth; individuals with little or no wealth may have no access to credit and face limits
on the kinds of labor and land rental contracts that they can enter into. Through this
means, the impact of a given initial distribution of wealth may affect wage rates, interest
rates, investments, and bequests and may persist indefinitely over time (Banerjee and
Newman, 1993 and Mookherjee and Ray, 1998, 1999).
Modern theory, in contrast, suggests that those working in the Coase tradition
were looking for inefficiencies in the wrong place. The iconic examples of technological
externalities--the pastoral examples and the lighthouses, as well as many others
emphasized by Chandler's history of American business--are ones where the
"unappropriated benefits" can be internalized through private arrangements. Such private
arrangements include mergers, which change the boundary between what is transacted in
the market and what is transacted within the firm. But there are many other externalities
not amenable to easy solution. They include information externalities, group reputation
effects, agglomeration effects, and knowledge spillovers. They also include pecuniary
externalities (Newbery and Stiglitz 1982, Greenwald and Stiglitz 1985). Pecuniary
externalities often look analytically like externalities of the familiar technological sort.
Recall the example above on property rights, where as a larger number of people fenced
10
in their forests, the return to fencing went up. In that example, the spillover effects were
transmitted only through the change in the wage rate.
Modern theory radically broadens our notion of spillover effects. It shows that there
are many cases where even the price vector can be viewed as a public good. In such
cases, the price vector is not a deterministic outcome that one can mechanically derive
from supply and demand functions. Instead, each individual's choices in a society may
contribute to a better or worse equilibrium price vector. There are multiple, Paretorankable equilibria. In one equilibrium, the price system points the way to an efficient
outcome, better for everyone than the alternative equilibrium outcomes; but there are
other equilibrium prices that do not.
"Ecological Economics"
Whereas neoclassical economics emphasizes the forces pulling toward equilibrium
and with similar forces working in all economies, all should be pulled toward the same
equilibrium, modern development economics focuses more on evolutionary processes,
complex systems, and chance events that may cause systems to diverge. Thus, it tends to
be influenced more by biological than physical models. Near the end of the Origin of
Species, Darwin (1859) wrote, in thinking about the Galapagos Islands:
[The plants and animals of the Galapagos differ radically among islands that
have] the same geological nature, the same height, climate, etc . This long
appeared to me a great difficulty, but it arises in chief part from the deeply seated
error of considering the physical conditions of a country as the most important for
its inhabitants; whereas it cannot, I think, be disputed that the nature of the other
inhabitants, with which each has to compete, is at least as important, and
generally a far more important element of success (p. 540).7
7
Darwin (1859) devotes two chapters, XII and XIII, to this idea.
11
The economy is like an ecosystem, and Darwin was implicitly recognizing that
ecosystems have multiple equilibria. Far more important in determining the evolution of
the system than the fundamentals (the weather and geography) are the endogenous
variables, the ecological environment. Luck accidents of history may play a role in
determining that and, thus, in the selection of the equilibrium.
The table tells the main story of the change between the old and new views of
spillover effects. From these spillover effects, it is easy to formulate models with
underdevelopment traps. We elaborate on these examples in the next section, and present
an empirical test for farm households in rural China in the following section.
Beekeepers and
apple farmers
Externalities
Polluting
factories
"Ecological" view
Lighthouses
Group reputation
12
To analyze this situation, consider a simple model in which the profit (utility) of any
producer (all producers are assumed identical) depends on prices, his own level of R&D
(his action ai , which can be any value between 0 and 1) and the level of R&D of all
others (their action a). Since we will be concerned here only with the set of symmetric
equilibria, we consider only the case where all other producers choose the same action.
13
Thus, we write the profit function as Ui(ai ; a ,p(a)), where p is the price vector (which
itself depends on the vector of actions of the agents). Assume for each agent decreasing
marginal returns to an increase in the level of his action. Each agent chooses its action to
maximize its utility, given the actions of others. (Each agent is small enough that there
are no strategic interactions, and it ignores its effect on p). The reaction function
(1)
ui1(ai; a, p(a)) = 0
characterizes the action that the representative agent i will take for all possible values of a
selected by the remaining actors. ui1 represents the partial derivative of ui with respect to
the first argument ai. (1) states that, given a, the agent cannot obtain a higher payoff by a
marginal change in the level of his action. Figure 2 depicts the case where a higher
action a by all other agents will lead the remaining agent i to follow suit. A higher action
by other agents increases the marginal return to higher action by each. The actions of
different agents are complements.
The interior, symmetric equilibria are values of a* that solve the equation:
(2)
. When others do little R&D, it does not pay any firm to do much R&D, but a
14
shock that changes the level of R&D by each firm to a level even slightly above a*
will
generate a discontinuous response that shifts the equilibrium to a*
Bureaucrats and innovators. Sah and Stiglitz [1989] formulate a model of societal
equilibrium in which individuals can choose to behave bureaucratically or
innovatively. Bureaucrats make life for innovators more difficult, and conversely. Let
x be the fraction of the population that chooses to be innovative. Let U(I; x, p) be the
utility associated with the innovative strategy, and let U(B; x, p) be the utility associated
with the bureaucratic strategy. Each individual chooses the activity that yields him the
greater utility, taking x and p as given, where p is a function of x: p= p(x). Then it is easy
to see that there may be multiple equilibria. If most people choose to behave
bureaucratically, then it may pay only a few people to behave innovatively, and
conversely. An interior equilibrium (where x is between 0 and 1) is a fraction x* that
solves the equation
15
Equilibria also may exist where all agents make the same choice, one entailing
bureaucratic behavior if
A slight variant of this model can be used to explore evolutionary dynamics. Assume
that rather than the individuals choosing to be either innovative or bureaucratic,
differential reproductive rates are a function of utility levels, so that
for some positive constant k. Then the set of equilibria will be the same as before, and
the equilibrium upon which the economy converges depends on its history. Historical
events e.g. the opening of a country to international competition that differentially
hurts bureaucratic firms may move the economy from one equilibrium to the other,
thereby affecting the long-run rate of technological progress.
16
17
agents. Agents carry out overseas trade on behalf of the merchants, and make one
choice: to be honest or to cheat the merchant. A merchant also makes one choice: to rely
on collectivist or individualist means to punish cheaters. Under collectivist enforcement,
a merchant refuses to hire an agent who is known to have cheated any merchant in the
collective group. Under individualist enforcement, a merchant punishes only agents who
have cheated him. Greif shows that if a merchant believes that collectivist enforcement is
likely to occur, then it may not be in his interest to hire an agent who is known to have
cheated other merchants. That makes such expectations self-fulfilling.
The intuition for this result is straightforward: an agent who already has damaged his
reputation has little to lose by cheating again, and so he will be more easily tempted to
cheat his current employer than would an agent with an unblemished reputation. That
makes the agent who has already damaged his reputation by cheating an undesirable
prospect to hire. On the other hand, if the merchant believes that individualist
enforcement will occur, then the motive for collectivist enforcement is absent. Thus, two
equilibria, one entailing collectivist enforcement and the other individualist enforcement,
may exist. The equilibrium that is selected will depend on beliefs (culture).
In the short run, reliance on individualist enforcement will be more costly since it
forgoes the stronger, group-level punishment mechanism. But in the long run,
individualist enforcement will strengthen the forces contributing to the emergence of
state-level mechanisms to enforce contracts and adjudicate conflicts. By facilitating the
18
widening of markets and anonymous trades, such institutions, in turn, tend to promote
long-run growth. Greif [1994] interprets the history of the West in just such terms.
The structure of ownership. Whereas many writers in the Coase tradition have
empahsized that, once one took account of transactions costs, private negiations would
lead to an efficient ownership structure. (A modern, qualitied statement is Grossman and
Hart, 1986.) This implication, however, may break down when the ownership structure
has spillovers for others. Hoff and Sen (2000) examine a simple setting where owners of
residential property negotiate with would-be residents. Each would-be resident
household chooses between home-owning or renting the residence, knowing that only as
a homeowner will the household have incentives to expend effort in maintaining the
property. Surplus is created when homeowners (rather than absentee landlords) expend
effort in maintenance. But for low-income households, imperfections in the credit market
mean that there is a cost to homeownership: the real interest rate for borrowers is higher
than for that for savers. In choosing whether to rent or purchase their residence, a
household compares the benefit of the expected surplus (the appreciation in the value of
its home) with the transaction cost of borrowing. An improvement by one homeowner
unavoidably increases the value of the parcels owned by others in the neighborhood.
Thus, one impact of a larger number of homeowners in the neighborhood is that the
return to homeownership increases. When these spillover effects are strong enough, Hoff
and Sen show that there may be multiple equilibria in the critical level of income above
which an individual will choose to become a homeowner.8
8
There are two interpretations of the model. The one we describe here focuses on equity
investments by residents. An alternative interpretation focuses on equity investments by
19
of individuals in the neighborhood are homeowners, they generate the higher level of
local spillovers that makes that better state of affairs a stable equilibrium. The critical
income level falls, respectively, to y*
or y*
.9
entrepreneurs. The model is a kind of parable of capitalism, where private ownership of capital
(homes by residents, firms by entrepreneurs) energizes an economy and yet, because there are
spillovers across agents, it is not the only equilibrium state of affairs.
9
Formally, let F(y) be the fraction of households with income below y. Then an equilibrium is
defined by a critical income level y* above which a household chooses to become a homeowner,
and a fraction x* of households who are homeowners, such that 1-F(y*) = x*. Equivalently,
F-1(1-x) = y*. A stable equilibrium is one where the F-1(1-x) curve cuts the y* curve from above,
so that for perturbations in expectations below (above) x*, the actual income level is greater (less)
than the critical income level. We discuss the equilibrium concept in the appendix.
20
the endogenous formation of interaction groups. Local poverty traps can be selforganizing.
The modern theory of traps based on demand effects depends on two factors: scale
economies and some nontradable input into production. For example, if intermediate
goods are nontradable (they cannot be imported), then increasing returns in their
production can generate external economies at the level of final (tradable) goods. An
expansion of industry in an economy increases the demand for these nontradable inputs,
which lowers their average costs and increases the available variety. With greater variety
of intermediate inputs, production of final goods may be more efficient (e.g., computer
technicians who specialize in particular programs can troubleshoot problems faster than
generalists). It can thus be the case that when all other sectors industrialize, it pays the
remaining sector to do so, but when all other sectors use a traditional technology that
does not require intermediate inputs, it pays the remaining sectors to do so, too. An
underdevelopment trap can thus be sustained even when the economy is fully open to
21
international trade [Helpman and Krugman 1985, ch. 11; Rodrguez-Clare 1996; Rodrik
1996].
There are a variety of ways one can think of the nontradable inputs. One way is that
they represent different categories of specialized skilled labor, e.g. computer technicians
and software designers. As Rodrik [1996: 2] argues, A workers decision to invest in a
specialized skill depends both on the demand for the particular skill and the existence of
complementary skills in the economy. But this example raises the question, why cant a
single firm train the labor force it needs and thereby internalize the externalities among
the decisions of employees and between their decisions and those of the firm? Acemoglu
(1997) suggests a reason. He shows that even perfect contracting within a firm and
perfect capital market may fail to internalize the social consequences of the decisions
made by workers and firms. His explanation relies on search costs.
Acemoglu's model has two kinds of actors: firms, which may adopt new technology
or not; and workers, who may become trained to use the new technology, or not. A
workers investment in training pays off only if he is employed by a firm that has
innovated; and a firms investment in innovation pays off only if it employs a worker that
is trained. There are a large and equal number of firms and workers. Each firm employs
just one worker. There are two time periods. In the first period, a firm is matched with
one worker, they jointly make decisions over training and innovation, and there is
complete contracting between them, i.e., no information problems or transactions costs.
At the end of the first period, there is some risk of separation. If separation occurs, a firm
22
has to find a new worker, and a worker has to find a new firm. In the second period,
output is produced. The time line is illustrated below:
Period 1
decisions over
investment in innovation
and in training are made
by the firm and the worker
Period 2
separation between
the firm and the worker
occurs with probability s
output is produced
If there were no search costs in the labor market, separation between a firm and
employee would not create a loss. If separation occurred, the worker would simply move
on to another firm that had adopted the new technology, and all the surplus from training
and investment would be captured by the firms and workers who made the investments.
But suppose that search is costly. With costly search, matching will be imperfect. There
is no guarantee that the firm with the investment in the new technology will be matched
with the worker who has the training.
For simplicity, assume the matching process is random (but any assumption short of
costless, perfect matching would serve, too). Then the probability of a good match is the
proportion of firms with the new technology (which is equal to the proportion of the
workers who are trained). From the perspective of the firm and its worker making their
investment decisions in period 1, the combined returns from training and innovation at a
present value cost C are equal to -C + [1-s] + s, where s is the probability of
separation and is the payoff to the new technology (with > C). This says that with
probability 1-s, the pair do not separate and so they capture the return on their
23
investment. With probability s, the pair separate and thus the expected combined return
on their investment is only .
By substituting = 1, we can see that an equilibrium where all firms innovate and all
workers are trained exists: the private returns to training and investment are positive. By
substituting = 0, we can see that an equilibrium without training and innovation may
also exist. The combined expected gains to the firm and worker from innovation and
training when no one else adopts the new technology are only [1-s] - C, which will be
negative if the probability of separation, s, is sufficiently close to one. In this example,
therefore, a possible equilibrium is no innovation and no training in the economy.
Another consequence of costly search, which we do not develop here but which
Acemoglu develops, is that there is imperfect competition in the labor market. This
depresses the workers return to training, which further erodes his incentives to train.
To recapitulate, the reason for the multiplicity of equilibria is that a firm's likelihood
of finding the right worker depends on the thickness of the market (the number of trained
workers). And the worker's likelihood of finding the right employer also depends on the
thickness of the market provided by firms who have adopted the new technology. Of
course, without a risk of separation (s=0), there would be no inefficiencies since there
would be no interactions with future employees or employers. The inefficiency arises
because of an externality between the worker and his future employer, and between the
firm and its future employee, which cannot be internalized because the identity of the
actor with whom one may be matched is unknown.
24
An Econometric Test:
Local poverty traps among farm households in China
Examples from this literature are Azariadis and Drazen 1990 and Easterly and Levine 2000,
who provide evidence for underdevelopment traps based on cross-country growth patterns, and
Glaeser et al. 1996, who provide evidence of social interaction effects in cross-city crime levels.
25
one finds a rural poverty rate in the inland mountainous province of Guizhou in 1990 that
is 7-10 times higher (depending on the poverty line) than in the neighboring coastal
province of Guangdong, only a few hundred kilometers away.
The data are from a six-year panel of 5,600 farm households in southern China
over 1985-90. Jalan and Ravallion estimate two models, which are derived from
optimizing behavior.11 The first is a simple expository model where the only two
variables that matter for the consumption growth rate of a household are initial household
wealth per capita (HW) and mean wealth per capita in the county of residence (CW). The
estimated equation for the growth rate, g, is (t-ratios in parentheses):
(3)
(8.13)
The results indicate that in counties where average wealth is higher, average growth of
household consumption is higher. Thus, there is divergence over the 6-year period of the
survey. Jalan and Ravallion interpret this result to mean that an increase in the average
wealth of the county increases the marginal return to own household wealth. This is due
entirely to geographic externalities, rather than increasing returns to own wealth at the
farm-household level, since the negative coefficient on HW implies that there are
11
The key equilibrium condition equates the intertemporal marginal rate of substitution with the
marginal product of 'own capital', which is a function of the initial endowment of own capital and
the amount of community capital. The econometric analysis then tests the hypothesis that this
function is decreasing in own capital and increasing in county capital. The estimation method
26
decreasing returns to capital within households. Within the model, the results suggest
that a high level of household wealth in a high-wealth region can have the same marginal
product as a low level of household wealth in a low-wealth region.
We illustrate these results in Figure 4. Let K denote the household's capital stock,
and K denote the average household capital stock in the county. The econometric results
suggest that marginal productivity function is downward sloping with respect to own
capital, and shifts up with an increase in the average level of capital in the county. (Ignore
points 1 and 2 in the figure for now.)
(4)
and also plots the actual values of household wealth and county wealth from the survey.
Notice that every household is near the critical line. (The reader may check his
understanding of the graph by noting that a typical household whose per capita wealth is
ln 6 yuan will enjoy rising or falling consumption over time, respectively, as the
household lives in a county with per capita wealth lower or greater than ln 6.5 yuan.) It is
clear from the plot that there is a large subset of the data for which county wealth is too
low, given household wealth, to permit rising consumption. Spillover effects appear to be
large enough to generate poverty traps.
controls for latent household and geographic effects in consumption growth rates at the level of
27
We now use Figure 4 to illustrate the possibility of dual equilibria. For this
purpose, it is useful to make the simplifying assumption that every household in a county
is identical, so K = K . Point 1 is an underdevelopment trap where household capital is
low and the returns to new investment are low because others' capital is low. But there is
another equilibrium at point 2 where the reverse is true.
The richer model that Jalan and Ravallion estimate does not use county wealth but
instead the detailed county-level variables listed in the table. The table shows their main
results (dummies for county, period, mountains/plains, coastal/inland, etc. are deleted).
Coefficient
estimate
t-ratio
0.0420*
3.4328
0.0013
1.5013
0.0023*
4.5678
0.0160
1.6949
0.0159
0.9000
-0.0313*
-2.5295
0.0011*
3.6882
0.0067*
2.1156
0.0741*
4.3033
Geographic variables
-0.0228
-1.0254
the household.
28
The results indicate that both of the county variables that relate to the extent of
modernization in agriculture (farm machinery usage per capita and fertilizer usage per
acre), and also the proportion of the population employed in non-farm commerce, have
highly significant positive impacts on individual consumption growth rates. A one
standard deviation increase in farm machinery usage in an area adds 0.6 percentage
points to the annual consumption growth rate holding all else constant; a one standard
deviation increase in fertilizer usage adds 1.5 points. By comparison, a one standard
deviation increase in rural road density add 0.7 points. Following the same basic
procedure as above (setting g = 0 and evaluating all but one of the variables at its mean
value), Jalan and Ravallion show that the magnitude of these spillovers is large enough to
generate underdevelopment traps, consistent with the implication of their simple,
expository model.
Perspectives on Policy
Work on coordination failures suggests that development may be both easier and
harder than was previously thought. While under the older theory, all one had to do to
ensure development was transfer enough capital and remove government-imposed
distortions, under the new theories, all one has to do is to induce a movement out of the
old equilibrium, sufficiently far, and in the right direction, that the economy will be
attracted to the good equilibrium. While this may require fewer resources, it may
require more skill. Some policies could lead the economy to an even worse equilibrium.
That is, even after the policies were removed, their ill effects would persist.
29
One response to the modern literature on coordination failures has been to emphasize
the limitations in our knowledge of the combination of activities that should be
coordinated and, hence, the dangers of a using the power of the state to establish a
particular coordination mechanism. Jeffrey Sachs, for example, points out that the
problem of highly centralized coordination of activities by government, as occurred in the
centrally planned economies, is not so much that they never experienced rapid growth,
but rather that they suffered from a lack of inventiveness and became "prematurely grey''
(attributed to Sachs by Matsuyama, 1998). Matsuyama compares the problem of
coordination to "the problem of hundreds of people, scattered in a dense, foggy forest,
trying to locate one another..." (p. 134). Neither governments alone, nor markets alone,
can solve it. Early writers who correctly pointed out the sources of coordination failures
drew the wrong policy lessons when they interpreted coordination failures as a call for a
'big push' industrialization centrally controlled by the state.
A further issue is that to make the analysis of intervention precise requires a dynamic
framework. Only in a dynamic framework can one ask whether an initial coordination
failure will in fact transmit itself over time. Why wouldnt forward-looking agents, with
sufficiently low discount rates, adopt a path (that might include the option of changing
their behavior several times) that would permit as an equilibrium a self-fulfilling move
away from a bad equilibrium to a good one? Is there really any scope for policy? Adsera
and Ray (1998) address these questions in a setting where each agent makes a discrete
choice between two activities (which could be interpreted as entry into a high-technology
sector that offers a high return in the long run if it obtains a certain critical mass, versus a
30
low-tech sector. These authors obtain a striking result: If the positive externalities from
moving to the more favorable set of activities appear with a time lag (that can be made
arbitrarily short), then the final outcome depends entirely on initial conditions unless
there is some gain to being the first to switch. To put it another way, without some gain
to being among the first to switch, each individual will rationally wait for others to switch
first, and so no one will switch at all! Initial conditions will thus determine the entire
equilibrium outcome.
Adsera and Ray are thus able to show that there is a potential role for policy to enable
an economy to break free of history. A temporary intervention can 'force' an equilibrium,
and yet, once the equilibrium is attained, the intervention is no longer necessary to
support it. This has the advantage that by the time agents have learned how to corrupt the
rule-administering process, the rule may no longer be needed. We next consider two
such interventions.
31
12
A historical case is Korea in 1961. President Park inherited a corrupt bureaucracy, from
Synghman Rhee, that chose policies on the grounds of self-enrichment. Within a month of seizing
office, he dismissed about the top 10% of bureaucrats, jailed owners of conglomerates for
corruption, and sent the rest of the bureaucracy to two-week training courses in management,
efficiency, and public spiritedness. He then personally monitored the performance of the
economic bureaucrats and shifted them from one bureau to another quickly, so that they could
not develop corruption networks. The result was a total transformation of the functioning of the
government and its interaction mode with the chaebols, from a soft state to a hard one. Park then
proceeded to design the subsequent development plan.(personal correspondence of Irma
Adelman,; Mason, 1980).
13
Other examples of temporary policy that can force a shift from one to another equilibrium are
bankruptcy law and a ban on child labor. Miller and Stiglitz [1999] present a model in which a
bankruptcy law that establishes stronger debtor rights eliminates the bad equilibrium in which
there are large numbers of bankruptcies resulting from the large transfers associated with large
32
An example of the dynamics of the political process may help illustrate what we have
in mind. Assume government is contemplating privatizing a monopoly. There are
several potential buyers. Each has an interest in ensuring that the regulations that prevail
after privatization allow him to continue to enjoy the monopoly profits, and perhaps even
leverage the monopoly power further. But each, thinking that he has a small probability
of winning, is unwilling to spend much to ensure this collective good (or bad,
depending on ones perspective). Moreover, each may face large costs of identifying
who the other potential buyers are. Even if a potential buyer succeeds in identifying the
others, if they are numerous there would still be a free rider problem, each claiming
creditor-friendly bankruptcies. Basu and Van [1998] show how child labor laws can eliminate a
bad equilibrium with child labor. In the good equilibrium that results, no one actually wants to
have his children work.
33
publicly that he himself will obtain high profits through increased efficiency rather than
by exploiting monopoly power.14 But once the privatization has occurred, there is a
single party who is the winner. There no longer is a collective action problem, and the
winner has the incentive and resources to fight legislation imposing regulation or
competition. Thus, before the privatization, it may be possible to pass rules to promote
competition (since there is no organized resistance in the private sector)15 and there may
be, admittedly weak, public interest groups pushing for it. The sequencing of reforms
whether regulatory policies precede or follow privatization matters. In one sequence,
one may end with a competitive or regulated industry, where the benefits of privatization
in terms of lower consumer prices are realized. In the latter case, one may end up with an
unregulated monopoly, one which, to be sure, may be more efficient than it was as a
public sector producer. But it may be more efficient not only in producing goods, but also
in exploiting consumers.
It is precisely because history matters that interventions can be effective in the long
run. A perturbation to the system at one date can have permanent effects. By contrast, in
neoclassical and related theories, it is fundamentals including those associated with the
political process that determine long-run outcomes.
14
Palfrey and Rosenthal (1984) present a model in which the larger the number of potential
beneficiaries of a discrete public good, the less likely the public good is to be supplied.
15
In the next section, we discuss the case, which is especially relevant in transition economies,
where there is organized resistance within the government to privatization.
34
In many cases, too, we have learned that the privatization process may even have
limited efficacy in stemming the flow of on-going rent-seeking by government. For
instance, if local authorities have regulatory oversight (environmental, building permits,
etc.), local government approval is needed for continued operation. It matters not what
16
In the transition economies, it has been argued that privatization of natural monopolies and
highly concentrated industries should proceed even when government is too divided between proand anti-reform forces to create a regulatory regime prior to privatization (Boycko, Shleifer, and
Vishny 1996). But this argument would seem to violate the following straightforward criterion of
consistency: If one argues that government cannot implement a policy (e.g. industry
regulation) because of a trait (a divided government), then one cannot also argue that
government should do a policy P (privatization), unless one can show that P is consistent with the
trait . If the reformers have enough power to impose privatization, then the argument that they
cannot impose regulation is consistent in the above sense only if privatization is less costly to
the ministries than regulation would be, i.e., because the ministries privatize to themselves (Hoff
and Stiglitz 2000).
35
pretext the government needs to hold up the company. Eliminating one pretext still
leaves a plethora of others. Privatization thus does not effectively tie the hand of
government. It is only a deep intervention, which changes the nature of government
behavior, that will succeed in addressing these concerns. We earlier provided one
example from Korea.
Finally, consider the unsuccessful agricultural privatization in Russia in 19911999, based on Amelina (2000). In 1991, Russia legalized individual farming and
dismantled the subsidies for cooperative farms. Yet six years later, the share of
agricultural land used by cooperatives had fallen little: from 91% in 1991 to 80% in
1997. One might have hoped that the introduction of private property rights would have
caused farmers to exit the inefficient system of cooperative farms and produce for
themselves. But market institutions for providing inputs to the farmers for storage,
processing, transport, and insurance were not in place. When the Soviet system collapsed
and cooperatives were left without federal support, district politicians to varying degrees
took up the task of ensuring the supply of inputs and subsidies to the cooperatives, as the
Soviet center had once done.17 This removed the potential demand new market
institutions and for suppliers capable of servicing the needs of small producers. Amelina
interviewed households to learn their reasons for remaining within the cooperative
system. Among the top two reasons (out of a choice set of 10) in both districts she studied
was that "There is no other place to work" (Amelina, p. 94).
17
Amelinas comparison of two districts finds that this was more true in the district in which
agriculture bulked larger in the local economy. In that district, most politicians had risen through
the ranks of the cooperative system. They had highly developed human capital in transferring
funds to and from the cooperatives, and a large political stake in meeting cooperatives' needs.
36
Conclusion
Developments in economics over the past 30 years have validated RosensteinRodan's basic intuition. A critical determinant of actions is ones environment, including
the behaviors of other agents in that environment. Whereas we used to believe that the
implication of externalities was that the economy would be slightly distorted, we now
understand that the interaction of these slight distortions may produce very large
distortions. An economy may be "trapped" in a bad equilibrium, even though there exists
a better state of affairs that would also be an equilibirum.
Modern theory has extended Rosenstein-Rodan's insight very far. We now see that
some of the basic distinctions developed in standard theory do not hold. There is no
simple technology-based distinction between activities that produce externalities and
those that do not, or between activities with public good properties and those with private
good properties. The externalities that matter for welfare are not just direct
interdependencies (Meade's beekeeper and apple farmer). We now recognize many
classes of systematic externalities, of which an important example are those that arise in
purely price-mediated interactions. Given history, beliefs, and chance, certain behaviors
are rewarded, others are not. Rewarded behaviors will tend to increase relative to others,
and that may further increase the rewards to those behaviors. Initial differences in
circumstances or beliefs may not only persist, but be magnified over time.
37
Development policy in this view is both easier and harder than it was before. It is
easier because, in general, there is slack. The lack of resources need not be the
fundamental constraint on development. A temporary policy intervention, or a seemingly
minor shock, may produce discontinuous change. But policy is harder because there is
no single easily identifiable source of failure that is waiting to be resolved.18 Neither the
transfer of capital, nor free markets and international trade, nor the emergence of an
entrepreneurial class ensures development. In some environments, the entrepreneurial
class become entrepreneurs in predation! In the view outlined here, development
requires a set of complementary changes in the behavior of agents, which not even the
market mechanism can coordinate. We suggested certain policies policies that change
beliefs, temporary reforms in law, and changes in the distribution of wealth that may
contribute to coordinated changes to shift an economy to a better equilibirum.
We hope we have conveyed the intellectual excitement generated by the idea that
multiple equilibria, some of which are desirable and some of which are traps, can occur
18
Despite a long history in development economics of arguing that there was such a factor. See
Adelman, forthcoming.
38
due to the collective interdependence in decision-making.19 The lesson to draw from this
literature is that coordination failures abound and are important. Neither the market alone
nor government alone can solve them. There are in many cases misguided incentives in
the private sector. There are a different set of misguided incentives in the public sector.
But it need not be the case that the misguided government cannot correct the misguided
private sector. There may be a social equilibrium in which the forces are balanced in a
way that is Pareto-improving relative to a situation in which the government's hands are
completely tied, and certainly better than one in which the private sector's hands are
completely tied.
Mathematical Appendix
This appendix highlights the logic and common mathematical structure of many
of the models described in this article. We focus on static models of market equilibria.
By static we mean that the interactions across agents are treated as contemporaneous,
rather than intertemporal. This assumption is made for simplicity. (One can interpret
19
Consider the simple adage, If a man can make a better mousetrap than his neighbor,
though he builds his house in the woods, the world will make a beaten path to his door"
(attributed to Ralph Waldo Emerson by Bartlett 1980). And consider the favorable case where
people know about the invention. From the perspective of the literature on coordination failures,
the outcome predicted by the adage might still require that individuals expect that there will be
enough users to make services in mousetrap repair affordable, that search costs for those services
not be prohibitive, that there is confidence that improved mousetraps would not be stolen, that
barriers sufficiently restrict the free movement of mice so that one mousetrap can make a
difference in one's environment, and that there be a means for the disposal of dead mice.
39
40
ACTIONS
Continuous
choice
variable
Discrete
choice
variable
Property rights
(de Meza-Gould 1992)
Innovation
(Sah and Stiglitz
1989)
Contract enforcement
(Greif 1997)
II
Actors differ in
their payoff
functions
III
Actors differ in their
strategy sets
Training and
innovation
(Acemoglu 1997)
Innovation
(Sah and Stiglitz
1989)
The structure of
ownership
(Hoff and Sen
2000)
Rent-seeking
(Murphy-ShleiferVishny 1993)
41
ui1(ai; a, p(a)) = 0
We assume that an increase in everyone else's action (a) raises ui . As also noted above
(equation (2)), the interior equilibria are the values of a* that solve
If complementarities, captured in this model by the condition that ui12 > 0, are
sufficiently large, there may be multiple Pareto rankable equilibria, as illustrated in
Figure 2. Each individual is better off in the equilibrium where all choose a higher
action.
42
Complementarities exist in this model if the relative return to the first activity is
increasing in the fraction of the population that undertakes the first activity. Formally,
the partial derivative of the payoff function with respect to x, denoted Uxi, satisfies
This states that when all other individuals choose the first activity, it is individually
optimal to choose the first activity. Another corner solution exists where all choose
action 2 if
This states that when all individuals choose the second activity, it is individually
optimally to choose the second activity.
In some specializations of the model that we discussed (de Meza and Gould, 1992,
and Murphy, Shleifer and Vishny, 1989, section IV and 1993), the impact of other
individuals' actions is entirely through prices. All that matters is the "atmosphere", and
43
the atmosphere can be represented solely by the price system. Thus, the utility function of
the ith agent can be written as Ui = Ui(ai; p(x)).
The model can be generalized to an arbitrarily large number of discrete activities. In
Murphy, Shleifer, and Vishny [1993], there are three activities: cash crop production, a
subsistence activity, and rent-seeking (predation). The returns to the subsistence
activity, denoted by
, are exogenous, while the returns to cash crop production and rentseeking are decreasing in the ratio n of people engaged in predation relative to those
engaged in cash crop production. An interior equilibrium is described by values n* that
solve
Ui (1; p(n*)) = Ui(2; p(n*)) =
Suppose that over some range of n, the returns to cash crop production are decreasing
more steeply than the returns to predation. This implies that, over some range of n, the
relative returns to predation are increasing in n. In this case, multiple Pareto-rankable
equilibria, some characterized by a high level of predation, and others characterized by a
low level of predation, may exist.
44
why some individuals choose one action rather than another. The next category of
models entails individual differences in payoff functions.
The structure of these models is such that there is some attribute of the individual,
reflected in, say, his utility function or wealth, and denoted for simplicity by c; and there
is a probability distribution of individuals according to c, say F(c). ). Individuals have a
choice of two activities, 1or 2. The individual chooses his activity, ai, to maximize
Vi(ai; x, c), taking x as given. (For simplicity, we suppress the dependence of payoffs on
p(x).) The utility functions have the structure that we can order individuals by c, such that
there exists a critical value c* such that individuals whose attribute is above c* prefer
activity 1, while individuals whose attribute is below c* prefer activity 2. Formally,
for c > c*
and
Complementarities are defined, as above, by the condition that the relative return to
activity 1 is increasing in the fraction x of individuals undertaking activity 1:
Vxi(1,x,c)
- Vxi(2,x,c) > 0. When complementarities are sufficiently strong, there can exist
multiple solutions for c*.
45
Multiple equilibria can also emerge from the interaction several different kinds of
agents. Consider a situation in which there are groups of actors that differ in their strategy
sets, e.g., firms and workers. (For simplicity, we will represent each group by a single
agent, but in fact each group can consist of a large number of agents. In that case, we
solve for the symmetric equilibrium of each class of agents using the techniques of Class
IC.)
Suppose there are two groups of actors, and suppose the action of the first is a
continuous variable denoted by a, and the action of the second is a continuous variable
denoted by b. Then the first group maximizes a payoff function v1(a; b, p(a,b)) with
respect to a, given b and p; and the second maximizes v2(a; b, p(a,b))with respect to b,
given a and p.
The interior equilibria are the solutions to the equations
va1 (a*,b*,p(a*,b*)) = 0
and
vb2 (a*,b*,p(a*,b*))= 0
There may exist multiple values of (a*,b*) that solve these equations if there are
complementarities between the two groups of actors, which is captured by the condition
that vab i > 0.
46
References
Acemoglu, Daron. 1997. Training and Innovation in an Imperfect Labour Market. Review of
Economic Studies 64(220) July: 445-464.
Adelman, Irma. Forthcoming. "Fallacies in Development Theory and Their Implications for
Policy." In Gerald Meier, ed., Pioneers in Development. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, forthcoming.
Adsera, Alicia and Debraj Ray. 1998. History and Coordination Failure. Journal of Economic
Growth 3(3) September: 267-276.
Amelina, Maria. 2000. False Transformations: From Stalins Peasants to Yeltsins Collective
Farmers Working Paper (Washington, DC: World Bank), forthcoming.
Arnott, Richard and Joseph E. Stiglitz. 1991. Moral Hazard and Nonmarket Institutions:
Dysfunctional Crowding Out or Peer Monitoring? American Economic Review 81(1)
March: 179-190.
Azariadis, C. and A. Drazen. 1990. Threshold Externalities an Economic Development.
Quarterly Journal of Economics 105, 501-526.
Banerjee, Abhijit J. and Andrew F. Newman. 1993. Occupational Choice and the Process of
Development. Journal of Political Economy 101(2) April: 274-298.
__________. 1998. Information, the Dual Economy, and Development. Review of Economic
Studies 65(225) October: 631-653.
Bardhan, Pranab. 1997. Corruption and Development: A Review of Issues. Journal of
Economic Literature, 35: 1320-46.
Bartlett, John. 1980. Familiar Quotations. (Boston: Little, Brown & Co.).
Basu, Kaushik and Pham Hoang Van. 1998. The Economics of Child Labor. American
Economic Review 88(3) June: 412-427.
Besley, Timothy and Stephen Coate. 1998. "Sources of Inefficiency in a Representative
Democracy: A Dynamic Analysis." American Economic Review 88(1) pp. 139-154.
Boycko, Maxim, Andrei Shleifer, and Robert W. Vishny. 1996. Second-best Economic Policy
for a Divided Government. European Economic Review 40(3-5) April: 767-774.
Cheung, Steven S. 1973. "The Fable of the Bees: An Economic Investigation." The Economics of
Legal Relationships: Readings in the Theory of Property Rights, ed. Henry G. Manne,
457-470. New York: West Publishing Company.
Coase, Ronald. 1960. The Problem of Social Cost. Journal of Law and Economics 3: 1-44.
__________. 1974. "The Lighthouse in Economics." Journal of Law and Economics 17 (2) 35776.
47
48
Hoff, Karla and Arijit Sen. 2000. Homeownership, Coordination Games and Polarization in
Neighborhoods. World Bank. Manuscript.
Hoff, Karla and Joseph E. Stiglitz. Forthcoming. "Modern Economic Theory and Development."
In Pioneers in Development, Gerald M. Meier, editor. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hoff, Karla and Joseph E. Stiglitz. 2000. "The logic of political constraints and reform, with
applications to privatization." World Bank, manuscript.
Jalan, Jyotsna and Martin Ravallion. 1998 Geographic Poverty Traps? A Micro Model of
Consumption Growth in Rural China. Discussion Paper No. 86, Institute for
49
Newbery, David M.G. and Joseph E. Stiglitz 1982. "The Choice of Techniques and the
Optimality of Market Equilibrium with Rational Expectations. Journal of Political
Economy 90 (2, April). 223-247.
North, Douglass C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance (New
York: Cambridge University Press).
North, Douglass C. 1994. "Economic Performance through Time." American Economic Review
84: 359-368.
North, Douglass C. and Robert Paul Thomas. 1973. The Rise of the Western World: A New
Economic History (New York: Cambridge University Press).
Nurkse, Ragnar. 1953. Problems of Capital Formation in Underdeveloped Countries. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Olson, Mancur. 1965. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Piketty, Thomas. 1997. "The Dynamics of the Wealth Distribution and the Interest Rate with
Credit Rationing." Review of Economic Studies 64: 173-189.
Ravallion, Martin and J. Jalan. 1999. Chinas Lagging Poor Areas. AEA Papers and
Proceedings: Income Distribution in China. 301-305.
__________. 1996. Growth Divergence Due to Spatial Externalities. Economics Letters
November 1996, 53 (2): 227-32.
Reding, Paul and Juan Antonio Morales. 1999. Currency Substitution and Network
Externalities. unpublished, University of Namur, Belgium.
Rodrik, Dani. 1995. "Trade and Industrial Policy Reform." In Jere Behrman and T.N. Srinivasan,
Handbook of Development Economics volume 3B (Amsterdam: North-Holland), pp. 29252982.
Rodrik, Dani. 1996. Coordination Failures and Government Policy: A Model with Applications
to East Asia and Eastern Europe. Journal of International Economics 40(1-2) February: 122.
Rodrguez-Clare, Andrs. 1996. The Division of Labor and Economic Development. Journal of
Development Economics 49 April: 3-32.
Romer, P. 1986. Increasing Returns and Long-Run Growth. Journal of Political Economy, Vol.
94. 1002-1037.
Rosenstein-Rodan, Paul. 1943. Problems of Industrialization of Eastern and Southeastern
Europe. Economic Journal 53(210-211) June-September: 202-211.
Sah, Raaj Kumar and J.E. Stiglitz. 1989. Sources of Technological Divergence between
Developed and Less Developed Countries. In Guillermo Calvo, et al., eds. Debt,
50
51
$
Rent,
F(L) - w(x)L
Cost of
enforcement
x, fraction of resource
owners who enforce
their property rights
52
ai
1
Agent is
reaction
curve
45o
a*
a
a*
a*
53
y*'
y*''
y*
y*'''
F-1 (1-x)
0
x*'
x*''
x*'''
11
54
$
Marginal cost of capital
2
1
F
( K , K + K )
F
(K, K )
K + K
household capital
55
(g = 0)
Consumption grows
(g>0)
Consumption falls
(g<0)
6
5
2
6
Household wealth (log)
10
56