0% found this document useful (0 votes)
52 views8 pages

Biology vs. The Blank Slate: Ronald Bailey Nick Gillespie Print Edition

- Steven Pinker argues against three modern myths in his new book The Blank Slate: the blank slate, the noble savage, and the ghost in the machine. - The blank slate myth is that the mind has no innate structure and is entirely shaped by the environment. The noble savage myth is that people have no innate violent impulses. The ghost in the machine myth is that people have an immaterial soul not reducible to brain function. - Pinker argues these are myths because humans must have innate mental mechanisms to acquire culture, studies show violence is a human universal, and experiences show parts of the brain are associated with behaviors like violence.

Uploaded by

Adrian Guzman
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
52 views8 pages

Biology vs. The Blank Slate: Ronald Bailey Nick Gillespie Print Edition

- Steven Pinker argues against three modern myths in his new book The Blank Slate: the blank slate, the noble savage, and the ghost in the machine. - The blank slate myth is that the mind has no innate structure and is entirely shaped by the environment. The noble savage myth is that people have no innate violent impulses. The ghost in the machine myth is that people have an immaterial soul not reducible to brain function. - Pinker argues these are myths because humans must have innate mental mechanisms to acquire culture, studies show violence is a human universal, and experiences show parts of the brain are associated with behaviors like violence.

Uploaded by

Adrian Guzman
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8

Reason Magazine - Biology vs.

the Blank Slate

Page 1 of 8

http://www.reason.com
http://www.reason.com/news/show/28537.html

Biology vs. the Blank Slate


Evolutionary psychologist Steven Pinker deconstructs the great myths about how the mind works.
Ronald Bailey and Nick Gillespie | October 2002 Print Edition
Steven Pinker has been called "science's agent provocateur" by the Guardian, named an "evolutionary
pop star" by Time, hailed as a "wunderkind" by The Washington Post, and acclaimed by the London
Times as both a "world-class cognitive psychologist" and a "stud-muffin of science." Yet Pinker, a
professor of psychology in the Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences at the Massachusetts
Institute of Technology, is more than a scientific superstar. He's also the author of the bestsellers How
the Mind Works and The Language Instinct. His new book, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of
Human Nature (Viking), is likely to continue his string of publishing successes -- and to keep him at the
red-hot center of discussions over the meaning and implications of the increasingly important field of
evolutionary psychology.
Evolutionary psychologists such as Pinker argue that the human mind, like the human body, has been
designed by natural selection through the process of biological evolution. Insights from evolutionary
psychology are dramatically transforming the ways in which political scientists, economists,
anthropologists, social psychologists, linguists, and cultural studies critics think about social and
political institutions. If Pinker and his colleagues are right, it turns out that there really is an innate
human nature common to all people.
To be sure, this is not your grandfather's human nature. Evolutionary psychologists argue that the brain
is a physical system with built-in neural circuits designed to generate environmentally appropriate
behavior. These neural circuits are specialized for handling different adaptive problems, and most brain
functioning is unconscious. Because our brains evolved to handle problems faced by our Stone Age
ancestors, some innate behaviors are maladaptive in the modern world. These range from our tendency
to divide people into in-groups and out-groups to our sweet tooth, which helped our ancestors select ripe
fruit in a world where food was scarce, but leads to obesity for many in societies where food is
abundant. Innate brain modules exist for activities such as social learning, language, feeding, mating,
and many other unconscious behaviors. Many of these neural circuits have been mapped by brain scans
and by clinical studies of brain-damaged people.
Evolutionary psychology is addressing age-old questions about human nature. Are people inherently
good? Are they social animals? Are they rational, utility-maximizing individuals? If both nature and
nurture shape our characters and determine our destinies, what is the precise contribution of each? Do
we have free will? These questions lie at the heart of centuries-long political, philosophical, and
religious conflicts. And the answers inform how we think social, political, and economic life should be
organized.
Evolutionary psychology discomfits many intellectuals and scientists and Pinker has been savagely

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 2 of 8

attacked by both the left and the right. Marxists such as Harvard's Richard Lewontin and the late
Stephen Jay Gould assert that evolutionary psychology is little more than fatuous cocktail party
speculation, while conservative commentators in The Weekly Standard and First Things charge Pinker
with trying to undermine the religious basis of morality.
The Blank Slate, which combines scientific insights from genetics, neuroscience, computer science, and
evolutionary biology, is Pinker's rejoinder to such critics. In it, he masterfully deconstructs what he calls
the main "myths" about human psychology that have dominated and distorted intellectual discourse
about human nature for the last century.
Pinker, a native of Montreal, received his B.A. from McGill University in 1976 and his Ph.D. in
psychology from Harvard in 1979. After serving on the faculties of Harvard and Stanford he moved to
MIT in the early 1980s.
Reason Science Correspondent Ronald Bailey and Editor-in-Chief Nick Gillespie spoke with Pinker this
May in Washington, D.C., where he delivered a lecture at the Carnegie Institution.
Reason: What is the aim of your new book, The Blank Slate?
Steven Pinker: To explore why the concept of human nature and biological approaches to the mind in
general are seen as so politically suspect. Why do they arouse so much emotion? Why do people think
that there are great moral issues at stake, as opposed to empirical issues about how the human mind
works?
Some of the issues I explore are concerns of the left, which sees evolutionary and genetic approaches to
the mind as reactionary. Others annoy the right, which thinks that a materialist view of the mind that
incorporates computation, neuroscience, evolution, and genetics undermines the basis of morality and
leaves us with only a dangerous amoralism.
Reason: You talk about three modern "myths" in the book: the blank slate, the noble savage, and the
ghost in the machine. Explain them briefly.
Pinker: The blank slate is the doctrine that the mind has no unique structure and that its entire
organization comes from the environment via socialization and learning. The blank slate mentality is
popular with people who believe that any human trait can be altered with the right changes in social
institutions. It's popular in the more radical branches of feminism, although not with the original core of
feminism that stressed the drive for equity between the sexes. I think it allies to some degree with
Marxist approaches to society. Not that Marx literally believed in a blank slate, but he certainly believed
that you could not intelligently discuss human nature separate from its ever-changing interaction with
the social environment.
The doctrine of the noble savage is that people have no evil impulses, that all malice is a product of
social institutions. The noble savage myth is behind the sensibility that violence is learned behavior, a
slogan that is repeated endlessly whenever violence is chronicled in the news. It's also behind the
Romantic idea that violent nonconformists are actually seeing the hypocrisy of society and challenging
social institutions from a marginalized viewpoint, as opposed to the idea that such people are
psychopaths and that we should prevent them from wreaking havoc on everyone else.
The doctrine of the ghost in the machine is that people are inhabited by an immaterial soul that is the
locus of free will and choice and which can't be reduced to a function of the brain. The ghost in the

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 3 of 8

machine [idea] lies behind the religious and cultural right -- literally in the case of people who want to
couch the stem cell debate in terms of when ensoulment occurs.
But it's there in a vaguer way, too, among others who fear that a materialist viewpoint -- the idea that
human experience and choice are products of a physical organ called the brain -- is corrosive of
morality, meaning, and ultimate purpose.
Reason: Why do you call these ideas myths?
Pinker: Because they're wrong. Let's talk about the blank slate. Just on logical grounds, blank slates
don't do anything. They just sit there. Human beings do things. They make sense of their environment,
they acquire language, they interact with one another. They use reasoning to bring about things that they
want. Even if you acknowledge, as you have to acknowledge, that learning, socialization, and culture are
indispensable aspects of human behavior, you have to admit that you can't have culture unless you have
some kind of innate circuitry that can invent and acquire culture to begin with.
The noble savage [myth] has been refuted by studies of hunter-gatherers and societies more generally
that show how violence and warfare are a human universal. The reports of tribes out there somewhere
who never heard of war have turned out to be urban legends. I think many Western intellectuals had
always been impressed that in many battles among hunter-gatherers, the battle is called off as soon as
the first couple of people are killed. That led to the idea that warfare among pre-state societies was
largely ritualistic. But in fact, if you do the numbers and count the bodies, two deaths in a band of 50
people are much bigger than the September 11th casualties in a society our size.
Careful studies show that hunter-gatherers are dead serious about war. They make weapons as
destructive as their ingenuity permits. And if they can get away with it, they massacre every man,
woman, and child. In our own society, which is far more peaceful than the native groups, if you ask
people whether they have ever fantasized about killing someone, anywhere from 70 percent to 90
percent of the men and about 40 percent to 60 percent of women say that they have.
Reason: And the rest are lying.
Pinker: (laughs) There are also parts of the brain that seem associated with violence and outbursts. We
know this partly because of accidents or operations through which certain portions of some people's
brains were removed. Some sort of inhibitory brake was removed, and the individuals became more
prone to violence.
As a cognitive scientist, I go back to thinking the problem through mechanistically. Just as in the case of
the blank slate, you can't have learning without some kind of learning machinery. Human violence is
highly nonrandom behavior. It's not the kind of thing that can arise from a simple malfunction. There's a
popular notion that violence is a kind of disease or a public health problem; that's what all of the mental
health agencies believe.
Reason: You say in The Blank Slate that Hobbes was right and Rousseau was wrong. Is civilization
basically the development of institutions designed to rein in male violence?
Pinker: I think that's got a lot of truth to it, absolutely. That's what the rule of law is, and that's what a
democracy is for. I don't think it's wiped out these impulses, and our fantasy lives may not be that
different from those of the Yanomamo warrior. But we don't actually act on them. We can have lust and
mayhem in our hearts, but not necessarily in our actions.

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 4 of 8

Reason: Why is the ghost in the machine doctrine a myth?


Pinker: Neuroscience is showing that all aspects of mental life -- every emotion, every thought pattern,
every memory -- can be tied to the physiological activity or structure of the brain. Cognitive science has
shown that feats that were formerly thought to be doable by mental stuff alone can be duplicated by
machines, that motives and goals can be understood in terms of feedback and cybernetic mechanisms,
and that thinking can be understood as a kind of computation. Not computation the way your IBM PC
does computation, but computation nonetheless -- a kind of fuzzy analog to parallel computation. So
intelligence, which formerly seemed miraculous -- something that mere matter could not possibly
accomplish or explain -- can now be understood as a kind of computation process.
Reason: Do you feel like we're going through a cycle of anti-science sentiment, of technophobia?
Biotechnology, in particular, has raised the ire of both the right and the left.
Pinker: I think part of the fear of biotechnology really comes from a notion of the ghost in the machine.
One of the great fears of cloning -- the absurd idea that cloning is going to create an army of mindless
drones -- comes from a mental model of cloning that says that it's duplicating the body without a soul.
The other fear is that it is some kind Faustian grab at immortality, a hubristic desire to make ourselves
immortal. That relies on a mental model of cloning as duplicating the soul together with the body. So if I
clone myself, that's actually going to be me. So much of the debate on cloning comes from these
misconceptions of what it is. Which I think makes perfect sense, if the mental model that most people
have of other humans is a body inhabited by a ghost.
I also think there's a notion of purity vs. contamination at work. It's a kind of noble savage myth.
Cognitive psychologists call it "intuitive essentialism" -- that living things have an essence that gives
rise to their biological properties. It's easy to think of genetically modified foods as living things whose
essences have been contaminated by polluting elements as opposed to the biological view, which is that
organisms are bundles of genes which vary continuously over the course of evolution.
Reason: In an earlier book, How the Mind Works, you say it's possible we will never understand the
mind. Do you still believe that?
Pinker: We may never understand it at an intuitively satisfying level. From a scientific standpoint, I
think we can be satisfied that every aspect of conscious experience can be tied to or caused by some
process in the brain. But what it actually feels like to have a brain is one of these age-old paradoxes that
probably is an artifact of the way our mind conceptualizes things. I would liken it to our puzzlement
over how time can begin at the Big Bang. It's impossible not to think, well, what was it like before the
Big Bang? Or, what is the effect of the universe being curved in the fourth dimension -- what exactly
does that look like? There, the problem is not a deficit in physics; the problem is a deficit in our own
intuition. There is an aspect of reality that can never be intuitively satisfying even though our best
science tells us that it is true.
Reason: In the new book, you suggest that "we may have to make room for a pre-scientific explanatory
concept in our view of human nature -- fate." What do you mean by that?
Pinker: By fate, I don't mean divine preordination. I mean uncontrollable fortune. We can't account for
about half of the variation in things like personality and intellect. I suspect that this 50 percent of the
variation that is neither in the genes nor in the family may be chance events in development, the way
your brain wires itself up within the constraints of the genes.

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 5 of 8

Reason: So for whatever reason, during development, something zigged rather than zagged?
Pinker: Yes, whether the growing axons in your brain zig rather than zag. Whether you inhaled a virus
or your mother inhaled a virus, whether you got the top bunk bed or the bottom bunk bed. All kinds of
uncontrollable events that may have a profound role in making us who we are. Indeed, there is reason to
suspect just from the studies of biological development of simple organisms that chance has to play a
role. When you look at genetically homogenous strains of roundworms and fruit flies growing up in a
well-controlled monotonous laboratory environment, they are not the same. They have physical
differences. They have longevity differences.
Reason: You've exposed the essentially materialist roots of human society. How does that not translate
into humans just being apes, precisely in the way with which the right is so uncomfortable?
Pinker: We are apes, but we're our own species of apes. We're not chimpanzees, and we're not gorillas.
We're a species of ape that has this outsized brain. Among the faculties of this outsized brain is the
ability to learn from history via language and recorded documents. And a moral sense and an ability to
perceive consequences of our actions.
I don't really know where the moral sense is located in the brain because, in a sense, it encompasses a
number of the different faculties. Morality encompasses a mentality of autonomy and interchangeability
of interests. It is also tied to notions of purity and defilement and to notions of conformity to community
norms. If you could take any person and tap his or her moral intuitions, you would get this melange of
sentiments, not all of which coincide with morality as it would be understood by a moral philosopher.
People, for example, tend to equate morality with high rank. We see that in the language: words like
noble, which are ambiguous, [meaning both] high ranking and morally exalted. We see it in celebrity
worship: People think that Princess Diana and John Kennedy Jr. were highly moral people, but they
were pretty average. People tend to blur good looks with morality. You can give them a bunch of
photographs and ask them to judge how nice they think the people are. The better-looking people are
judged as being nicer.
All that is to say that the psychology of morality is multifaceted. There is no one answer to where
morality is in the brain. Recent research has been looking at the part of the brain called the ventromedial prefrontal cortex, pretty much the part of the brain that sits above the eyeballs. When that is
damaged by early brain injury, you grow up with what looks like defective conscience, an inability to
empathize, an inability to think through conflict resolution. But I suspect that it's a complex system
involving a number of parts of the brain.
We're stuck with brains. These are brains that give us pleasure and satisfaction from certain outcomes.
We appreciate beauty. We fall in love. We have a sense of justice and morality. I don't see what's so
terrible about satisfying those particular values that our brains provide us with.
In the case of morality there is a kind of built-in logic, namely that it's inherently contradictory to
impose a standard of behavior on others that you are not willing to have applied to yourself. An amoral
egoist might be able to prevail by sheer brute force by terrorizing everyone else, but if you want to
justify the way you behave to others, if you are part of a community in which your well-being depends
on others, you are kind of stuck with some kind of moral logic. That's why the universal core of morality
across cultures is some kind of golden rule mentality.
Reason: How does a materialistic approach play out on the left? Isn't there an impulse to say, "Let's take

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 6 of 8

these human monkeys and train them in a way that is more perfect?"
Pinker: The fear on the left is that if there is a human nature, we won't be free to design a better society
in the future. They worry that we are marionettes or meat puppets on the ends of strings and that we're
doomed to create a world of oppression and inequality. The reason that doesn't follow is that human
intelligence is an open-ended combinatorial system.
Language is the prime example: Even if we're equipped with a fixed set of grammatical rules and a fixed
vocabulary, we can spin out a mind-boggling array of sentences that have never been uttered before.
Each one of those sentences corresponds to a distinct thought. The open-ended creativity of language is
just a way of externalizing the open-ended creativity of thought. People can come up with new ways of
resolving conflicts or attaining social goals in the same way that they can cook up new technological
solutions to problems. You don't need an unconstrained ghost in order to account for human ingenuity.
Additionally, a number of people think that there is a kind of logic that propels human moral progress.
This is what [philosopher] Peter Singer refers to as the "expanding circle." Intuitions that may have
evolved to deal with life in the clan or the tribe are now enabling us to extend sympathy to other people
and treat them as having interests equivalent to our own. Over the course of history, we have expanded
that circle out from the clan to the tribe to the nation to both sexes and to all races and to all humanity.
Having that kind of moral progress doesn't mean that human nature has ever been erased and
reprogrammed. It simply means that a gadget that may have evolved to deal with a clan can be applied
to larger and larger groups of humans.
Reason: Doesn't a materialist approach undermine Enlightenment notions of free will and autonomy?
As you point out in your book, people are already using excuses such as, "It wasn't me, it was my
amygdala. Darwin made me do it. The genes ate my homework."
Pinker: What we call free will is a product of particular circuits of the brain, presumably concentrated
in the prefrontal lobes, that respond to contingencies of responsibility and credit and blame and reward
and punishment and alter their operations as a consequence.
Our decision to hold people responsible for their behavior is itself part of the environment in which the
brain works. The brain can respond to an environment in which people are held responsible, and that's
why we should continue to hold people responsible.
More to the point, you don't need to invoke a soul or some mysterious process of free will to hold people
accountable. Indeed, one could argue the opposite of that: If we really are totally unconstrained -- if
there is a self or soul that can do what it damn well pleases -- that's when holding people responsible
would be futile. The soul could always choose to ignore contingencies of credit, blame, reward, or
punishment: "I don't care if you think that I'm a lying, cheating bastard. I do what I damn well please."
Reason: There's a cartoon about evolution that shows a sequence in which a fish looks up from a pond,
followed by an amphibian, a reptile, and a primate, ending with a guy wearing a tie. The first four
figures have thought balloons over their heads that read, "Eat, survive, reproduce." The final balloon,
over the man's head, reads, "What does it all mean?" Our genes are interested only in replicating
themselves, so evolution has designed us, and all other living things, with that goal in mind. You have
written that if you choose not to reproduce, you're saying, "If my genes don't like it, they can go jump in
the lake." How does one account for this ability to defy the evolutionary imperative?
Pinker: I don't think evolution did design us to reproduce. Evolution designed us to enjoy sex and to

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 7 of 8

love children. Well, our children, anyway. There is a fallacy that people easily slip into, especially when
they hear explanations of evolution that use the metaphor of the "motives" of genes. It's easy to confuse
the metaphorical motives of the genes with the real motives of the whole person.
There's some pedagogical advantage to putting yourself in the mind-set of the genes -- to think that
genes are driven by this supposed desire to make copies of themselves. But it's important not to confuse
that with what people want to do. I don't think most people want to make copies of themselves. The way
the genes accomplish their metaphorical motive of making copies of themselves is wiring the brain to
like sex and to love little children. In a world without contraception, that's enough to get genes to make
copies of themselves. If you change the world to one with contraception, and adoption, and many other
things that sever these old cause-and-effect contingencies, then you can have the same desires but they
do not necessarily result in babies.
Reason: What do insights from evolutionary psychology tell us about what society should be?
Pinker: I think a concept of human nature gives you insight into human interests, what makes people
happy in general. But this understanding can't provide any insight into how you trade off the happiness
of one person against the happiness of another in cases in which they conflict. That's why we will
always have politics and moral arguments and so on.
Reason: Many critics of evolutionary psychology fear that it may exacerbate social and economic
inequalities by justifying them on biological grounds.
Pinker: Whether humans are mentally indistinguishable or not is an empirical question, and we're not
going to make people into clones by a desire that they be clones, even on the dubious premise that that is
desirable.
Yet we can adopt measures that achieve greater equality if we decide that that is a social good. I think all
that biology tells us is that there may be costs as well as benefits. It is not a new idea, but people have
pointed out that equality of outcome and equality of opportunity are not only different but they are
necessarily in conflict. That doesn't mean necessarily that you have to sacrifice equality of outcome. It
just means that different political ideologies can be arrayed on what point along that tradeoff they argue
is best.
An extreme authoritarian Marxist would sacrifice all freedom to the goal of the equality of outcome.
Perhaps an extreme libertarian position would sacrifice any kind of equality of outcome in favor of
equality of opportunity. If those are the terms of the debate, science can't tell us what's the optimum
point along that tradeoff.
Now, the moral principle regarding equality is simply that people not be prejudged on the basis of
certain group averages, the averages of the groups to which they belong. That is, you should not
discriminate against someone based on gender or ethnicity. That doesn't say that all races and all ethnic
groups and all genders are indistinguishable, although they may be. It says that you don't even have to
worry about that; you should treat individuals as individuals.
Reason: The evolutionary psychologist's account of human behavior is clear and succinct, but as the
physicist Steven Weinberg says, "The more comprehensible the universe becomes, the more pointless it
seems."
Pinker: It may be pointless in some cosmic sense, in the same sense in which there's no point going on

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

Reason Magazine - Biology vs. the Blank Slate

Page 8 of 8

living because, as the young Woody Allen character in Annie Hall said, "The universe is expanding, and
someday it will break apart and that will be the end of everything, so why should I do my homework?"
There's a point at which the Woody Allen anxiety -- what we might call the "Karamazov worry" -- is
confusing two levels of analysis. The first scale consists of billions and billions of years and a universe
which came into existence and which will go out of existence. The second is the scale of hours, minutes,
days, and years in which we live our lives. Just as you don't worry about putting your laptop on the table
after the physicist says that it's mostly empty space on an atomic level, you don't worry about life being
a sham just because the neuroscientist says that morality comes from the brain.
We are looking inside our brains, and the moral sense is an inextricable aspect of human experience that
we have to live with precisely because that's the way our brains are put together. We can go through the
mental gymnastics of stepping outside our brains and looking at how it functions, but once we live our
lives and deal with one another as individuals, these are the intuitions that we are stuck with. And again,
not arbitrarily but for reasons that we can even gain some insight into when we do step outside
ourselves.
Reason: That wonderful ability of recursion that we have -- that we are able to step outside and look at
how our brains function -- still leaves us feeling a sort of ultimate meaninglessness?
Pinker: (laughs) Yeah.
Reason: In other words, except for science, we haven't really gotten much further than Descartes when
it comes to grounding meaning and existence?
Pinker: Yes, in some sense. But what's the alternative? It's not as if there is some coherent alternative
that we're abandoning. It's not as if God decreed on the day of creation that this is the meaning of life.
The same curiosity that leads you to step outside yourself to ask, "Why do we have moral intuitions?"
also makes you step outside God's world and ask, "Well, what told God to create that as the meaning of
our existence?"
So you still have that gnawing existential anxiety. But let me go back to the question of whether seeing
morality as a product of the brain licenses amorality. In practice, it is less dangerous than the idea that
morality is ultimately vested in the commands of a religious authority. 9/11 is only the most recent
example of a case where morality derived from religion leads to horrible atrocities.
Try Reason's award-winning print edition today! Your first issue is FREE if you are not completely
satisfied.

http://www.reason.com/news/printer/28537.html

8/29/2007

You might also like