Whatever Happened To Knowledge
Whatever Happened To Knowledge
of Science
http://sss.sagepub.com/
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
Additional services and information for Social Studies of Science can be found at:
Email Alerts: http://sss.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts
Subscriptions: http://sss.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
Citations: http://sss.sagepub.com/content/42/3/474.refs.html
436555
2012
Whatever happened to
knowledge?
Stephen Turner
Keywords
Bruno Latour, Michael Polanyi, science wars, social constructionism, Thomas Kuhn
Fifty years on, Kuhns Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1996 [1962]) remains a landmark, but understanding its consequences for science studies is not simple. In many
ways it used ideas from Conant and Polanyi, but it reinserted claims about ungroundable
premises from neo-Kantian philosophy, with the predictable result of problems over relativism and scientific progress. These elements remained in social constructionism, leading to problems over reflexivity and reality. Latour, in Science in Action and elsewhere,
determinedly turned away from cognitive explanations in favor of networks. But networks do not explain on their own. So the task of socializing the epistemic and espistemologizing the social returns.
Kuhns Structure of Scientific Revolutions was, at the time, a dramatic break with
something, though in retrospect it is more difficult to see what the break was with than it
seemed at the time it was published. Positivism is the usual candidate for the thing that
it broke with, but the book was published in the most positivist of book series, and was
seen as unproblematic by that most positivist of readers, Rudolph Carnap. The basic
framework of the book, the idea of conceptual revolutions, was taken over from Kuhns
mentor and one of the crucial figures in the pre-history of science studies, James Bryant
Conant. Conant had employed Kuhn in the Harvard course he had designed to teach nonscience undergraduates what science was, from the point of view of the working scientist
struggling with scientific problems, rather than teach them chemical and physical formulas. Much of the descriptive account of the experience of science in Kuhns book was
taken over from Michael Polanyi (1958), whose notion of tacit knowledge, among other
things, made its way into the concept of paradigm.
Corresponding author:
Stephen Turner, Department of Philosophy FAO 226, University of South Florida, Tampa, FL 33620, USA.
Email: [email protected].
475
Turner
Before Kuhn
What made Kuhn revolutionary, and at the same time retrograde, was something not to
be found explicitly in these writers, except in a very attenuated way in Carnaps internal
external distinction and conventionalism: the kind of radical relativism about the foundations of science that Kuhn built into his notion of paradigm. This too had a source, and it
was a source threaded through the 20th century in various guises, including one that had
a special influence at Harvard itself through Alfred North Whitehead. Also at Harvard,
the physiologist/chemist/philosopher/sociologist Lawrence J. Henderson promoted the
idea of conceptual schemes (1970 [194142]); and Carnap, who spent time at Harvard
in the late 1930s, developed an influential analysis of the internalexternal distinction
that served to translate these issues into linguistic terms, but also to conceal the problem
of relativism by treating external questions as problems insoluble by the kind of formal
analysis that could be done of the internal logic of a scientific theory (Carnap, 1950).
Conant, like Polanyi, was a physical chemist who had lived through the quantum
revolution: for him the transformation of conceptual schemes was an existential fact. But
it was a fact that had implications for the nature of scientific knowledge, and this was
what transfixed them. Both Conant and Polanyi were concerned with the specificity of
scientific knowledge, and with how scientists thought, both in relation to their subject
matter and other scientists. Polanyi in particular was fascinated with the actual psychology of scientific thinking, awareness, and the ways in which discovery happened.
This was very much in tension with both the philosophy and sociology of science of
the time. As Stephen Cole (2004: 837842; esp. 839840) has shrewdly observed, Robert
K. Mertons interest in science was with science as a whole, not with the specifics of this
or that discovery. The philosophy of science had inherited a collection of strongly held
taboos against psychologism, a bogeymen invented by philosophers such as Husserl,
Schlick, and Frege (cf. Kusch, 1995), and so concerned itself with the logical structure
of theories and the rational reconstruction of this structure, and of confirmation, rather
than what was dismissed as the context of discovery. One may think of this as a step in
the de-naturalization of epistemology. But it was to get worse.
Positivism of the Vienna variety was created as a response to a certain kind of antirelativistic neo-Kantianism, which it replaced with the idea that parts of the framework of
physics, namely the mathematical structure, were relative (Howard, 1990: 369373;
Friedman, 1999: 7186, esp. 81). The basic thought that positivism disposed of was the idea
that there was a conceptual structure uniquely valid for and presupposed by any field of science. The innovation of logical positivism was to recognize that one could get the same
scientific results, the same predictions, with different presuppositions, which implied that
these presuppositions were not properly part of science, or even part of the realm of the
factually true. They were at best conventions or something like it: necessary in the sense
that you couldnt do the prediction without some machinery like this, but not uniquely necessary, because one could do the same predictions with different conventions.
This reasoning, however, inadvertently transformed the way one could think about the
history of science. The old neo-Kantian view was that physics had a (unique) conceptual
order that it presupposed and that could be reconstructed by philosophical analysis. The
new view was that the history of science was the history of successive presuppositional
476
schemes. The fact that these schemes could be further reconstructed in different ways to
produce the same predictions was a curiosity beside the historical point: that different
thinkers in fact operated with different presuppositions.
477
Turner
Actor-network theory
Science in Action (Latour, 1987) was a self-conscious goodbye to all that. Latour explicitly rejected as bogus the conflict between the competing explanations of science. This
was his response to the science wars: to be freed from all these debates about rationality, relativism, culture, and so on (p. 213). Consequently he called for a moratorium on cognitive explanations of science and technology (p. 91) at the same time as he
rejected social constructionism. Actor-network theory (ANT) was the radical substitute.
The actors were not actors, however, but actants. Latour eliminated the knower, even
the intending agent, by flattening agency to the point that everything had it, including
physical objects, all of which were actants and potential network members.
478
479
Turner
trained as a psychologist, why science had to stop cold when it came to explaining true
scientific belief (Bloor, 1981; Laudan, 1981). The battle over the limits of naturalism and
the legitimacy of normativism as an element of explanation of whether invoking a
normative notion of reason or truth actually explains a scientific belief was the right
battle, but it was subverted and confused by the presence of unreal normative transcendental notions, such as shared presuppositions.
The hard work, from which these lengthy episodes have been a diversion, is to epistemologize the social, to understand the elements of belief and belief formation, which
inevitably depend on our knowledge of others and of institutional routines, and to do
so in a naturalistic way, avoiding explanatory short-cuts, such as the appeal to transcendental non-facts of the sort that Kuhn added to Conant and infest social constructionism. And this will force us to ask the politically uncomfortable questions we find
so difficult, questions about when to believe experts, about whether and when the
consensus formation processes of science can be relied on, and to face our prejudices
with hard questions.
References
Barnes B and Bloor D (1982) Relativism, rationalism, and the sociology of knowledge. In: Hollis
M and Lukes S (eds) Rationality and Relativism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2147.
Bloor D (1981) The strengths of the strong programme in the sociology of knowledge. Philosophy
of the Social Sciences 11(2): 199213.
Carnap R (1950) Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4:
2040.
Cole S (2004) Mertons contribution to the sociology of science. Social Studies of Science 34(6):
829844.
Collins H (2010) Tacit & Explicit Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Friedman M (1999) Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Henderson LJ (1970 [194142]) Sociology 23 lectures, 194142. In: Barber B (ed.) L.J. Henderson
on the Social System. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 57148.
Howard D (1990) Einstein and Duhem. Synthese 83: 363384.
Kitcher P (2003) Science, Truth, and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kuhn T (1996 [1962]) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd edn. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Kusch M (1995) Psychologism: A Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge. London
and New York: Routledge.
Latour B (1987) Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Latour B (1988) The politics of explanation: An alternative. In: Woolgar S (ed.) Knowledge and
Reflexivity. London: Sage, 155176.
Latour B and Lpinay VA (2009) The Science of Passionate Interests: An Introduction to Gabriel
Tardes Economic Anthropology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Laudan L (1981) The pseudo-science of science? Philosophy of the Social Sciences 11(2): 173198.
Pickering A (1984) Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press; Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Polanyi M (1958) Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
480
Biographical note
Stephen Turner is Graduate Research Professor of Philosophy at the University of South Florida,
Tampa. His most recent book is Explaining the Normative (Polity Press, 2010). His most recent
writings on relativism include Davidsons Normativity in Dialogues with with Davidson, Jeff
Malpas, ed. (MIT Press, 2011).