This document discusses the key concepts of arguments in logic. It defines an argument as a set of premises intended to establish the truth of a conclusion. Premises support the conclusion but the conclusion can appear anywhere - at the beginning, middle or end. Arguments are either deductive, where the premises guarantee the truth of the conclusion, or inductive, where the premises make the conclusion probable but not certain. The document distinguishes between an argument's validity, where the premises cannot be true without the conclusion also being true, and its soundness, which requires the argument to be both valid and have true premises.
Download as DOC, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
64 views
Logic 1
This document discusses the key concepts of arguments in logic. It defines an argument as a set of premises intended to establish the truth of a conclusion. Premises support the conclusion but the conclusion can appear anywhere - at the beginning, middle or end. Arguments are either deductive, where the premises guarantee the truth of the conclusion, or inductive, where the premises make the conclusion probable but not certain. The document distinguishes between an argument's validity, where the premises cannot be true without the conclusion also being true, and its soundness, which requires the argument to be both valid and have true premises.
Lecture 1: Arguments In studying logic, the notion of argument is central. An argument is a set of thoughts or sentences which are intended to establish the truth of some specific conclusion. Arguments are important in all sorts of different contexts; they are especially important in philosophy.
Premises and Conclusions
Its crucial to distinguish the conclusion of an argument from its premises: the premises of an argument are the thoughts or sentences which are intended to establish the truth of the conclusion. Example: If its raining you need an umbrella. Its raining. Therefore you need an umbrella. Here, the first two sentences are intended to establish the truth of the third: the first two sentences are the premises and the third is the conclusion. Example: You need an umbrella. For its raining. And if its raining, you need an umbrella. Here the second and third sentences are intended to establish the truth of the first: the second and third sentences are the premises, and the first is the conclusion. Example: If its raining you need an umbrella. So you need an umbrella. Because its raining. Here the first and third sentences are intended to establish the truth of the second: the first and third sentences are the premises, and the second is the conclusion. General moral: The conclusion of an argument doesnt always come at the end: it may come at the beginning, or in the middle. Different words or phrases can be used to mark off the conclusion from the premises.
Deductive and Inductive Arguments
Its also important to distinguish between two different types of arguments: deductive and inductive. A deductive argument is one thats intended to have this feature: if its premises are true, then its conclusion has to be true as well. With a good deductive argument, there is no possibility that its premises are true while its conclusion is false. Not all good arguments are deductive. Some arguments, though good, leave at least some possibility that while their premises are true, their conclusion is false. Example: You have tossed 1000 consecutive heads. So your coin is not fair. This argument seems good: it would be quite reasonable to accept its conclusion on the basis of its premise. Nevertheless, there remains a chance (albeit very small) that its premise is true while its conclusion is false. This means that it does not count as a good deductive argument. Arguments of this kind are called inductive.
In logic, its absolutely vital to appreciate the distinction between validity and soundness. Validity: An argument is valid if (and only if) theres no possibility that its premises are true while its conclusion is false. Soundness: An argument is sound if (and only if) it is valid and has true premises. A good way to grasp the distinction between validity and soundness is to think of arguments that are valid but not sound. Example: We are in Paris. If we are in Paris, then we are in France. So we are in France. This argument is valid: there is no way that its premises can be true while its conclusion is false. But the argument is not sound: its second premise is true, but its first premise is false. Example: My name is either Fred or Bob. My name is not Fred. So my name is Bob. This argument is valid: there is no way that its premises can be true while its conclusion is false. But the argument is not sound: though its second premise is true, its first premise is false. Compare these with two other arguments which are both valid and sound: Example: We are in London. If we are in London, then we are in England. So we are in England. Example: My name is either Fred or Charlie. My name is not Fred. So my name is Charlie. These arguments are both valid: there is no way that their premises can be true while their conclusion is false. In addition, both arguments are sound: their premises are true. Reading Tomassi, P. Logic. Chapter 1, Parts I III. Exercises Exercise 1.1, Questions 1- 4 (in the Tomassi book).