0% found this document useful (0 votes)
60 views6 pages

Bo de Bertrand

Erdos provided an elementary proof of Bertrand's postulate in 1932 using properties of the middle binomial coefficient. The proof shows that if there is no prime between n and 2n, then an upper bound on the middle binomial coefficient is smaller than its known lower bound, unless n is small. For large n, this leads to a contradiction, proving Bertrand's postulate. The proof relies on two key lemmas - that each prime factor of the binomial coefficient contributes at most 2n to its value, and that the product of primes up to x is at most 4x/x.

Uploaded by

o0ohung4499o0o
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
60 views6 pages

Bo de Bertrand

Erdos provided an elementary proof of Bertrand's postulate in 1932 using properties of the middle binomial coefficient. The proof shows that if there is no prime between n and 2n, then an upper bound on the middle binomial coefficient is smaller than its known lower bound, unless n is small. For large n, this leads to a contradiction, proving Bertrand's postulate. The proof relies on two key lemmas - that each prime factor of the binomial coefficient contributes at most 2n to its value, and that the product of primes up to x is at most 4x/x.

Uploaded by

o0ohung4499o0o
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 6

Erd oss proof of Bertrands postulate

David Galvin

April 21, 2006


Abstract
In 1845 Bertrand postulated that there is always a prime between n and 2n, and he
veried this for n < 3, 000, 000. Tchebychev gave an analytic proof of the postulate
in 1850. In 1932, in his rst paper, Erd os gave a beautiful elementary proof using
nothing more than a feweasily veried facts about the middle binomial coefcient. We
describe Erd oss proof and make a few additional comments, including a discussion of
how the two main lemmas used in the proof very quickly give an approximate prime
number theorem. We also describe a result of Greeneld and Greeneld that links
Bertrands postulate to the statement that {1, . . . , 2n} can always be decomposed into
n pairs such that the sum of each pair is a prime.
1 Introduction
Write (x) for the number of primes less than or equal to x. The Prime Number Theorem
(PNT), rst proved by Hadamard [4] and de la Vall ee-Poussin [7] in 1896, is the statement
that
(x)
x
ln x
as x . (1)
A consequence of the PNT is that
> 0 n() > 0 : n > n() p prime, n < p (1 + )n. (2)
Indeed, by (1) we have
((1 + )n) (n)
(1 + )n
ln(1 + )n

n
ln n
as n .
Using a more rened version of the PNT with an error estimate, we may prove the following
theorem.
Theorem 1.1 For all n > 0 there is a prime p such that n < p 2n.

Dept of Mathematics, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA 19104; [email protected].


1
This is Bertrands postulate, conjectured in the 1845, veried by Bertrand for all N <
3 000 000, and rst proved by Tchebychev in 1850. (See [5, p. 25] for a discussion of the
original references).
In his rst paper Erd os [2] gave a beautiful elementary proof of Bertrands postulate
which uses nothing more than some easily veried facts about the middle binomial coef-
cient
_
2n
n
_
. We describe this proof in Section 2 and present some comments, conjectures and
a consequence in Section 3. One consequence is the following lovely theorem of Greeneld
and Greeneld [3].
Theorem 1.2 For n > 0, the set {1, . . . , 2n} can be partitioned into pairs
{a
1
, b
1
}, . . . , {a
n
, b
n
}
such that for each 1 i n, a
i
+ b
i
is a prime.
Another is an approximate version of (1).
Theorem 1.3 There are constants c, C > 0 such that for all x
c ln x
x
(x)
C ln x
x
.
2 Erd oss proof
We consider the middle binomial coefcient
_
2n
n
_
= (2n)!/(n!)
2
. An easy lower bound is
_
2n
n
_

4
n
2n + 1
. (3)
Indeed,
_
2n
n
_
is the largest term in the 2n+1-term sum

2n
i=0
_
2n
n
_
= (1+1)
2n
= 4
n
. Erd oss
proof proceeds by showing that if there is no prime p with n < p 2n then we can put
an upper bound on
_
2n
n
_
that is smaller than 4
n
/(2n + 1) unless n is small. This veries
Bertrands postulate for all sufciently large n, and we deal with small n by hand.
For a prime p and an integer n we dene o
p
(n) to be the largest exponent of p that
divides n. Note that o
p
(ab) = o
p
(a) + o
p
(b) and o
p
(a/b) = o
p
(a) o
p
(n). The heart of the
whole proof is the following simple observation.
If
2
3
n < p n then o
p
__
2n
n
__
= 0 (i.e., p |
_
2n
n
_
). (4)
Indeed, for such a p
o
p
__
2n
n
__
= o
p
((2n)!) 2o
p
(n!) = 2 2.1 = 0.
So if n is such that there is no prime p with n < p 2n, then all of the prime factors of
_
2n
n
_
lie between 2 and 2n/3. We will show that each of these factors appears only to a small
exponent, forcing
_
2n
n
_
to be small. The following is the claim we need in this direction.
2
Claim 2.1 If p|
_
2n
n
_
then
p
o
p((
2n
n
))
2n.
Proof: Let r(p) be such that p
r(p)
2n < p
r(p)+1
. We have
o
p
__
2n
n
__
= o
p
((2n)!) 2o
p
(n!)
=
r(p)

i=1
_
2n
p
i
_
2
r(p)

i=1
_
n
p
i
_
=
r(p)

i=1
__
2n
p
i
_
2
_
n
p
i
__
r(p), (5)
and so
p
o
p((
2n
n
))
p
r(p)
2n.
In (5) we use the easily veried fact that for integers a and b, 0 [2a/b] 2[a/b] 1. 2
Before writing down the estimates that upper bound
_
2n
n
_
, we need one more simple
result.
Claim 2.2 n

pn
p 4
n
(where the product is over primes).
Proof: We proceed by induction on n. For small values of n, the claim is easily veried.
For larger even n, we have

pn
p =

pn1
p 4
n1
4
n
,
the equality following from the fact that n is even an so not a prime and the rst inequality
following from the inductive hypothesis. For larger odd n, say n = 2m + 1, we have

pn
p =

pm+1
p

m+2p2m+1
p
4
m+1
_
2m + 1
m
_
(6)
4
m+1
2
2m
(7)
= 4
2m+1
= 4
n
.
In (6) we use the induction hypothesis to bound

pm+1
p and we bound

m+2p2m+1
p
by observing that all primes between m + 2 and 2m + 1 divide
_
2m+1
m
_
. In (7) we bound
3
_
2m+1
m
_
2
2m
by noting that

2m+1
i=0
_
2m+1
i
_
= 2
2m+1
and
_
2m+1
m
_
=
_
2m+1
m+1
_
and so the
contribution to the sum from
_
2m+1
m
_
is at most 2
2m
. 2
We are now ready to prove Bertrands postulate. Let n be such that there is no prime p
with n < p 2n. Then we have
_
2n
n
_
(2n)

2n

2n<p2n/3
p (8)
(2n)

2n

p2n/3
p
(2n)

2n
4
2n/3
. (9)
The main point is (8). We have rst used the simple fact that
_
2n
n
_
has at most

2n prime
factors that are smaller than

2n, and, by Claim 2.1, each of these prime factors contributes


at most 2n to
_
2n
n
_
; this accounts for the factor (2n)

2n
. Next, we have used that by hy-
pothesis and by (4) all of the prime factors p of
_
2n
n
_
satisfy p 2n/3, and the fact that
each such p with p >

2n appears in
_
2n
n
_
with exponent 1 (this is again by Claim 2.1);
these two observations together account for the factor

2n<p2n/3
p. In (9) we have used
Claim 2.2.
Combining (9) with (3) we obtain the inequality
4
n
2n + 1
(2n)

2n
4
2n/3
. (10)
This inequality can hold only for small values of n. Indeed, for any > 0 the left-hand
side of (10) grows faster than (4 )
n
whereas the right-hand side grows more slowly than
(4
2/3
+ )
n
. We may check that in fact (10) fails for all n 468 (Maple calculation),
verifying Bertrands postulate for all n in this range. To verify Bertrands postulate for all
n < 468, it sufces to check that
2, 3, 5, 7, 13, 23, 43, 83, 163, 317, 631. (11)
is a sequence of primes, each term of which is less than twice the term preceding it; it
follows that every interval {n + 1, . . . , 2n} with n < 486 contains one of these 11 primes.
This concludes the proof of Theorem 1.1.
(If a Maple calculation is not satisfactory, it is easy to check that (10) reduces to n/3
log
2
(2n + 1) +

2nlog
2
2n. The left hand side of this inequality is increasing faster than
the right, and the inequality is easily seen to fail for n = 2
10
= 1024, so to complete the
proof in this case we need only add the prime 1259 to the list in (11)).
3 Comments, conjectures and consequences
A stronger result than (2) is known (due to Lou and Yao [6]):
> 0 n() > 0 : n > n() p prime, n < p n + n
1
2
+
1
22
+
.
4
The Riemann hypothesis would imply
> 0 n() > 0 : n > n() p prime, n < p n + n
1
2
+
.
There is a very strong conjecture of Cram er [1] that would imply
> 0 n
0
> 0 : n > n
0
p prime, n < p n + (1 + ) ln
2
n.
And here is a very lovely open question much in the spirit of Bertrands postulate.
Question 3.1 Is it true that for all n > 1, there is always a prime p with n
2
< p < (n+1)
2
?
As mentioned in the introduction, a consequence of Bertrands postulate is the appeal-
ing Theorem 1.2. We give the proof here.
Proof of Theorem 1.2: We proceed by induction on n. For n = 1 the result is trivial. For
n > 1, let p be a prime satisfying 2n < p 4n. Since 4n is not prime we have p = 2n+m
for 1 m < 2k. Pair 2n with m, 2n1 with m+1, and continue up to n+k with n+k
(this last a valid pair since m is odd). This deals with all of the numbers in {m, . . . , 2n};
the inductive hypothesis deals with {1, . . . , m 1} (again since m is odd). 2
Finally, we turn to the proof of Theorem 1.3. The upper bound will follow from Claim
2.2 while the lower bound will follow from Claim 2.1.
Proof of Theorem 1.3: For the lower bound on (x) choose n such that
_
2n
n
_
x <
_
2n + 2
n + 1
_
.
For sufciently large n we have ln
_
2n
n
_
> n (from (3)) and for all n we have
_
2n
n
_
/
_
2n+2
n+1
_

1/4 and so
(x) ln x
x


__
2n
n
__
ln
_
2n
n
_
_
2n+2
n+1
_
n
__
2n
n
__
4
_
2n
n
_ (12)
We lower bound the number of primes at most
_
2n
n
_
by counting those which divide
_
2n
n
_
.
By Claim 2.1 each such prime contributes at most 2n to
_
2n
n
_
and so
__
2n
n
__

_
2n
n
_
/2n.
Combining this with (12) we obtain (for sufciently large x)
(x)
x
8 ln x
.
For the upper bound we use Claim 2.2 to get (for x 4)
4
x

px
p

x
(x)(x/2)
and so
(x)
4x ln 2
log x
+ (x/2).
5
Repeating this procedure log
2
x times we reach (for sufciently large x)
(x)
8x ln 2
log x
+ (2)

9x ln 2
log x
.
2
References
[1] Cram er, H., On the Order of Magnitude of the Difference Between Consecutive Prime
Numbers, Acta Arith. 2 (1936) 2346. 1936.
[2] Erd os, P., Beweis eines Satzes von Tschebyschef, Acta Sci. Math. (Szeged) 5 (1930
1932), 194198.
[3] Greeneld, L. and Greeneld, S., Some problems of combinatorial number theory
related to Bertrands postulate, J. Integer Seq. 1 (1998), Article 98.1.2.
[4] Hadamard, J., Sur la distribution des z eros de la fonction (s) et ses cons equences
arithm etiques, Bull. Soc. math. France 24 (1896), 199220.
[5] Havil, J., Gamma: Exploring Eulers Constant, Princeton University Press (2003).
[6] Lou, S. and Yau, Q., A Chebyshevs Type of Prime Number Theorem in a Short
Interval (II), Hardy-Ramanujan J. 15 (1992), 133.
[7] Poussin, C. de la Vall ee, Recherces analytiques sur la th eorie des nombres premiers,
Ann. Soc. Sci. Bruxells (1897).
6

You might also like