iiillliiiiiliiiilli'
^i
tiumiA^:'uu'f.)i.iur,fU\m
^^^^^^^^^^^^B
^^^^R^fllHRl^^^^^
iii
ill
MOVEMENTS OF THOUGHT
IN
THE
NINETEENTH CENTURY
THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS
CHICAGO, ILLINOIS
THE BAKER & TAYLOR COMPANY
NEW YORK
THE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
LONDON
THE MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA
TOKYO, OSAKA, KYOTO, FUKUOKA, SENDAI
THE COMMERCIAL PRESS, LIMITED
SHANGHAI
MOVEMENTS OF THOUGHT
IN
THE
NINETEENTH CENTURY
GEORGE
H.
MEAD
Late Professor of Philosophy, The University of Chicago
EDITED BY
MERRITT
H.
MOORE
Professor of Philosophy
Knox
College
THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS
CHICAGO ILLINOIS
COPYRIGHT 1936 BY THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. PUBLISHED APRIL I936
SECOND IMPRESSION NOVEMBER I938
COMPOSED AND PRINTED BY THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS
CHICAGO, ILLINOIS, U.S.A.
C^
PREFATORY NOTE
^S
/-\
-^
-^
YET,
comparatively
has been done by
little
way
of
synthetic studies of nineteenth-century thought as a
This situation
whole.
is
aggravated in that what
is
available for the use of the student, or other interested persons,
is
of relatively
little
value because of lack of time, lack of train-
ing, or other reasons.
To
date, the
most extensive
single
work
on this period is /IVTerz^four- volume work History of European
Thought in the Nvneieenth Century. But of this work the length
alone makes its widespread use unlikely, and in some instances
unfeasible, except for specific problems considered apart from
their wider significance. Added to this is the difficult nature of
the text. It is so detailed, so complex, as of course the thought
of the century was, that the uninitiated are apt to find it more
baffling than helpful. On the other hand, some work of a more
popular nature has been done, but largely by French and Ger-
man
writers.
Much
of this material
tively unavailable to a large
make
is
untranslated, and so rela-
number
of persons
who would
Again, not a small part of the bibliography on the nineteenth century relates to works on particular
otherwise
use of
it.
phases of the thought of the period. Among these are Royce's
The Spirit of Modern Philosophy^ Levy-Bruhl's excellent work
on the History of Modern Philosophy in France^ and Ruggiero's
European Liberalism. These are limited in scope.
Thus Professor Mead's lectures on the "Movements of
Thought in the Nineteenth Century" are peculiarly apt, for a
number of reasons. They are inclusive. Even a brief perusal of
the Table of Contents
is
sufficient to indicate the catholicity of
I think it may truly be said that few significant
thought developments have been neglected. The lectures are also
relatively simple. Being designed, as they were, for undergradu-
their scope.
ate students in the University of Chicago, they are presented
[
v1
320G31
PREFATORY NOTE
from a point of view which such students can readily grasp. This
a great boon to the general reader who wishes a picture of
the thought of the century as a whole. Again, their development does not go into such detail as to hide general tendencies. Finally, Mr. Mead's penchant for turning old problems
around in such a way as to bring new hght on them keeps his
is
These factors all lead to the
cumulative value which these lectures have as one goes through
them. One cannot read them with any care without having a
real sense of what went on in the century immediately before
our own.
Of course, when these lectures were given, Mr. Mead had
not designed them for publication. They are classroom lecbut of an exceptures, reported in the form of student notes
tionally complete and exact nature. They have the value and
deficiencies of the purpose for which they were intended. In this
case, however, the former completely outweigh the latter. Perhaps, had Mr. Mead himself prepared them for publication,
they might have been presented in a somewhat different form.
It is, I think, unHkely that he would have made any significant
changes the material is too good as it stands. These lectures
make up a course that was presented numerous times. In this
process they were subject to constant growth of insight and consequent revision. Thus, it is no idle statement to say that they
represent their author's mature views. As the reader of them in
their present form will discover for himself, these views are
worthy of conscientious study.
At least in part, the publication of this volume grows out of
Mr. Mead's untimely death. He had, during his life, been
peculiarly unwilling to soHdify his thought in the form of published works. It seemed regrettable, however, that a mind of
such penetration, such power, one that had such an influence
on colleagues, students, and friends, should be left without
record for posterity. Thus, under the instigation of his son. Dr.
Henry Mead, and his daughter-in-law. Dr. Irene Tufts Mead,
plans were made to collect available material suitable for publilectures from being repetitious.
PREFATORY NOTE
was undertaken in conjunction with the Drs.
Mead and, at their request, by Professor Arthur E. Murphy. At
his suggestion I was asked to co-operate with the plan through
cation. This
the editing of notes on the nineteenth century.
With the exception
of the second half of the chapter on Berg-
son, the material of the
book
is
prepared for Mr. Alvin Carus.
taken from stenographic notes
It is one of a number of sets
of such notes taken for him
in various courses offered by Mr.
Mead. No one could have asked for better material with which
to work. Changes of content were almost wholly unnecessary.
The bulk of the problem was one of mechanical rearrangement
of material into chapters. This presented some difficulty. Mr.
Mead had a very effective teaching habit of advancing cyclically
through his subject matter. The result was a good deal of repetition. But each time he came back to a problem it was set in
a slightly new frame. In editing the material, there has been
a question as to how far this repetition should be retained and
to what extent the notes should be condensed and carried along
without backtracking. Both methods have been used, I trust
with some degree of success.
Half of the material
for chapter xiv
on Henri Bergson
is
from
notes of Mr. George A. Pappas. These were not stenographic,
and the
difficulty in regard to their use
necessary to
fill
them out,
to
was
increased. It
was
complete unfinished sentences,
and, in some cases, to guess at the meaning and significance
This led to a dual difficulty. On the one
wished to be true to Mr. Mead's point of view. At the
same time I had to remember that it was Bergson who was being
of brief notations.
hand,
was necessary to avoid obvious misrepreI trust I have had reasonable success
in meeting these demands. In so far as possible, I have tried to
phrase this material as Mr. Mead would have.
interpreted and that
it
sentations of his position.
The
character of these notes very aptly brings us to a discus-
we have utilized
them in this volume and in the preservation of other of Mr.
Mead's material. The problem hardly arises in connection with
sion of the value of student notes in general as
fviil
PREFATORY NOTE
Mr. Murphy's preparation of the Carus Lectures. These lectures were given with the intention of expansion and later pubHcation. This Mr. Mead's untimely death precluded, and it was
necessary that the task be completed by another. No such
situation existed in thecaseof the series of which this is a part. It
is true that after his death great quantities of notes and papers
in various stages of completion were found among Mr. Mead's
effects. There was no indication that any of them were being
arranged for publication, however. What justification is there,
then, for our having undertaken their preservation in this form,
other than that of sentimentaHty?
My answer to that question is dual. On the one hand, there
is the matter of historical precedent. It is a fact more or less
widely known among students of philosophic works that, but
for the utilization of student notes and other material prepared
primarily for classroom purposes, many of our philosophical
would not
This is the case specifically with at least
part of our collections of the works of Epictetus, Aristotle, Leibnitz, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel. Certainly, then, to utilize such
classics
notes
exist.
not to exceed the bounds of decorum. Furthermore,
is
it
much, or any, of the subject matter gathered from
the material of the writers mentioned above had the great
virtue of being stenographic. With the single exception referred
to, all the notes utilized in the preparation of this volume, and
most, if not all, that composing the contents of the others of this
series, may be regarded as verbatim recordings of Mr. Mead's
is
doubtful
lectures.
if
The amount
of error in such transcription
slight, consisting primarily in
and
so on,
rect. I
think
far as this
The
which a
little
we may
ground
is
is
relatively
such details as misspelled names,
care enables one to detect and to cor-
ignore any criticism of our procedure, so
concerned.
other justification for the preservation of the material in
found in its worth as throwing light on
the problems with which it deals. Here our evaluation cannot
be so objective. In this connection I can simply repeat what I
have said earher in this Preface. It is a fact that Mr. Mead did
published form
is
to be
PREFATORY NOTE
not specifically intend the publication of this material as
stands. It
was the consensus of opinion among
it
his students
now
and
his colleagues that it should be published. In this opinion his
family and friends concurred. This is, I concede, not an unimpeachable argument for proceeding with their publication. It
certainly gives an initial probability to the
contain material which
and
judgment that they
continue to be, of value to
students of philosophic problems. The nature and source of the
is,
will
contents has been specifically indicated. Having this
mind,
There is
no question about this being the work of an original mind. We
might wish Mr. Mead himself had put it in final form. That
the reader
wish
is
must make
Even
vain.
in
his final evaluation for himself.
in its
present form, the material has that sug-
and interpretative value of which I have spoken above.
debt to Drs. Henry and Irene Mead and to Mr. Murphy
gestive
My
for considering
estimate.
If,
me
in
when
connection with this undertaking
first
great an admirer of Mr.
started on the work,
Mead
as were
dents and colleagues (both of which
be),
my rereading and
that. I
am
it
cannot
made me
Mr. Charles W. Morris, particularly
my disposal material that he gathered after he
for placing at
as
some others of his stuwas my good fortune to
re-working of these lectures has
also grateful to
was not
took
up the work when Mr. Murphy left the University of Chicago,
and for valuable assistance and corrections in the preparation
of the manuscript.
I
wish also to acknowledge
my
debt to
my
wife and to Miss
Edna Lorraine Evans for assistance in preparing the manuscript. The preparation of the final typewritten copy was the
work of Miss Lucille Hogan and Miss Gertrude Venable. The
Index
is
the
To my
work of Mr. Vincent Tomas.
and colleague. Dr. L. W. Elder,
friend
wish to ex-
press an especial indebtedness.
Merritt Hadden Moore
Knox College
November
i,
1933
IX
INTRODUCTION
WHILE
would certainly be an oversimplification, it
would not be a misstatement to say the thesis which
underlies these lectures, and which Mr. Mead is most
it
interested in bringing
it s
demand
home
for freedo m,
to his reader
with
its
demand
is this:
for
t he
Science, with
substi tution o f
rational authority for _the_arbitrarv authority whi^h characte r-
ized the rne dieval period, Ts~the outstan dTH g'lact not simpl y of
tlie"^ nineteenth
century hut o f
ffipkpnaj<;;an^f (nr
^
itself.
mo dem
all
tho ught since, and including
scicncc brought in the Renaissance
If one gets the full import of
what
is
meant by
this state-
have discovered the key through which entry
may be made into the new approaches which Mr. Mead brings
to the study of the movements of thought and also to his
original, and sometimes abstruse, contributions to philosophic
thought. One finds a continuous flow of such statements as this:
Science is the surest knowledge we have. A striking feature of
his analysis of social movements is his analogy between procedure in these fields and in what we regard as the sciences
properly so-called. For example the doctrines of Hobbes, Locke,
and Rousseau are dealt with as alternative hypotheses in the
effort to give a scientific theory of the state. In each case
departure is made from laws thought to be universal. To these,
ment, one
will
exceptions are found. In the light of these exceptions
make
a modification of our hypotheses.
The
we must
genius of the re-
however, that, instead of waiting to have the
exceptional instance turn up, he bends his whole energy to
ferreting out particular cases for an explanation of which our
search thinker
is,
accepted theory
is
inadequate.
ment of Mr. Mead's
ments
in the
swift review of the develop-
move-
analysis of the correlation of thought
century with which our immediate study
is
cerned will indicate that he neatly exemplifies his thesis.
con-
INTRODUCTION
I
Since
have indicated the central place of research science
Mr. Mead's thought, the reader
will
not be surprised
if I
in
point
out that in this particular set of lectures the development centers around the problem of methodology. A traditional story
about Mr. Mead's courses that was handed down from one gen-
was
any particular
class was lucky, it might have the good fortune of having him
finally get through to contemporary problems, the implication
clearly being that he seldom did so. Needless to say, that was an
exaggeration. However, his analysis of movements in the nineteenth century does begin with medieval thought, and it might
quite as well have gone back to Aristotle, for it begins with a
statement of the substance-attribute relation which was the
eration of students to another at the University of Chicago
that he always went back to Aristotle and,
if
foundation of Aristotelian science. This concept plays the dual
background against which the nineteenth-century
role of a
on the subject-object
relation, and as the ground of serious problems which serve as
the soil in which the thought of the last century took root and
found nourishment.
The rationalism which colors European thought since 1600,
and which pervades our contemporary scientific period through
the assumptions of the knowability of nature, of the uniformity
metaphysics
is
developed, founded, as
it is,
of nature, and, consequently of the universality of natural laws,
is
rooted in medieval theology. Picturing the universe as carry-
ing out the purposes of a divine, rational being, any irrational
element was excluded automatically, since
intelligent but
From
had the power to make
this source
come
God
not only was
his intelligence effective.
the rationalistic characteristics of
ern science. Galileo, Copernicus, Kepler, and
Newton,
to
modmen-
mathematics to the universe with an
Mathematics, the most rational of our
tion only four, applied
almost naive trust.
would fit a rational world.
This worked in two directions. On the one hand
disciplines,
it
led to a
rather remarkable success in the study of physical processes.
\
xii
On
INTRODUCTION
the other hand it led to the b ifurcation of nature. The church
was unconcerned with the physical world. This world was merely the stage on which the drama of man's salvation was played.
And the play was the thing. The scientist could muddle around
with the material to his heart's content so long as his theories
did not trespass on the domain of the soul, did not carry over
into the realm o f value s. Methodologically, Galileo and his suc-
They
cessors found values were irrelevant to their study.
ig-
nored them as subjective. Under the double impulsion referred
to above, values were taken from the world and made subjective, put into men/sjieads. This attitude, which made the physi-
world rational and mathematical, but which left the realm of
man's moral life and freedom, as attributes of
soul stuff, was made into a philsophy by Descartes. But what
had been started was not to be so easily stopped. Carrying the
logic of the situation through to its inexorable conclusion, the
cal
values, including
empiricist reduced the attributes of the physical world to the
same status that Descartes had reduced values. Primary, as well
as secondary, qualities became attributes not of physical but of
spiritual substance. Ending with the annihilating skepticism
of Hume, the rational universe of science, with its universal and
necessary principles, and the soul, the bearer
butes,
became nothing more than the habitual
now
of
all attri-
association of cer-
The substance of the
soul having been
wiped out, the attributes no longer had any ground to adhere to.
To this problem, Immanuel Kant proposed an answer, but
it did not take the form of a reinstatement of substances. The
basis for the universality and necessity required by a rational
science is found in the mind itself. Man, the subject hav ijTig_certain ideas of a perceiver.
tain experience, not a substance bearing certain attributes, im-
poses~on his experiences certain forms which
make them
ra-
tional. True, Kant limited the application of these forms to
phenomena and was himself a skeptic, as far as the possibility
of knowledge of the noumena was concerned. We can
indeed,
our practical, active needs require that we must postulate certain things of the realm which lies behind the experienced. The
INTRODUCTION
formal character of phenomenal knowledge saved science,
on the basis of the forms of the mind,
it
was again
for,
possible to
defend the notion of universal and necessary truths as apphed to
experience. But such a science is phenomenalistic.
What of values? Kant felt impelled to make judgments in
this field as universal as our phenomenal judgments. It is this
aspect of his system that brings Mr. Mead to speak of him as
the philosopher of the revolution, a rather startling thing to
say of the staid and orderly
little
German
professor.
Let us go back a moment. When the scientist of the Renaissance carried over from the teachings of the church the notion
of a rational universe, he posited this as an assumption. He set
it up as a postulate for the guidance of his thinking. But he
came more and more to realize its postulational character.
When the church had set up this same concept, it had framed
it in the form of an arbitrary dogma. As such it was imposed
on the thought of the time.\The essence of the conflict which
is referred to in the general term 'the revolution" is the conflict
between the rational authority of the budding science and the
arbitrary authority of the church.
Apphed to society, this means simply that man tried to find
human nature itself the rational basis for the state and all
correlative human institutions. The older theory was that kings
served by divine right. The church was God's agent on earth.
in
Therefore the church could dictate on social and political mat-
was arbitrary, it rested on the church's relation to God. There was no basis for an appeal above that authority; it was arbitrary. The revolution challenged that authority and endeavored to substitute in place of it a rational authority; it attempted to show that the order of society flowed
from the rational nature of man, and from the rational character of society itself. This is the way out for Hobbes, Locke,
and Rousseau. Such a solution is impossible, however, unless it
can be shown that man's vohtions have a rational character.
ters.
Its authority
When Hume
seemingly destroyed the universal character of
such volitions by reducing to a set of habitual associations the
[xiv]
INTRODUCTION
rational substance in which such values
and volitions inhered,
he sounded the death knell of the revolution.
Man
could not
on the basis of his own rational nature because his so-called "universal and necessary" principles were
mere habits of thinking. Therefore, when Kant gave new foundation to the universality of scientific judgments, he saved rationalism; when he went on to give universality to man's volitions, to values, he saved the revolution. On the basis of Kant's
philosophy, a rational order or society became possible, and for
the arbitrary authority of the church or any other institution
could be substituted a rational authority based on human
build a rational state
nature.
In making
man
a sovereign, in
not only justifies a
movement
making him
a lawgiver,
Kant
that had gone before and was
rapidly coming to a head in the French Revolution, he also laid
the basis for future development.
With
revolution failed.
this failure
Historically, the political'
came
the endeavor to turn
the clock back, to recapture the past with
its
values, its order,
|
seeming stability. This attempt is romanticism. The failure
to build an actual society on the foundation of liberty, equality,
and fraternity led to a sense of defeat. To offset this, efforts
were made to transplant the past into the present.
In the field of thought this took the form of an attempt to
interpret the present in terms of what had gone before. Men
could not get back to the past because, for better or for worse,
they had lived through the experience of revolution. They
could not see the old order as it had been seen by those who
Hved in it. That made them aware of two things. On the one
hand, they became sensitized to themselves; they became selfconscious of their predicament. On the other hand, they saw
themselves as the outgrowth of what had gone before.
When they attempted to formulate this position in theoretical
terms, they found that Kant offered suitable concepts. In the
its
first
place,
Kant
"
re-established the objectivity of experience
through the nature of the
world.
Men had
lost their
self.
The
moorings
self legislates; it
makes
its
in the defeat of the revolu-
INTRODUCTION
tionary hope.
They no
longer
felt at
home
In their world.
They
were strangers to the present and sought solace in the old order
which, though arbitrary, was nevertheless rational. But lo
were one to follow Kant, he could have a rational world, for
the world is what we make it to be. We, as selves, determine
what the world is; it is the objectification of ourselves. In the
words of Schelling, man and nature are identical. Thus man is
as much at home with the universe as he is at home with himself, and since man is rational the universe will be also.
In the second place, with the emphasis on the self the notion
of activity, of process, of development and evolution, begins to
replace the earlier picture of static forms.
The
categories of sub-
and object replace those of substance and attribute as
the ultimate metaphysical concepts; the notions of change and
development replace those of static forms and universal types.
This latter is beyond Kant. We are now in the company of
the romanticists. Yet, it was Kant's emphasis on the role of
ject
the self as giving universality to experience that
velopment
possible.
disciple Fichte
That he
rejected
it
made
this de-
in the repudiation of his
simply indicates he failed to see the implications
own position. The problem posed by the skepticism of
Hume, and which Kant met with his critical philosophy, was
of his
answered by the romanticists through the identification of the
of knowledge with the self in the very process of knowing.
Nature and man are one. The self and the not-self, reason and
nature, are one whether regarded from the point of moral ex-
^,|-object
perience, as in Fichte, or of the aesthetic experience, as in
Schelling, or of the logical experience, as in Hegel.
Nature de-
velops through processes identical to those through which the
self develops.
/TRe transition from Kant to Hegel
is
a shift from an explana-
tion of the world in terms of static forms to one utilizing the
notion of an evolutionary process. For Hegel, the formal principles through the
ligible give
way
medium
of which experience becomes intel-
to a process
through which the forms them-
selves arise in the course of experience.
[xvi]
The
logic of the
new
INTReDUCTION
direction in thinking
is
one of a dynamic process rather than one
of fixed quantities. In other words, the Romantic ideaHsts were
doing within the field of philosophy what Lamarck and Darwin
were doing for biology.
The
science of the Renaissance
was based upon the problem
of the juxtaposition of simple physical particles as these were
brought together and torn apart as a result of motion. That
these combinations were manifest in groupings having the
characteristics of
common
objects distinguishable from one an-
other through their forms was entirely irrelevant to this earlier
statement.
The forms
of trees, stones, persons, are imposed on
the physical elements arbitrarily.
They have no
the interpretation of physical reality.
lution gives
is
What
significance in
the theory of evo-
a description of the process through which the
forms themselves
arise.
As Mr. Mead points
out, the title offone
one
of Darwin's books was The Origin of Species^ in other words,
5, the
origin of forms. The earlier science based on the ultimates
es of
matter and motion was saved, after Hume's destructive blast,
by Kant, who said that the form of objects is a projection in
experience of certain forms native to the mind itself. This leaves
us with the possibiHty of a phenomenal science but without any
clue as to the nature of things-in-themselves. The Romantic
and absolute
idealists
who
follow
Kant
find the nature of the
our experience. Darwin and
Lamarck carry the same general idea over into the problem of
thing-in-itself in the unfolding of
the appearance of forms in the biological world as a consequent
of a life-process which
is
time to time in such a
constant but which adapts
way
as to enable
changed conditions. Each of these men has
how
the adaptation occurs.
They
it
his
from
under
itself
to persist
own theory
as to
agree in the fact of a constant
with the particular forms of any given era dependent upon the conditions under which the life-process goes on at
any given time.
life-process
This same general notion receives further philosophic de-
velopment in vitalism, the most recent comprehensive statement of which is to be found in the position of the contemporary
i\
/
'
INTRODUCTION
French philosopher Henri Bergson. Thus the idea of evolution
gradually becomes completely general and bids fair to supplant
in all fields of thought both the Aristotelian science of fixed
forms and the early mechanical science of matter and motion;
it becomes a basic assumption applicable to every problem
from the development of the physical world to that of political
societies.
II
Turning
to another
phase of the development of ideas
the nineteenth century,
Mr. Mead
in
traces the correlation be-
tween problems in the field of social and economic phenomena
and other phases of scientific development. Here particularly we
find exemplified the author's abihty to restate the relations
among
the various factors of a
movement
in
such a
way
as
throw the whole problem into a new perspective. Rejecting
the common association of the Industrial Revolution with
the discovery of large deposits of easily available coal and
iron, coupled with the unaccountable increase of inventive
genius, Mr. Mead shows us these diverse roots of the movement: the expansion of markets, due, on the one hand to
the opening of new fields through the explorations that marked
the early modern period and continued through the movements
toward empire, and, on the other hand, to a sudden rather unaccountable increase in the population of Europe; changes in
the agricultural practices of England which released numerous
peasants from the land and made them available for labor of
other types; the appearance of factory towns as a result of takto
ing production out of the
home and
bringing the means of pro-
duction together in plants where the division of labor and the
application of increasingly adequate machinery
to turn out
goods
in sufficient quantities to
made
it
possible
meet the growing
demand.
Out of the new situation two expressions of the scientific
temper of the modern age arise. One of these is the development of an economic theory and a social theory capable of ac[
xviii
INTR@BUCTIN
counting for the new phenomena; the other, the appearance of
new scientific concepts which meet needs arising in the invention of
new
processes of production.
Adam
Smith and of Malthus we find the roots
from which the orthodox economic theory flowered. According
to the former, the market is a point of exchange of goods in
which each party to the exchange profits, in the sense that he
gives something he has but does not want for something the
other party to the bargain has and in turn does not want. With
their release from the land an increasingly large number of men
had their ability to work (their labor) to exchange for money
In the work of
No
(for wages).
bound
longer being
to a lord or to the land, as
he had been in the feudal society, the individual could sell his
labor in the market in return for the money which he needed
and wanted. Theoretically,
this
a situation in which a bar-
was
gain was reached which was to the advantage of both parties.
But Malthus indicated
the tendency
this:
is
for
population to
increase geometrically while the increase in the food supply
is
one of the costs of production, and since, in the interests of profits, the cost of production must be reduced as much as possible, the tendency is for
labor to underbid its competition, with the result that soon the
price of labor has been forced down to a starvation level. The
outlook from the point of view of orthodox theory was, therefore, very dismal.
only arithmetical. Thus, since labor
However,
points:
is
is inadequate. It breaks down at two
can consciously control population increase and
this theory
man
the production of food; through voluntary organizations of
keep wages above the
starvation level. Out of these inadequacies of the orthodox view
utilitarianism and
arise two social philosophies of significance
workers
it
becomes possible
also
to
Marx. In these Mr. Mead sees
the attitude of research science at work again. Science adthe socialistic theory of Karl
vances through the conflict of universals, "theories," with
"brute facts." This relationship is discoverable in this problem.
The
difference between the
two suggested answers
f
xix
lies
mainly
INTRODUCTION
in
their direction.
The
with the background of
utilitarians,
English empiricism, which had reduced scientific laws to the
psychological habits of association, was an opportunistic philos-
ophy of
society which gave a very practical rule of
thumb
for
what of that carried over from the past should be
retained and what should be rejected. Marx's theory is more
ambitious. A fusion of Hegelian metaphysics and the orthodox
distinguishing
economic doctrine, Marx's position points to the dialectic of
the economic process. This process leads inevitably to a revolution in which workers, aware of the international character
of their problems, unite throughout the world to set up a new
As Mr. Mead points
social order.
ground seriously
1
9 14.
He
ment by
out, that
movement
lost
in the nationalistic disaffection of socialists in
also indicates the scientific
inadequacy of
this
move-
calling attention to the fact that socialism never ac-
curately depicted either the actual conditions or the actual
wishes of the laborer. It thus becomes one more social theory,
perfectly legitimate as such, which breaks
ticular facts.
Out of
this
breakdown
down against parnew conception
arises a
and the replacement of revolutionary socialism by the
liberal
doctrine of social evolution.
What Mr. Mead
is
especially
that our thinking takes the
wants us to see in this connection
same form whether in the field of
economic or political theory or in that of science properly so
called. In each case we start with some theory, some universal.
This we retain and extend until such time as we find some particular fact which does not conform to the law, or the hypothesis
as
it
it is
given.
The
result
is
a modification of the theory so that
deals adequately with the exceptional instance, where this
possible, or, if such modification
is
is
impossible, to the rejection
of the theory.
Laws
of this sort are clearly of a type distinct from those
formulated under the inspiration of absolutism and authority.
"Vi
The laws of science are not dogmas: they are postulates. The
method of research science always conflicts with fixed dogmas;
and, as Mr.
Mead
is
anxious to have us see, so far the former
INTRODUCTION
has always been successful whenever these two methods have
had occasion to lock horns.
The
When
Industrial Revolution touches science in another
too.
the entrepreneur began to use the extensive application of
machinery to meet
in
way
his productive needs,
he found that he was
want of some concept which would enable him
to discover the
efficiency of different machines, various forms of
comparative
power, and so
forth. In other words,
cept of the unit of work.
With
he needed a general con-
this incentive, the
problem was
attacked by the scientists of the period; and the outcome of
their activity was the formulation of the idea of energy. This
now one of the most significant and extensively applied
whole gamut of scientific notions, made its appearance
as a bookkeeping conception of the physical world! It enabled
the producer to compare his alternative means of production, his
sources of power, in terms of the units of work available in each.
Instances might be pointed out at some length of this sort of
reciprocal stimulus in which the scientist has found his incentive in a problem posed by the producer, and, on the other
hand, where the entrepreneur has applied to his problems in-
concept,
in the
formation discovered by the scientist in the solution of his probwe will disregard, for there remain two other rami-
lems. These
thought which must be indicated.
As was pointed out when we indicated that the roots of our
idea of a rational world go back to the Middle Ages, the modern
scientist is committed to the thesis that the world can be underfications of
modern
scientific
The most common formulation
commitment is
found in the statement and acceptance of laws of nature. The
success which has attended the reduction of natural phenomena
stood.
of this
to basic uniformities has led to the postulation of an explana-
determined by its relation to pthers. This has led commonly to the assumption that
the extension of scientific knowledge implies a mechanistic_
philosophy which reduces man, as everything else, to a phase
in a process carried on inevitably and unavoidably. At this
tion of the world in
point Mr.
Mead
which each event
is
protests with the rather unique,
XXI
and somewhat
INTRODUCTION
paradoxical, view that the
more the processes of nature can
is man's freedom.
This follows from the fact that our control over nature is proportionate with our understanding of it. Mechanical science
does not mechanize human conduct. Rather, it gives man freedom; for the more we know of the processes governing our environment, the greater is our ability to get control over it.
Thus, instead of being the end of attempts to explain man and
his institutions in terms of ends, mechanical science becomes a
guaranty of the successful attainment of those ends. The reason
this seeming paradox can be maintained carries us back to an
appreciation of what modern science is doing. Research science
approaches problems. In its attempt to solve its problems, it
uses certain postulates. It does not, however, present these
postulates as a systematic account of the world in any particular aspect. The concepts it employs are recognized solely be-
be described in terms of laws, the greater
cause of their fruitfulness.
Out of this phase of the
scientific attitude
develops the second
point of influence mentioned above. Science has given rise to
philosophic movements. In the nineteenth century both prag-
matism and realism arise out of science. The former relates to
the method of science. In the preceding paragraph it was said
that science recognized certain concepts because of their fruitfulness.
Couple with that another characteristic of science since
the Renaissance, the utilization of observation to discover the
"brute fact" which makes necessary the modification of
sci-
and you have the background out of which developed William James's radical empiricism on the one hand
and John Dewey's instrumentalism on the other. Such other
forms of Pragmatism as that of Hans Vaihinger spring more
directly from previous philosophical movements, notably the
metaphysic of English empiricism and the phenomenalism of
entific concepts,
Immanuel Kant's theory of knowledge. Among these various
forms of the pragmatic position, Mr. Mead's own thought attaches definitely to those which spring from an analysis of
what
is
involved in research science.
[
xxii
INTRODUCTION
But, besides pragmatism, another type of philosophy modern
reaHsm springs directly from modern science. Here an attempt
of a definitely philosophic sort
entific
conclusions.
It
is
made
to
supplement
sci-
has already been indicated that the
such makes no attempt to give any systematic account of the universe as a whole or of any particular aspect of
it based on his postulates, on his observations, or on his concluscientist as
But the human mind has always wished to know more;
has always sought some statement of the nature of the uni-
sions.
it
verse either as a whole or in
its
different aspects.
of the nineteenth century and of our
those
who make
own
The
generation
is
reahst
among
the attempt to supply the answer to this re-
putedly more ultimate question.
In the lecture in which he deals with realism Mr. Mead
stresses particularly a rather special phase of this movement,
its
interest in logic, an interest reflected especially in the
work
of Mr. Bertrand Russell and Mr. Alfred North Whitehead.
The
had been concerned with
aspects of reahty. This goes back to Aris-
logic of traditional rationalism
formal, classificatory
During the nineteenth century, however, the question of
became a matter of vital concern as reflecting central hopes
and ends of various movements. Romanticism, for example,
comes to an articulate head in the idealistic, dynamic logic of
Hegel; pragmatism finds its intellectual feet in the utiHtarian
or instrumentalistic logic of Mr. John Dewey.
totle.
logic
Realism is interested in a very different approach to the problem of reality than either of the movements just mentioned.
Recognizing the two phases of experience, the formal and the
material, the realist proposes to deal with the formal without
reducing
it,
as the English empiricists
and Kant had,
either to
associated states of consciousness or to forms characteristic of,
and projected by the mind
itself.
The
realist
conceived of the
forms as relations existing objectively. These relations are "out
there" quite as much as the object related. We think them; but
that would be impossible
thought.
The
if
there were not something there to be
logical interest of the realist
becomes, therefore,
INTRODUCTION
an interest
in
breaking up the object of knowledge into
its
various elements, together with the connections or relations that
hold them together. The logical forte of realism is analysis.
Thus appears again the problem of the individual. To the consideration of this problem Mr. Mead devotes the last chapter of
the book, making it also the point of introduction of the contemporaneously important idea of relativity. Here Mr. Mead
leans toward Mr. Whitehead rather than toward Mr. Russell.
Ill
have attempted to indicate some of the ways in which
analysis of the thought movements of the nineteenth century centers around the scientific movement of the
period, the movement which gives the key for interpreting this
rich and complex period. In the following sections of this Introduction two things remain to be noted. In the first place,
we must discover what phases of the thought of the period have
not been included. Secondly, and primarily for those who read
this volume without having read The Philosophy of the Present,
edited by Mr. A. E. Murphy, and Mind, Self, and Society,
edited by Mr. C. W. Morris, some hint must be given as to
what is involved in Mr. Mead's notion of the past and his
theory of the self, both of which are significantly referred to in
the present work.
Perhaps the most important of the omissions is the lack of
any mention of the pessimists, Nietzsche and Schopenhauer,
and of the movement known as "positivism." The latter omission is somewhat cared for in the material which forms the Appendix of this volume. In the analysis of French philosophy
August Comte, at least, is given a fairly adequate treatment.
So
Mr. Mead's
Of course,
it is,
to a certain extent, true that positivism exerted
and temporary influence. Yet,
Saint-Simon and Comte, it indicated a live
a rather local
as expressed
by
interest in
the
philosophic implications of the success of the methods of
sci-
ence, particularly as these bore on the possibility of a true scientific
approach to the problems of society. These interests are
INTRODUCTION
congenial to Mr.
Mead; and yet
for
some reason, on which
speculation would be both in vain and useless, he neglected this
doctrine in his analysis of nineteenth-century
movements
as a
whole.
volume makes no preMerz's monumental, fourvolume work on History of European Thought in the Nineteenth
Century. Apparently, Mr. Mead saw the purpose of his course
as twofold. On the one hand, he wished to demonstrate the organic continuity of ideas. Therefore he emphasized the significance of the thought of the Renaissance for the period we are
considering. He also wished to select from the numerous fields
and developments in the last century the tendencies which particularly demarcated the genius of that period and which carry
It is trite to indicate that the present
tense of such catholicity as
is
found
in
To do this in a course of approxisomething
of a task. On the other
mately
is
hand, as I had already indicated, Mr. Mead's thought centers
primarily around the development of research science and the
ramifications of this discipline in other fields. These limits are
indicated not with an intention to censure but only to assist
the reader in his orientation to the material which follows.
Nonetheless, one is struck with the absence of any mention of
Nietzsche and Schopenhauer. As reflecting the negative side of
Romantic and absolute idealism, the least that can be said is
that they exerted a widespread influence in the last century. If
one may apply the Hegelian dialectic to the question, one may
say that Schopenhauer is the antithesis which carries Hegelianism itself into a position demanding a new synthesis. No doubt
both thinkers would have rebelled at being thus intimately
linked together in the inexorable logic of a system. Within
limits, it is no doubt true that Hegel thought of his own philosophy as the crowning synthesis. On the other hand, Schopenhauer did not take kindly to his neglect by the optimistic idealists who were his contemporaries. Yet, it is not an injustice to
treat his pessimism as Romantic idealism's negative side.
A further significance of Schopenhauer's thought is indicated
over into the present scene.
forty-five lectures
[xxv]
INTRODUCTION
by Mr. DeWitt H. Parker in the Introduction to
volume of selections from Schopenhauer's writings.'
succinctly
his Httle
In this statement he indicates a very real influence of Schopenhauer on the contemporary representative of the philosophy of
irrationalism,
M. Henri
Bergson. Whether or not there
influence of the sort indicated
is
direct
by Mr. Parker, irrationalism
is
and is deserving of a consideration usually
minimized by those sharing the more usual predilection to rationalism. To have failed to deal with Schopenhauer seems like
persistent tendency
a real oversight.
Mr. Mead mentions neo-Kantianism and the newer idealmovements in Germany, England, and America, only to
indicate that Hegel remained a force in the latter two countries after his influence had died out in Germany. Fechner,
Paulsen, Windelband, Eucken, Miinsterberg, T. H. Green,
Bradley, and Bosanquet are scarcely mentioned. Wundt apistic
pears in his role as one of the founders of modern, experimental
psychology, a
Mead
movement
these individuals
which
to the consideration of
which Mr.
devotes a considerable amount of space. Along with
is
may
be cited the neglect of the study of value
rooted in this period and
cussion in our generation.
The
is
a focal point of heated dis-
field
of aesthetics
is
scarcely
touched, and then primarily as related to the metaphysical
connotations of Schelling's philosophy. Ethical theory
tioned only where
it
is
men-
appears as an adjunct of considerations
The development of
French philosophy receives attention only in the material incorporated as an Appendix.
As a treatise dealing with movements of thought other than
philosophic, as it does wherever these illustrate the genius of
of dominant social and political theories.
research
science,
the
following omissions
should be noted.
Beyond the use of their material to indicate the advance of
scientific method, Mr. Mead does not trace the details in the
development of physical and biological theories of the period.
'
Schopenhauer: Selections, edited by
De Witt H. Parker (New York:
ner's Sons).
xxvi
Charles Scrib-
INTRODUCTION
The
philosophic oflfshoot of the emphasis on evolutionary ideas
vitalism
is
dealt with significantly only as
it
appears in the
work of M. Henri Bergson. This is a little odd, for in some ways
this movement, centering around Eucken, Fechner, and Driesch
on the Continent, and appearing also in England in the latter
part of the century, is significantly and pecuharly related to
certain forces at work during this era. Mathematical theory is
unmentioned except as related to recent developments in
logical theory. Theories of education and of the state appear
only as related to social, pohtical, and economic ideas.
ments
in literature
and
Move-
art in general receive attention only as
illustrative material.
Again
let
me
indicate that these omissions are mentioned,
not as criticisms, but solely to indicate to the reader points at
which the present work
need to be supplemented.
will
IV
We
come now to the final sections of this Introduction, in
which we shall attempt to give some indication of the meaning
of Mr. Mead's doctrines in regard to the nature of the self
and of the past. These are treated respectively in the volumes
by Mr. Murphy and by Mr. Morris, which were mentioned above. Since they both play a part in the development
of the ideas of the present volume, some attention must be
given them here. Had one asked Mr. Mead what problems were
of pecuHar interest to him, and with which he found himself led
to deal in something other than the usual way, he might well
have indicated the problem of the nature of the self and the
problem of the past.
As a study deahng with thought in the preceding century,
this volume must reflect, at least by implication, Mr. Mead's
edited
theory of the past.
The
pursuit of history brings one inevitably
into intimate grips not only with the past as a fact but also with
the whole question of evidence, of divergent interpretations, of
the continuity of
so on.
True
movements from one period
to the basic
approach to
[
xxvii
and
the problem with which
to another,
INTRODUCTION
he treats the problem of the
an
instance
of
application
past as
the
of the methods of research science. At least in the primary conception of his theory
on this matter, the statement that each generation recreates
this series of lectures is concerned,
new and
the past, that for each age a
the Rubicon, must have
come
to
different Caesar crosses
Mr. Mead from
his
awareness
that theories of historical interpretation are broken on the same
type of exception, of "brute fact," that gives
in scientific research.
Our knowledge
rise to
of the past
is
problems
transmitted
form of theories, of universals, just as the knowledge of
nature is transmitted under the form of natural laws. In each
field the discovery of new data, the uncovering of new monuments, bring exceptional cases which require that our concepts
be reconstructed. The study of history, the problem of the past,
thus becomes nothing more or less than a single instance of the
scientific approach to any problem whatsoever.
Perhaps in the present volume this character of the past is
best evidenced in the treatment of romanticism. In its attempt
to turn the clock back, to catch again and give living expression
to the spirit of the Middle Ages, romanticism illustrates Mr.
Mead's contention that the past exists for either an individual
or an age only in so far as they project themselves back into the
period in which they are interested. Now, such projection always presupposes a present experience. Thus, in the case of the
romanticists, the return to the past carried with it the sense of
defeat which followed the collapse of the revolution. Whether
they liked it or not, they returned to the past sadder and wiser
men. Having lived through the revolution and its failure, the
in the
men
of the
new day saw
the earher period as
for the medievalists themselves or for the
of reason,
first,
who
it
was impossible
exemplars of the
followed them, to have seen
it.
Thus we
life
see,
that the romantic interpretation of the Middle Ages
is
from the experience of that age by those who lived in
it; secondly, that the romantic interpretation of the Middle
Ages is markedly different from that of the Age of Enlightenment, which immediately preceded the period of the revolution.
different
xxviii
INTRODUCTION
In this single case
we not only
see the impossibility of an
identical past for successive ages;
we
also see that the process
through which each period determines the nature of the past
is simply the method of research science applied to a type of
problem with which we do not ordinarily associate it. In other
words, the problem of the past and of research science are one
the novelty being the particular, exceptional event which requires modification of our theory; the form being the theory,
the universal which we posit as the condition of our having a
thread, a guiding idea in our interpretation.
The
position indicated here
is
not a denial of the past in the
sense of a solipsistic absorption of the past and the future in the
momentary experience of an instantaneous, "knife-edge"
pres-
ent. Just as the scientist recognizes that his researches deal
with
real objects,
although admitting he does not
know
their nature
completely, that his theories about them will be subject to continuous modification as new data are presented, and that in the
end the object will be distinctly different from the object with
which he started, so the student of the past, the historian in particular, is dealing with a series of events really antecedent to any
particular present, but a series of events which is successively
described in quite different terms as our interpretative theories
change, as the experience of the race is accumulated, and as new
data present themselves. In this process the new past is different
from the old, just as for the scientist the new object differs from
the one it replaces. In neither case is the problem simply that of
seeing what is "out there." Seeing, in any significant sense, depends upon our looking, and looking reflects the whole system
of interests, theories, purposes, and ideals that leads us to seek
one, rather than another, nature in the thing under consideration. This is true of all phases of scientific research as it is of
all human endeavor. Completely impartial observation is never
achieved. The dice are always loaded in favor of some preference. No matter how rigidly we may attempt to check and
counterbalance the personal equation, our considerations are
guided by theories which we expect to have to modify or to
[
xxix
INTRODUCTION
completely reject. Indeed, Mr.
method
research
down
Mead indicates one
as involving conscientious
aspect of the
efforts
to
break
the very theories which guide our investigations at any
given time. In connection with the theory of the past, Mr.
Mead
does not deny the fact of pastness.
any alternative
He
never suggests
to the fact that a real Caesar crossed a real
What
insist upon is that for each age there is
and a different Rubicon, because of divergent
ideational backgrounds with the resultant projection on the past
Rubicon.
he does
a different Caesar
of different interpretative hypotheses.
Belonging, as he does, to the group closely associated with
Mr. Dewey, and having been deeply influenced by the early
works of Mr. Whitehead, Mr. Mead had no place for an absolute, static time composed of an infinite number of distinct and
separate "knife-edge" moments. Time is a process. As process,
it is change. The past is a part of time. Since what is true of
the whole is true also of its parts, the past, too, must be characterized by fluidity, by change. If one agrees with Mr. Mead
in giving up the absolutistic notion of time which we inherit
from the nineteenth century, one has no alternative but to accept the consequences of this shift of position; one must acquiesce to
some
sort of relativism. It
is
in part this substitution
of
relativism for absolutism in the interpretation of concrete tem-
makes Mr. Mead's doctrine seem, at least
strange and difficult to understand. Most of us have
poral experience that
at
first,
so
not caught the
Or we may
full
implications in the shift of point of view.
and accept rationally what is involved in the
change without having as yet made our emotional peace with
the
see
new approach. Relativism
is
not, as yet, a part of our un-
consciously accepted assumptions.
lutistic
We
still
fit
into the abso-
niche of the preceding century. Should the
new move-
ment, which was so strong in the first quarter of our century,
permeate our thinking as that of Newton did the thinking of our
new
become manifest which will acwhich give us pause.
In any case, we can admit the practical significance of
forebears, a
Z,eitgeist will
cept, as self-evident, theories
XXX
INTRODUCTION
Mr. Mead's doctrine: history
exists only to the extent that indi-
viduals put themselves back into the past; this being the case,
there
is
no alternative
to the conclusion that the past as
an ob-
ject of historical study differs from age to age, for the individuals
of any given period never bring to their criticism the same
background, the same interests, the same accumulation of
racial experience as do the individuals of different periods,
We come now
Mr. Mead's treatment of the problem of the
is the subject matter of the volume edited
by Mr. Morris as the first of the group of which this is the
second. The problem is also considered at some length in the
material composing the present volume, where we meet it in two
connections, first in the analysis of the Romantic movement,
which, as we have just seen, also throws light on the problem of
the past, and in a later chapter dealing with the problem of
society, for in Mr. Mead's mind the processes of social move<
ment and that of the development of selves were inseparable.
self.
to
This problem
The crux
of the author's doctrine of the self
is
the portrayal
of the process through which the self appears as a result of the
assumption of various
roles, first
of one person, then of another,
then of another. Out of this procedure one comes gradually to
see one's
own
role as
it is
demarcated from those of other per-
sons whose roles one has temporarily assumed. Thus,
awareness
is
achieved, for, by distinguishing
its
own
self-
role, its
part from the role of others, the self becomes conscious of
own
itself
statement we see that Mr.
study of this problem the modern
emphasis upon a dynamic process as over against the ancient
static statement. Just as he rejects the atomistic notion of
as distinct
Mead
from other
selves. In this
carries over into the
"knife-edge" presents in the analysis of time, so he rejects the
notion
of isolated,
atomic selves.
Selves
come
into
being
through a process of self-conscious interaction and interpenetration with other selves.
At
first
sight this process
may seem
f
xxxi
as difiicult to
understand
INTRODUCTION
as
was the theory of the past
in its first
statement. As in the
case of the latter, illumination comes through the exemplification of the process in the
again, as
movement
of thought; and once
have already indicated, the Romantic movement
is
the point of departure.
The
attempt to turn back the
and ideas of the medieval
period, to assume and play out the role of another age. This was
essence of romanticism
is its
clock, to clothe itself in the forms
achieved to the extent that a considerable amount of the trappings of the earlier period was brought out to be admired and
worn again if not actually, then vicariously through the literature and through the general ideas and ideals of the later period.
The revolution had not brought about many physical changes
in Germany; but the conquering armies of France, under the
leadership of Napoleon, did bring them. At first, as a result of
the infectious force of the enthusiastic and conquering Frenchmen, who, on their march away from Paris, enjoyed one sweeping victory after another, these changes were regarded as being
all
for the good.
But,
when
the tide of battle turned,
when the
moved back toward Paris
Moscow, a very dififerent feeling was enpresence. The ideal had collapsed. The revotogether with all that it had set into motion.
staggered, broken, bewildered horde
after the defeat at
gendered by their
lution
The
had
failed,
present turned out to be a
of disappointment.
those
who had
The
mean
age, one of disillusionment,
sense of defeat weighed heavily on
all
so recently given their souls to the forces emanat-
With both
immediate past and their
newborn hopes shattered and stripped away, men staked what
hope remained on a return to a still more distant past, that of
medieval feudalism.
Much as they desired this old order, much as they attempted
to identify themselves with it, an inevitable difficulty stood in
their way
they came back to this old order with different eyes.
The revolution had failed; and the men who had seen this
failure, who had shared in the defeat, could not have been unmarked by their experience. And they were not unmarked.
ing from France.
their
xxxii
INTRODUCTION
garb, they might emulate and eulo-
They might put on medieval
might
gize the troubadours, they
in
any number of ways attempt
the desired identification; but they failed to attain
could put on the clothes, but they could not
it.
make them
fit.
They
The
garments had been cut to the form and stature of another age,
and they hung ill-fitting and awkward from new shoulders. It
was like the play of children ransacking old trunks and putting
on the
finery, playing the roles of
activity
may
be quaint,
mains incongruous
may
it
the old
The result of such
memory, but it re-
another era.
stir
one's
clothes do not belong. So the ro-
manticists could turn back the clock, they could dig into the
forgotten past and attempt
belong to
Yet, having
it.
its
the experiment, having played
came back
the role of another time, they
self-consciousness of their
resurrection, but they could not
made
own
own age with a
their own role that
to their
position, of
they would not otherwise have had. In trying to be someone
else, they had collectively discovered themselves.
Here, in this historical movement, we find reflected what for
Mr. Mead is the basic element in the development of the self.
The self is a process. It is not an entity; it is an achievement.
Not only do we iDeoome aware
selves only
When
by assuming
a self has done this,
the self whose role
point
roles,
it is
it
of ourselves, but
by playing the part of
not only
it
has taken, but
is
this is the
also in a position to criticize itself.
someone
same time
it
else,
the self realizes
others.
in a position to criticize
and
becomes a standard of comparison, so to speak.
at being
we become
its
The
important
other self
When
playing
own nature
realizes the nature of the person
whose
"1
at the
role
is
being played.
In this connection one important difference between the
philosophy of Mr.
noted.
The
latter
Mead and
found
that of the romanticists
must be _
in this process a metai5hysical
theory
which the ultimate identification of the self and non-self in
an absolute spirit became possible. For them this is not only
the process of individual development but is identical with the
movement which permeates and governs the whole universe.
in
xxxiii
INTRODUCTION
The
individual self thus becomes the universe writ small. Mr.
Mead
is
not interested
process. His interest
is
in the
in the
metaphysical connotations of the
impHcations this view may hold
for social psychology. He turns to the process indicated to discover the genesis of persons as distinct from biological organ-
isms, to find the root of the socially important virtue of sympathy, and to indicate the development through which we as
individuals become aware of social Hfe. Again, as in his theory
of science and in his doctrine of the past, he posits the existence
The not-self, the other selves through the assumpwhose roles the new self is generated, are not objects
dependent upon the processes of a subject which plays its part.
Indeed, it cannot be, for there must be other selves whose roles
of objects.
tion of
can be taken before the business of taking roles
is
conceivable.
At this point the position we are considering breaks cleanly
away from metaphysical doctrines.
"^ In his treatment of the self Mr. Mead makes a great deal of
what in grammar is called the "reflexive mood." This is the
(mood of self-awareness. The self has no significance unless it
can turn back upon itself, can become its own object, distiniWuish itself in a milieu of other selves. Until this can be done,
made significant for the psychological and
problems which are Mr. Mead's major concern at
this point. That this self-awareness is not only possible but
a fact he finds indicated in the achievement of a reflexive form
in language, the form which recognizes the self as both subject
and object of an experience.
Whatever one may finally come to think of this doctrine, one
the self cannot be
I
Sociological
{
must recognize
it
as a fruitful hypothesis.
With Mr. Mead's
profound respect for the scientific method and for the technique
and successes of research science, not only would he himself have
thought of this position as a hypothesis, but he would have
wished criticism of it to be made in this Hght. Its fruitfulness as
a hypothesis
is
indicated especially in chapters xvi and xvii
of the present volume.
The immediate
implications of this theory for social psyf
xxxiv
INTRODUCTION
chology are at once apparent. It is only through the utiHzation
of social media that selves appear at all. Indeed, it is not an
overstatement to speak of the self as a society of selves. In the
process of "playing at" one role and then another we not only
become aware of our own role but find that we are potentially
any one of the selves whose part we have been taking. This is
shown overtly
in the
commonly recognized
fact that in shifting
from one social group to another we become "different" persons. This does not involve any elaborate theory of the disthing is much more common,
phenomenon indicated by that
others and in ourselves that, in moving
sociation of personality.
much more normal, than
phrase.
We
notice in
The
the
from one group to another, responses so divergent from those
we call "normal" are induced that we say, with literal truth,
the person in question is hardly recognizable as the same person in these various manifestations of his self, in the different
roles
which divergent situations
The
ability to be a
call out.
new person
in this sense,
however, goes
has already become
famihar with the part to be played. Each role has been taken
previously in play, in mimicking, as a result of esteem or for
back
to the fact that the self involved
some other reason, until the self gets the "feel" of a role and it
may be assumed becomingly when circumstances call it forth.
In this way the self is both enriched and made more flexible. Being a social milieu in miniature, the self can adapt itself to new
way as to make adequate social responses.
This matter of assuming roles is significant in another connection also. Not only does "playing at" one person and then
another enrich the social experience of the self involved; not
only is this the medium through which the self becomes aware
situations in such a
own nature
of
its
it
takes;
it is
opposition to those other selves whose roles
in
also the basis for the
theory requires as
sympathy which every
the basis of co-operative
effort
social
toward
sympathy for which every theory of
psychology must give an account. The traditional device
socially desirable ends, a
social
at this point
is
to
have recourse
[
XXXV
to a social instinct, or to bi]
INTRODUCTION
furcate behavior into acts motivated either by selfish or by altruistic desires.
Each of
culties, as the history
the basis of
these theories involves serious
diffi-
of personal and social ethics shows.
Mr. Mead's theory we have
of this difficulty also. In the process he describes,
play the part of other selves;
we
significance, of their difficulties,
also
and of
On
a possible solution
we not only
become aware of
their limitations.
their
Hav-
ing at least vicariously put ourselves in the other person's
shoes,
we
We have
We can put
are in a position to sympathize with him.
played his part, and we
know what he has
to face.
how
we would be affected by it, see what we would be likely to do if
we were in his place. Consequently, we can understand his behavior. The more roles we can assume in this fashion, the wider
ourselves in his position again and again, and each time see
will
be our sympathy, and the more significant will be our social
To be able to deal with this aspect of our behavior
without having to have recourse to special instincts or other
devices seems a real contribution to the social psychology of our
responses.
times.
VI
There is one further point to be advanced as showing the
worth of these various doctrines of Mr. Mead. One criterion
commonly agreed upon for testing scientific theories is the way
in which they correlate the findings of various fields. We have
already indicated that the position developed in this group of
lectures indicates a certain identity between the interpretation
of historical movements and of social phenomena. For example,
we pointed out
that, historically, the social process
cally represented in the
is
graphi-
Romantic movement. In the chapter on
individualism this same theory of the development of selves
significantly applied to the
is
problem of the individual. Further-
more, the same movements which indicate his social theory have
done double service through illuminating Mr. Mead's doctrine
One might go still further to indicate that these
may all be related in two directions: first, through his ac-
of the past.
ceptance of the method of research science as underlying
[
xxxvi
all
INTRODUCTION
significant
developments
in thinking;
and second, through
his
basic assumption that the description of experience in every
be made in terms of processes rather than in terms of
absolutes. In this further step a still more pertinent unity is
introduced into his whole thought structure, and such special
unities as have been indicated above are derived rather than
field is to
any case, the fact remains that the views presented
in this volume do stand together in such a way that a grasp of
that which pertains to one field will illuminate one's endeavor
to see what Mr. Mead is driving at in some other connection.
ultimate. In
Merritt Hadden Moore
xxxvii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PACE
CHAPTER
I.
II.
KantThe Philosopher of the Revolution
....
Born
III.
The Revolution Breaks Down; Romanticism
IV.
Kant and the Background of Philosophic Romanticism
V.
VI.
VII.
VIII.
l(X.
:.
From Renaissance to Revolution
X.
X[.
XII.
The Romantic Philosophers Fichte
The Romantic Philosophers Schelling
The Romantic Philosophers Hegel
Is
25
51
66
85
.
...
1 1
127
Evolution Becomes a General Idea
153
The Industrial Revolution The Quest for Markets
The Social Renaissance Utilitarianism
The Social Renaissance Karl Marx and Socialism
Industry a Boon to Science Mechanism the Handmaid of
.
Finality
XIII.
Modern Science
199
215
243
Is
Research Science
264
XIV, Science Raises Problems for Philosophy
ri Bergson
XV. Science Raises Problems for
Vitalism; Hen292
Philosophy Realism
and
3^^'
Pragmatism
XVI. The Problem of Society
How We
Become Selves
XVII. Mind Approached through Behavior
Made
169
Can
Its
360
Study Be
Scientific?
3^6^
JCVni. Individuality in the Nineteenth
Century
Appendix. French Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century
Index
405
.418
5^^
xxxix
CHAPTER
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
THE
general political, social, and institutional background of the period of the Enlightenment is the Renaissance.
The former
falls
in
a general
way
in
the
eighteenth century. Immediately back of it lies the Renaissance
and the philosophy of Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibnitz. The
philosophy of the eighteenth century gathers particularly about
of Leibnitz' philosophy made by
a published presentation
the
German
philosopher, Wolff. It was a
somewhat
superficial
statement, and it presented the world from the point of view of
what is termed "rationalism." There is one phase of this
rationalism to which I particularly want to call your attention,
namely, that it is an inheritance from an earlier period and
came into European thought by way of Christianity. \The conception of the world as a rational order came through the
theology of the church. The doctrine was built around the
gospel of Jesus and the conception of St. Paul when he undertook to formulate the Jewish theory in such a form that it
would be made universal.
With the advent of Christianity came the conception of a
world created by a God who was infinitely intelligent and who
had infinite power. Everything that such a deity created, everything that he did, must be the expression of that intelligence,
and nothing could resist its expression. You can see that there
could be nothing accidental or irrational in such a world.
Of
might not be rational to us. An infinite mind would
have purposes and methods of which we could not conceive
with our finite intelHgence. Particularly there would be purposes which would be carried out in later periods. We cannot
see what these purposes are. Therefore the world may appear to
us to be irrational; but actually, having been created by an
course,
it
[I]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
intelligence that has infinite
power and an
infinite
understand-
it must be rational clear through.
This conception, as I have said, was of a world which was
fashioned to carry out God's purposes. The first expression of
these purposes was found in bringing into existence men with
souls, who were free to sin and who were condemned to death
because of their sin. Back of this view lay the philosophy and
ing,
The world was thrown up, so to speak,
which the drama of the fall and the salvation of
man was to be enacted. It had just the relation to the drama
that the theater has. It had no purpose except as the scene in
which the drama could be enacted. After it was enacted, the
heavens were to be rolled up like a scroll. The history of the
world was simply a device of the Deity for the carrying-out of
this program. We have expression of this picture in the poetry
of Milton. God determines to replace the fallen angels by human souls, and for this purpose he takes out of the chaos matter
from which he fashioned the world. The value of the world centered in men's faith, in their souls, in what they experience.
In the light of this view St. Augustine, who Hved at about the
time of the fall of Rome, undertook, as Milton did later, to
justify the ways of God to man on the basis of what he conceived to be the inspired scriptures. He undertook to show
history of St. Augustine.
as the scene in
what God had tried to do, in so far as God revealed it to man.
As we have seen, the history of the world constitutes a sort of
drama.
It begins
Genesis.
with the creation of the world as depicted in
is presented as a free moral agent. He falls
Here man
from grace, he
sins,
and the punishment of sin
elects to offer salvation to
his son, if
man
man
will accept the
is
death; but
through the ultimate
means of
grace.
On
God
sacrifice of
that author-
Augustine undertakes to arrange the whole of human
history: it advances from the fall of man up to the appearance
of Christ, and his crucifixion, suffering, and mediation. From
that time on, the world presents the opportunity for man's sal-
ity St.
vation. It
This
was created
for that purpose.
much we know about
the world and about God's inten-
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
tion: he made the world out of nothing; he created it in six days
and placed man in it; man sinned, fell from grace, and God in
his infinite mercy set up his plan of salvation through the
appearance of Christ. From that time on, the world existed in
order that the sons and daughters of Adam and Eve might have
the opportunity of being saved. When this opportunity had
been offered, the drama, so to speak, would be completed. Then
the world was to be burned up, the scroll prepared, and those
lost in hell were to go on suffering through eternity. That is the
picture which St. Augustine portrayed.
But it assumes a perfectly definite end. And it assumes
another power besides that of God, and one which runs counter
to God, and that is man's free will. This is present because God
saw fit to create it. Of course, he created it with the possibility
of man sinning. Even the devils in hell speculated; but the
assumption was that God had infinite knowledge, and he knew
what the
result of his creation
would
be.
But there was
in the
world a principle which could oppose itself even to the infinite
power because God placed it there. He saw fit to create individuals with such powers. There should be suffering and misery
due to man's sinning. It was part of God's chastisement for sin.
The world was, on the face of it, irrational. It was a world
created by an infinite God, a perfect deity, but
still
one
in
and imperfection could appear because man could
Man was responsible for the evil and for the
accompanying suffering which came with sin. He could elect to
use the means of grace which God gave him to be saved, or he
could refuse and be lost. The picture of the world from that
standpoint was most comprehensively given by Dante; but we
have the same picture of it in Milton's Paradise Lost and Paradise Regained, having therein beings that were able to choose
contrary to God's law, consequently introducing the element of
evil into the world. It was natural, then, that the world should,
on the face of it, be irrational.
The medieval world was conceived of as being inhabited not
only by men and women but by evil and good spirits. It was a
which
evil
exercise his choice.
[3]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
world shot through with what we might call "magic." The
is simply a history of magic, but here
again the conception was that God was utilizing these spirits for
his purposes. You have a fitting picture of it in Goethe's Faust.
That world, as we look back on it, was all shot through with
magic and historiology. There was the conception of it as seem-
science of the Middle Ages
ing to be absolutely irrational. Yet this evil
end by God, and everything which
God
is
is
is
overcome
in the
for the highest glory of
fully rational.
This attitude was entirely different from that of the ancient
world. If we look back to the great systematic philosopher of
the ancient world, Aristotle, we find that he regarded the world
as provided with "forms." That is an Aristotelian technical
term which answers in a certain way, on the biological side, to
our term "species"; on the logical side, to our term "concept."
It answers to the nature of things, that about things which is
known. For example, it is that which goes to make up a tree,
that which constitutes the nature of a spade, a house, or a chair.
A spade is any object which we recognize as having a certain
nature. Aristotle recognized such noble objects, such forms, in
nature in so far as nature was rational. Objects which have certain exact characters, certain qualities by means of which we
can make them out and from which we can deduce certain consequences, can be defined. In this way we find objects in the
world from which we can deduce logical consequences.
But
was a great deal in
was not rational. A tree, for example, seldom
reaches its proper symmetry. Animals are subject to all sorts of
defects and monstrosities. His explanation of this, in so far as
he did explain it, was that the "matter" in the world somewhat
resisted the "forms." In any case he recognized not only that
there was a rational character but that some things were irrasomething was present that could not be
tional, accidental
Aristotle recognized also that there
the world which
accounted
for.
The ancient world assumed
that there was absolute perfection
in
tRe heavens. But the ancient
scientist
[4]
and philosopher recog-
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
nized an accidental character of affairs on the surface of the
earth.
They accepted
a world in which there
was not only a
rational order but an irrational something that could not be ex-
plained, something that just happened. If the assumption were
pushed
far
enough, we should find
Hume
contingent elements.
later
it
made
to
be resolvable into
this the basis for his
skeptical philosophy.;
The medieval
jn
it
that
was
world, as over against Aristotle's, had nothing
irrational. It
down through
was
this
medieval view which passed
the Renaissance to the world of
Galileo in particular
drew upon
rationality of the world, that
this
is,
modern
science.
conception of the absolute
the view that everything that
happens can be explained. The assumption which he used was
that God works through natural forces, As an infinitely rational
being he must act uniformly in accordance with what Galileo
terms the"rational lawof nature"; and he must act in a most perfect fashion, that is in a mathematical fashion. God is conceived
of as the supreme mathematician. Objects have certain ways in
which they move in reference to one another. These must be
expressed and carried out in accordance with mathematical law.
If we find out what the important processes of nature are, we
also discover the laws which represent their various relations;
we find out the laws by means of which God works. For example, one can look at a highly complicated machine without understanding it or knowing its purpose, and yet one can be confident that everything in it was arranged by a mechanic in
accordance with natural law. Now God has a perfect mind; and
the most rational manner in which to exercise a mind, from the
point of view of the physicist of the Renaissance period, was to
make mathematical use of it. It was thought, then, that laws
could be found in the world which could never be broken,
that uniformities could be discovered which would be absolute, because that must be the way in which a perfect mind
would work.
The attitude of Galileo and also of the early modern philosophers was that God inevitably presented a world to man which
[5]
THOUGHT
was
IN
so devised that
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
man
could understand nature. This marks
what we might
postulate of modern
the passage from
call
to the basic
science.
the "theological
We
dogma"
state this postu-
terms of the uniformity of nature; we assume that
nature may be comprehensively arranged in uniform series.
late in
We
have that confident faith. Our knowledge comes back
We assume that there is a world in which there
are the laws of nature, but we have no assurance of it. This
still
to nature.
one of the great contributions of the medieval period to
modern world, and it is a contribution which has been of
increasing importance as science pushed its investigations furis
the
and further into nature.
The eighteenth century was the century of the triumph of
mathematical analysis. The Copernican theory had been accepted by the scientists, and thus mathematical analysis was
carrkd both to the heavens and to the earth. This analysis,
which Galileo really initiated, was carried further and further and always with distinguishing success. Men had found a
language in which they could read the world; it was a mathether
i/
^,
matical language.
The
point
am
emphasizing
is
that the plan
of things was devised by an infinitely intelligent being
who
did
everything in a most perfect fashion. Every detail would be
carried out in the manner of a perfect mechanic. If God were a
mechanic, he would construct a world perfectly worked out.
This medieval faith in the uniformity of nature became, as I
have
said, the
background of the thinking of the modern world.
not belong to the ancient world. From the point of view
of the former there is nothing in the world which is accidental.
Everything is taken care of by God, and everything he does
It did
done in an absolutely perfect fashion. His methods are those
which express themselves in mathematical form. It was to
that faith that the scientist of the Renaissance period turned to
unravel the facts of nature. We talk sometimes about the uniformity of nature being demonstrated by the law of probabihties; and if we try to find what the line of the argument is, we
discover a number of uniformities. Together they represent the
is
[6]
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
uniformity of nature. If we ask
why we
find
them,
it is
because
we have already assumed the uniformity; we have taken it as
our major premise that n ature is uniform. If nature is not uniform, of course our argument falls to the ground. But you cannot prove the uniformity of nature by assuming it in advance.
It
is
a postulate;
it
has never been proved. If
we
look for the
we find it not in Greek philosophy but in
At the present time science does not go
origin of the concept,
Christian theology.
back
to a theological doctrine;
it
We
formity on a pragmatic basis.
ern science assumes the world
is
accepts the postulate of unistate natural laws; our
modwe
rational in the sense that
can explain that which we find in terms of the uniformities of
the laws of nature. We go on with perfect confidence because
so far this view has always worked. It
is
a postulate
which
cannot very well be overthrown. If the laws of nature break
down, we can assume that there is some other uniformity which
we have not found as yet. It is a postulate for us since we have
taken over the fundamental assumption of an infinite creator
who
has fashioned the world in a perfect way with a purpose of
own. That was definitely the attitude of Renaissance science; and, if you want an interesting account of it, you will find
it in Mr. Whitehead's Science and the Modern World. In the
early part of the book you will find a very adequate and admirable presentation. In this period the world had become more
and more definitive and scientific in its attitude. This is one of
the things that we do not think of; and consequently, because
we do not think of it, we do not realize that it is there. But it
has had a very profound effect.
When men in the Renaissance period turned to an intensive
study of nature, they found that their most efficient tool was
mathematics; it was that which enabled them to reach simple
elements and to discover what the uniformities were in the events
in which these simple elements appeared. Thus, if the world
his
was perfectly ordered, it was ordered by a perfect mathematician. God was the great mechanic, not because his ethical or
his
moral ends were at
all
of a mechanical character, but because
[7]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the means by which these were carried out were inevitably the
most perfect. If God created the world for the fall and the salvation of man, as he did from the point of view of the Middle
Ages, he would create it in a mathematical fashion so that a
mathematical statement of it could be given,
v/ This rationalistic conception of a mathematically ordered
world was a postulate which was almost a dogma. Those of you
who have
development of the philosophy of
know how they gave to
the mathematical interpretation of nature an almost religious
value. Descartes' conception was of a world in which reality
was that which was clearly and distinctly perceived; in which
truth was that of which the mind had immediate and clear
conception. Clearness and distinctness were his criteria for
truth. He pushed his analysis further than it had ever gone
before, carrying it over into analytical geometry. Here he used
the mathematical statement of the process of motion itself, dividing motion up into an infinite number of accelerations. Galileo showed that bodies fall with a uniformly increasing velocity.
Descartes carried on this mathematical conception in order to
reach elements which could be arranged into uniform series.
Scientists were occupied with this analysis for a century and a
followed
the
Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibnitz,
half.
This general attitude freed the scientist; it freed him from the
of the church. He was studying the indefinite matter in
which the church was not interested. The church was interested
in man's soul and its salvation, and the material scene in
dogma
which the drama took place was of no value itself.
I want to call your attention at this point to the fact that in
the ancient world the atomic doctrine was fully presented but
was not made use of. Our science has gone ahead through the
use of this atomic conception of matter. Not only do we have
atoms, but we divide the atoms up into electrons and protons.
The avowed purpose of Epicurus in his presentation of this idea
was to free men's minds of superstitions. There was no reality
outside of weight, size, and shape. That was all there was.
[8]
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
this doctrine he hoped to free the minds of his disciples
from the fear of death. But the philosophers who undertook to
find values in the world were unwilling to adopt this theory. In
fact, no other school did adopt this Democritean doctrine.
Trees and houses, and other things, as our science conceives
of therti; are made up of electrons. But a tree is not simply a
Through
dejfinLte
is
number of ultimate
responsible for the tree.
nature
is,
as Aristotle says, a certain
which brings about
in the tr ee
When
physical particles. Something else
There
phenomena
its
development into a
world are taking place
around us, we try to analyze them in order to understand
them. We are always seeking simplicity in our modern scientific method. But what has been done with the unities in the
content of the world? There is something more than atoms.
What right have we to take the particles of the tree and say that
tree
various
they constitute the tree
itself?
in the
These
particles are really con-
nected with the climate, the solar system, and other things. All
the particles have relationships with all the other particles in
A field of force surrounds every particle in
the universe.
verse.
There
is
no
justification for
of them and saying that these constitute a tree.
we have
the uni-
our taking a particular group
To make
this
back again to the medieval period, to the
time of Abelard. There is a certain nature of the tree which
develops in the tree itself, until it takes on the form of the fully
actualized tree. What Abelard substituted for this was the concept which we have of the tree. The tree is the matter. You can
conceive of the tree as made up of just matter. But our concept
clear
to go
of the tree, or the value that
it
has for us, with
its color, its
and its bark, is a concept which we form.
That concept we find in the tree in so far as it is in our mind to
begin with. Then there are certain likenesses which exist. The
philosophers of the Renaissance were more or less free to deal
with the physical world as made up of physical particles.
They could seek after this simplicity. If they were asked what
leaves and foliage,
the other attributes of the so-called physical world were, they
would say that they were put into men's minds
as impressions.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
and odors. The atoms and molecules had
What you have there, what you convibrations.
are
When
ceive of,
you strike the retina, you arouse
color; it comes from the mind itself. The secondary qualities
exist in the mind. Space, form, and motion
these alone were
supposed to belong with the objects themselves. The secondary qualities, those which come through the eye, the ear, and
the palate belong to the mind. We transfer these qualities
to things, and so more and more of the world is put into the
consciousness of individuals. This is particularly true of the
meanings of things, e.g., that which goes to make up a tree. The
characters which we state in terms of the concept of a tree exist
in the minds of men, and they had previously existed in the
mind of God. The determination of other characters, those
which Aristotle found in nature, could be put into the concolors, sounds, tastes,
no color
in themselves.
sciousness of individuals.
One of the
reasons
why
it
was
relatively easy to transfer these
attributes to the consciousness of the individual
is
another of
The whole universe is created simply
as a scene in which the drama of the soul, which is independent
of the setting, could be enacted. Would this human soul act
virtuously or viciously? Would it use the means of grace prothe gifts of Christianity.
it, or would it fall from grace? Everything bore upon
and salvation of man. The human soul had an infinite
Hfe, a life of blessedness or a life of suffering. It was essential
even to the perfection of God. It was thus relatively easy to
vided for
the
fall
carry over the important characters of the world into the consciousness of
man, and the work of the
scientist
was made easy.
he comes to realize that God is a great mathematician. In the second place the indefinite world, the indefinite
matter, in themselves have no value except in so far as they express the laws of God. And in the third place the consciousness of individuals is the very reason for the existence of the
world. The world is there only for the sake of the individual.
Going back to the point which I have already made: the
world was created for a specific purpose, and this purpose was to
First of
all
lol
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
be carried out by the agencies which God placed on the earth.
Those agencies were centered in the church. It was a living
source of inspiration. God spoke through this agency as he had
spoken through the Holy Writ. The church was inevitably the
source of authority. The period in which the medieval world
expressed itself most completely was during the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries. We have the picture of the world as the
theologian, the philosopher, the churchman, and the layman
was a world created for a certain definite purpose. The salvation carried out by God and, after the sacrifice
of his son, by the institution of the church itself was passed on
to man through the church. This was an outside authority. It
was an authority which came from an infinite deity; it was an
authority which was not to be comprehended in its operation.
God did not explain what all his purposes were; he told only
enough to guide men in their conduct. Aside from that, his
purposes transcend men's conduct. The institutions of the
family and of the state themselves came from God. He established them and all other institutions. The schools and the universities were the means by which man could comprehend the
will of God. This will is arbitrary. When you call in a physician,
his comprehension is presumably better than yours; otherwise
you would not call him in. He speaks with authority, but he
does not speak with an arbitrary authority. When you call upon
the engineer who builds a bridge or a skyscraper, you are not
making use of an arbitrary authority, because the ground of
the authority lies in the knowledge which you yourself can in
some sense grasp. But the authority of the church came from
an infinite deity, an infinite mind, whose knowledge you could
not comprehend. You had to accept it simply because God
spoke and gave his authority through the church. This authorconceived
ity
got
it.
its
It
expression not simply in the church but in the
hands of the king by God
himself. All institutions were conceived of as established by
God. In so far as the institution reflected God's purpose, man
had to accept the institution; it spoke with the authority that
state.
The sword was placed
in the
[II]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
from the church itself. This embodied itself in the
Holy Roman Empire. The Holy Roman Empire had
at its head the emperor, who was crowned by the pope. We
know that empire died out and went to pieces; it became, as it
were, neither holy, nor Roman, nor an empire. But that conception belonged to practically all men's minds during that
came
to
it
so-called
period.
The points which I have been bringing out are points which
we are apt to overlook in the background of the thought of the
Renaissance period. It was a period of fundamental revoa period of breaking away from the conceptions of the
authority of the church, an authority which was arbitrary. It is
this latter which makes revolutions almost necessary. The attilater
lution
tude of revolution which marks the early modern period was
one against the arbitrary authority of the medieval institutions,
an authority which came to them as supposedly inspired by
God, given by God, and given with reference to ends and purposes which lay beyond the purview of man so that he was unable to criticize those institutions or to reform them: he had
to receive them as they were. This was the fundamental conception which belonged to the medieval period; its institutions,
were fundamentally church institutions. In the mind of the
medieval period the state derived its authority from the church
and from God through the church. The transcendent character
of the divine purpose also carried with it the necessarily arbitrary character of the institution as such.
Men
could not de-
termine what the authority of the institution should be from
its
function in the community.
One could not say
that the ad-
ministration of the institution should have such and such authority in order to bring about certain results which
sented as desirable.
They had
men preGod in
to look to the purposes of
the establishment of these institutions, and so the authority of
the institutions was necessarily arbitrary.
this
came on
ing in
it
the basis of a description of
The reaction
human nature
against
as hav-
a rational principle from which authority could proceed.
This rational principle was presented by Rousseau as the recog[12]
FROM RENAISSANCE T0 REVOLUTION
nition of rights
could be
made
which were the end of the individual and which
universal because in asserting his rights the indi-
vidual recognized
The
them
as belonging to others also.
is one which took
French Revolution; and we
reaction against arbitrary authority
place, on the
political side, in the
Rousseau expressed the gospel of this revolution
He undertook to find in man's own nature
the institutions of society. He undertook to find in
shall see that
in his Contrat social.
the basis for
man's rational nature the basis for the state as the sovereign
authority. It was not necessary to go outside of man's own
nature to get the basis for such an authority. On this ground,
in so far as a member of the community both enacts and obeys
the laws of the community, a rational state is possible. If
laws express the will of the whole community, the individual is
able both to enact them and to obey them as a member of the
community. And such laws could express the will of the whole
community
in so far as
they expressed the rights of the members
of that community, for rights exist only in so far as they are
acknowledged, and only to the extent that those who claim them
man can
No man
affirm his own
acknowledge them in the person of others. That is, no
claim a right which he does not recognize for others.
can claim a right
who
does not at the same time
obligation to respect that right in
all
others. In so far, then, as
can be an expression of the rights of individuals, that
legislation can flow from the whole community because it will
take on the form of that which is universal. If men are capable
legislation
of recognizing rights as well as of claiming them, then they are
capable of forming a community, of establishing institutions
whose authority will lie within the community itself.
The revolution gathered about the rights of man. That has
been perpetuated in the Declaration of Independence and the
statement that men are born free and equal. The great and outstanding illustration of such rights is property. No one can
make
a claim to property except as he admits
When men came
it in
others.
to conceive the order of society as flowing
from the rational character of society
[13]
itself;
when they came
to
"if*
THOUGHT
IN
criticize institutions
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
from the point of view of their immediate
function in preserving order, and criticized that order from the
point of view of its purpose and function;
when they approached
the study of the state from the point of view of political science;
meby God
then, of course, they found themselves in opposition to the
dieval attitude which accepted
its
institutions as given
to the church. The medieval monarch ruled by divine right. In
England, where the Puritan government was to be a regime of
sense, it was still assumed that the form of the state was determined from without. With the revolution this form was
brought within the rational power of man himself in society so
that institutions could be criticized and discussed to determine
what they were designed to accomplish, and to see how far they
did accompHsh what they set out to do.
This general attitude is rationalistic, and is expressed spethose of Hobbes,
cifically in three accounts of government
Locke, and Rousseau. These are roughly dated about as follows: Hobbes about the time of the Puritan Revolution; Locke
by that which passes in English history as the Revolution, that
is, the disturbance in which the Stuarts were sent across the
channel and Parliament brought over William and Mary as the
sovereigns of England; and Rousseau by the French Revolution.
The work of these three men undertakes to justify these
revolutions. In one sense, of course, the doctrine of Hobbes
is
not a justification of revolution.
criticism of
it.
But
in criticizing
it
On
the contrary,
Hobbes attempted
it
is
to go
back to a study of human nature and to discover from that
study what sort of a state ought to exist. He does not go outside of that which man's reason can compass in order to account for the institution. The result which he reached as a
consequence is much like that of the medieval community.
From Hobbes's point of view every human being is necessarily
selfish, seeking for what he wants; and this brings to the community an inevitable conflict between all the individuals who
are seeking
what they want. When they seek the same thing,
is given by Hobbes in his Levia-
they are at war. This picture
[14]
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
than. [The conception of the state arises out of the social contract.
own
The
individual has natural rights, which spring from his
impulses and desires. But
one gathered together a group
of such individuals and the desires of all were set into operation, one would find that the different people would often desire
the same thing and would come to blows. A community established upon the basis of natural rights would lead to what
Hobbes called "a war of all against all." It was because of this
anticipated result that he advocated the absolute monarch. This
was the Leviathan;
it
if
was not the absolute monarch that be-
longed to the catholic tradition, the tradition of Christendom,
but one set up by individuals who were unable to agree with one
The individual was, from Hobbes's point of view, too
another.
entirely individualistic for the success of
state.
Yet you
any but an autocratic
find in him, in his reason, the principle of social
organization.
This seems actually to have been the result of the attempts
made
Men
in the revolution to establish a state
on a rational
basis.
out with one another; there was turmoil, internecine
warfare; and the final solution was found in the Leviathan, in the
fell
form of Napoleon, who took all the power into his own hands.
that seemed to be the only solution that could be presented
And
at the time.]^
Going from Hobbes
view of
to Locke,
human
we
find that the latter
He
had a
assumes that property, for
example, arises naturally from man's adding value to natural
objects by means of his own labor. If an individual has added
this value to the natural object, then it becomes his property.
And Locke assumed that men will recognize this as regards the
product not only of their own labor but also of the labor of
others. He assumes that man is naturally social, that he has an \/
interest in the good of others since all are found in social relationships with each other in their families and their neighborhood. So from Locke's standpoint there is material for the building up of a society based upon human nature. What is needed
different
nature.
'
Taken from student notes of
the
Summer Quarter
[15]
of 1928.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
some sort of an impartial authority, which all will
overcome the disputes which will arise over propover the rights of individuals in their social relations. But
primarily
is
recognize, to
erty,
he assumes that, if these disputes are settled from a standpoint
which all recognize, this authority will also be recognized. It is
the court, then, that
human
is
society, a court
really central in Locke's conception of
which
will settle disputes in
with the accepted principles that are to be found
nature
accordance
in
human
itself.
When we reach Rousseau, we have a somewhat different
approach to the problem. It is an approach which was determined by the political situation in France. The authority
there lay entirely with the monarch. All powers came back to
him, and all the authority which the different administrators of
the state exercised came from the king. He was the monarch,
and everyone else was a subject of the monarch. Rousseau approached the problem from the current fiction of a social contract in order to see
how
which the authority could
king, as the
monarch
in
community could be
established in
rest in the people themselves.
The
France, was proving inadequate to the
task which belonged to him. For example, he maintained orders
which served no function
in the
community and which had
the privileges of the old feudal caste.
Among
was that of high taxation. The king was unable
all
these privileges
to rid the state
of this incubus. There were advances in the administration of
the community, but it was still unsatisfactorily administered
and was criticized by the active intellects of the time. This was
done indirectly, for example, by Montesquieu in his Esprit des
lois, a special study of the old Roman order and of the English
order which serves as a critique of the orders which existed in
France.
But could the authority be brought back
to the people
them-
selves? This idea presented the seeming paradox of people being
both sovereign and subject, and this Rousseau undertook to
solve. How can the people be both? The answer he presents to
this
is
that the people
may
be sovereign in so far as they exercise
I
16
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
a volonte generale.
sovereign.
On
If they exercise this general will, each
the other hand, each
is
is
He
can be both
obeys the laws which the general
will enacts.
subject and sovereign
the will of the community.
if his will is
a subject in so far as he
This assumption, as over against Hobbes's, is that there can
be such a general will, that a man as an individual in the community can act not simply as a representative of himself or for
himself but for the whole community if his will is identical with
the will of the other members of the community. This not only
common
which were emphasized by
Locke, but it presupposes that the very form of the will which
man exercises is universal, that is, a man wills something only in
so far as he puts himself in the place of everyone else in the community and in so far as he accepts the obhgations which that
act of will carries with it. A striking illustration of this is found
in property. If one wills to possess that which is his own so that
he has absolute control over it as property, he does so on the
assumption that everyone else will possess his own property
and exercise absolute control over it. That is, the individual
presupposes
wills his control
interests,
over his property only in so far as he wills the
same sort of control for everyone else over property.
That represents the difference between the attitude of a rational being in a society and that of the man whose strength or
is able to hold on to something. When the latter wills
on to something, he does it despite everyone else. It is
his by his strong arm. He does not will that others shall maintain possession of their property. On the contrary, he is ready
to take things away from everyone else. To will to hold on to
what he has on the basis that might is right is to will to deprive
everyone else of his property just in so far as he has the opportunity to get it. There is a fundamental difference between
these two acts of volition. To will on the basis of power threatens everyone else in the community with the loss of that which
he has, because the power of one person is greater than that of
another. On the other hand, when a person comes forward
and says, "This property is mine, I propose to maintain it as
cunning
to hold
[17]
THOUGHT
IN
property," he can do
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
he can present evidence
that it is his property on bases which everyone else recognizes; it is property only in so far as everyone's possessions are
property. In this sense property is something universal. The
it
only
in so far as
type of possession guaranteed by might is quite particular.
There can be, then, a type of volition which is not, as Hobbes
conceived of
it,
what one
which belongs to the
individual in the sense of grasping for
wants. It can be a
individual in the
demand simply
same sense
for that
as the
same
sort of possession be-
longs to everyone else. What one wants is possession guaranteed
by the community itself. He wants property; he does not want
mere possession. Possession may be nine-tenths of the law, but
does not become valuable unless it is the law. One cannot call
upon the community to support it, cannot depend upon the init
stitutions of the
community
to
back
his claim, unless that pos-
session does constitute the law, unless that sort of possession
on
him property rights. A comwhich the voHtions of the different members would be
the part of anyone else would give
munity
in
of this universal character would, in the nature of the case, be
one made up of both sovereigns and subjects. The volition of
each would be the volition of all in so far as his acts were universal, not simply because they happen to agree, but because
what they set up is that which is guaranteed by all. What
makes property extremely valuable in the community is that it
does give to each man a right which everyone else recognizes,
which no one can take away. If the volitions of the members of
the community take on the form of rights which are acknowledged and recognized by everyone, the community is made up
of individuals who are both sovereign and subject.
Of course,
there are details in the doctrine of the Contrat social
which call for discussion. This conception of the universal will,
which could be the will of the individual and yet the will of all
the community, is of one which is universal not simply because of the number of people who get together and who
have the same ideas but because that which is willed is
willed by everyone in the community; it is because what is
[i8]
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
willed gets its value through
other words, this
is
its
being the
common
the nature of a right as such, and
it
will.
In
does not
On the other hand, we see in the
such
thing
as a right which does not carry
case of property no
exist unless this
with
it
is
recognized.
necessarily certain obligations.
right without at the
same time
nize other people's property.
One cannot
assert his
asserting his obHgation to recog-
One cannot
assert his rights to
property without at the same time recognizing his duties toward
that property. Otherwise it will not be property but mere possession; mere possession is not property.
Again, if one seeks for enhghtenment, he seeks that for which
he realizes all others must also seek. He is trying to find that
which has meaning for everyone, that which has value only in so
far as it
is
generally received, generally recognized.
What
are
community which is ignorant of
work of art in a community
?
What
value
of
a
great
them
is the
which is bHnd to it? What is the meaning of enlightenment in
general? If everyone is bound down by superstition, what is the
the so-called laws of nature to a
good of one's own private enlightenment
else? Education, which, of course,
is
if it
exists for
no one
the source of enlighten-
ment, must be general if it is to have the value which ought to
belong to it. One may, of course, exist in a class by himself to
which other classes are subservient, not a part of his own community. But in so far as one has social relations with others,
one's own enlightenment has value for him only to the extent
that it is shared by others who have social relationships with
him. If you are in the midst of a stampede of cattle, it is of no
use for you to know the purpose of their stampede. They do not
know it themselves. An enlightenment has no value unless it
is universal.
Of course, one may use the ignorance of others
for one's own advantage. But enlightenment as a social affair
must be universal to have any meaning.
The values which lie behind the organization of the institutions of the community must be universal values; and in so
and makes
what Rousseau called a
far as the will of individuals confirms these values
them the
basis of those institutions,
[19]
it is
THOUGHT
volonte generale.
of majorities.
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
This principle does not go back to a simple rule
rule of majorities may be the most satisfac-
The
means we have of expressing this general will, but it will be
a faulty one at best. If we seek for an expression of what we
mean by this, we find it in what is called "public opinion," that
tory
is,
that attitude which
make up
is itself
a universal attitude,
the character of the individual.
When
which goes to
is an effec-
there
tive pubHc opinion, one that really expresses the attitude of
everyone in the community, one recognizes it as one that has
and will have authority. It may be that such a universal opinion
cannot be reached. Or it may be that enhghtened individuals
within the community can recognize what is the meaning of the
social situation, can bring it home to the consciousness of the
people in the community, enlighten them, and thus give leadership. We may have to muddle along with a very inadequate expression of such a general will, but we assume that the authority
of our institutions lies in the rational nature of the individuals
which make up society. This point of view we have taken over
from the revolution. We do not assume that the institution depends upon an outside authority. We do not assume that human
beings have been trained in certain habits, like trick animals in
a circus. We assume that there flow from man's own rational
nature judgments and volitions which are or can be universal
in character, and that it is this which makes human institu-
tions possible; that
one
wills for himself
what he
wills for every-
one; that one obeys the voHtions of others because he identifies them with his own volitions. That is what lies back of
what we call, in general, democratic institutions. The form of
democracy is not essential to the doctrine. What is essential is
the assumption that
nize that their
tical
own
men
are sufficiently enlightened to recog-
volitions in great social matters will be iden-
with those of others
who
are so enhghtened that
when one
such things as property, enlightenment, and security, these
things will be recognized as public ends which are also the ends
wills
of the individual.
for himself
what
is
As
a result of this, the individual will will
good
for others.
[20l
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
Back of
this point of
sense a man's
view lay the doctrine of
own voHtions
rights. In this
give laws for society, and only in so
do give laws for society is a
society possible which does not depend upon some external
authority. Tjiis is a society in which the individual is the source
far as the individual's volitions
of the institutions.
society
is
possible in the sense of the old
by force. Such
but a society which springs from the citizen
empire, the ancient world, a society estabhshed
a society
.
himself
possible,
is
is
possible only in so far as the citizen can give laws for
the community; and he can give laws only to the extent that his
volitions are an expression of the rights
which he recognizes
in
others, only in so far as he expresses the volition of others be-
cause they affirm rights which the others recognize in him to the
extent that he affirms
them
for himself.
The rights which Rousseau recognized are few
They are those which gather about property, about
in
number.
the simplest
such as the family, the rights of education,
and the general right of liberty, that which is embodied in our
Declaration of Independence.
/-liberty became the slogan for the French Revolution. It;
social institutions
was naturally the gathering ground
trary authority. It carried with
were
you
their interests
free,
see, is
what
interests of
men
is
it
in the fight against arbi-
the assumption that,
would be
common
interests.
implied in the conception of rights
are, after all,
common
if
men
That,
that the
Even such an
common interest when
interests.
becomes a
one recognizes it as property. If v/hat one wants is not simply
possession but property, then one wants something that is universal, because that which he wants involves his recognition of
the possession of property by others. That is, he wants that
which is recognized by everyone; and of course he can demand
interest as that of possession
that of others only in so far as he recognizes their property
rights.
What
is
essential for a
community
is
common
interests.
This was represented in the slogans of the French Revolution,
not simply by liberty, but by the others equality and frater-
nity.
These
all
imply that the interests of men are
[21]
common
THOUGHT
interests, that that
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
which one person wants
is
something which
other persons want and which, at the same time, he wants them
to have.
Now
that can be formulated, as John Stuart Mill later formu-
lated the idea of liberty, in the assumption that one wants free-
dom
of action on his
own
part in so far as
it will
not interfere
with freedom of action on the part of other people. This
is somecannot be put into a clear-cut formula as is the
case with property, yet it lies behind most of our judgments in
our demand for freedom of action. A person is free to act providing he does not tread on someone else's toes. One wants freedom, but he should ask only for that which he is willing to grant
to others. If he asks for the opportunity to express himself, he
what vague;
must
at the
it
same time recognize the
rights of others to express
themselves, and his freedom must not encroach upon the free-
dom
of others.
One can make
culty
is
to give
a general statement out of this; but the
it
in clear-cut outlines, to
make
it
diffi-
clear just
freedom is. We can discover it in certain cases,
freedom of the ballot, of the vote; freedom of expression, of speech. In these cases you can make a definite
statement that that which you want you must recognize in the
rights of others. But if one attempts to make it the basis for the
order of society, one will find that it is negative, not positive.
Possession is positive. And if you ask that your possession
should be the sort which you recognize in everyone else, then
you can formulate it in the law of property, as it has been formulated in all communities in one way or another, and, of course,
more exactly in the more highly civilized communities. But it is
very difficult to start off with a conception of freedom and make
it the basis for the organization of society, for the concept is in
itself negative, asking simply that the individual shall be free
from restraint. But you have to recognize that you cannot ask
for freedom if that freedom will put you in the position of
enslaving someone else, of encroaching upon his freedom of
what
this sort of
as in the
action.
[22
FROM RENAISSANCE TO REVOLUTION
Turning
to the conception of equality,
but
difficult doctrine,
Freedom taken by
it
we have
more
still
does, at least, have positive content.
Equality
itself is negative.
is
the doctrine
same poHtical standing
that each person shall have at least the
may, of course, be carried over from
the political to the economic field, where we demand that every
person shall have the same property as another. It can even be
taken over into other fields, in which, however, it is more difficult to define. But in the field of politics one can define it in
terms of the right to vote and the counting of votes so that one
person shall count for one and only one. That is something that
as every other person. It
can be stated
racy
is
in positive fashion, in
terms of democracy. Democ-
the rule of counted votes, and consequently the rule of
the majority. This
is
and
a simple conception
quality of a political character
that
in
in
it,
in the appli-
we come back
cation of the revolutionary principles,
to
which each individual
counts for one and only one and which, in the exercise of the
vote, the counting of a ballot, leads to
jority.
The
government by the ma-
question then remains, of course, as to whether this
conception,
if it is
so simple, can be
organization of the community.
The
made
the basis for the
rule of the majority
which
this leads to is
not necessarily the rule of the community. Fifty-
one per cent
a majority, but
is
desires of the
ment. Yet
getting at
it
community
may
does not necessarily express the
comes back
is
an external state-
be the best working method that
what does represent the
The remaining
It
it
as a whole. It
will of the
idea, that of fraternity,
we have
for
community.
more gene ral.
is still
to the attitude of neighborliness, the identifica-
tion of ourselves with others, a
common
emotional interest in
comes under the general term "sympathy." It is
it is only under very exceptional conditions that
becomes universal. These are just the conditions which a uni-
others. This
very vague, and
it
versal religion undertakes to establish. It can establish
in certain
ways,
in certain periods,
but the conception
back. In so far as
is
all
one to which
it
only
under particular conditions;
all
universal religions
come
are creatures of one creator, in so far as
[23]
all
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
are children of one father, belonging, therefore, to a single family,
we
get this conception of fraternity.
But we can
and elaborate are the conditions by which
it is
see
how
varied
universalized. It
has been true in religion, as elsewhere, that people have to depend upon their sense of hostility to other persons in order to
identify themselves with their
found to be
much
too vague to
own group. This idea has been
be made the basis for the organ-
ization of the state.
24
CHAPTER
II
KANTTHE PHILOSOPHER OF THE
REVOLUTION
ROUSSEAU'S
I have stated in as brief
had a very great influence on
the development of his doctrine. As I have
conception, which
a fashion as possible,
-
Kant,
in
indicated, Rousseau's Contrat social
yj3.s
really the gospel of the
French Revolution. It was good rhetoric and took hold on great
groups of people. It was simply stated, so that the ideas could
pass into untrained minds. His abstract idea that the rights
of all the individuals in the community were the basis of the
state, was put into common terms. If you can put the action of
the state in terms of the rights of individuals, you can make the
members of the state both subject and sovereign, and it is not
whom
necessary to set up a monarch in
all
Hobbes
rights rest.
talked about natural rights, but they were only the rights of
might. Such rights would
man
if
there
was
to be
all
have
any order
handed over to a single
the state. But rights which
to be
in
are acknowledged and which have value only in so far as they
are acknowledged, rights which carry with
them the condition
of obligations, can be enacted only in a democratic community.
If the people want property, then they want that which everyone recognizes, which everyone in some sense possesses, which
everyone wishes to maintain. This conception, of course, can
be carried over from property to other institutions in the community. In that sense it can be made universal. This character
of the community is something which flows from the character
of human nature itself, from its rational character. Rousseau
said that rights, in this sense, are universal, that
In so far as the voHtions of the
they can be
made
What Kant
the laws for
community
is,
rational.
are in these terms,
all.
did was to go a step farther and say that
[25]
all
our
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
volitions should be of this
same universal
eralized the position of Rousseau; he
character.
made
it
He
gen-
the basis of his
moral philosophy. Rousseau indicated that the legislation of the
community should have the form of the expression of rights.
In so far as it did have that form, it made political structure
possible. Kant went on to say that every act which a rational
being carries out should take on this universal form. For him
morality, as such, consists in giving a universal character to
every act. In so far as an act does not have this character, it is
amoral. That is, if a man seeks for something which he does
not at the same time recognize as lying within the pursuit of
vX
he seeks something simply for himself, he is, to
Kant undertook to identify this
doctrine with the Golden Rule. His position was that man, in
other persons,
if
that extent, selfish, immoral.
his social nature, could give laws to society in so far as his
a universal end. What this means has been illusthrough
the concept of property as over against mere
trated
own end was
possession.
Rousseau referred
to those situations
which gather about
property, which gather about the defense of the
against the power that attacks
community
from the outside, about the
and rights of enlightened education. He selected those rights which everyone
recognized and insisted that in the community these ought to be
universal in character. They should be universal because it is
only in so far as they are universal that they have any value.
An enhghtenment that is confined to a single mind only, which
cannot be maintained over against another person on the basis
of a rationally accepted doctrine, is of no value, is not truth.
A thing is true if it is in such a form that you can convince
it
institution of the family, about the duties
another rational person that it is true; otherwise it is not true.
family would have no meaning unless the relations of the
father and mother and children were relations which were recog-
nized by the
relations of
community
itself as a
men and women and
they were the same for
all
means of ordering the
inter-
the care of children, and unless
members of
[26]
the community.
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
_
ant went on to say that every act which is moral should
on this universal form. He put this in the form of a cate-
So act that the maxim of your action can,,^^
That is, act in every case as you do
When you demand that you should
property.
reference
to
with
have possession of your own property, you are demanding that
everyone else should have possession of his own property. This
should be the basis of all conduct, and on this basis Kant
founded his moral theory. He undertook to show that the
human being could be a lawgiver because he is rational; could
gorical imperative:
be
made
a universal law.
be a sovereign because he
rational, because
is
a universal character to his volitions.
he can give
Everyone would then be
a lawgiver, but only in so far as he took account of the duties
would also be subject to
the laws that he himself gave. Man's intellect, in proportion
arising out of his volitions so that he
as
it is
rational,
is
a lawgiving intellect. It can create society
In this sense, because he generalized this principle of Rousseau's, Kant may be considered
by being universal
in character.
the philosopher of the revolution.
We
have seen how Rousseau's principle was generalized by
Kant
into his categorical imperative, in the affirmation that the
individual should
make
a general principle out of the
maxim
One should ask himself,
on the point of willing anything, whether he can also
will that everyone else should will the same thing under the
same conditions. Then he would discover whether or not his
volition is universal. For example, if one wills to tell a lie, if
he asks himself if he would will that everyone under the same
of his act, to use Kant's terminology.
when he
is
would lead to
evident contradiction, because, if everyone should lie under
those same conditions, then no one would believe anyone else
and there would thus be no purpose in the he.
What I have been trying to bring out is that the will of the
community must take on some such form as that expressed in
terms of property. It has to have an economic statement of
some such form as that. It is that which makes the will of the
conditions should
tell
lie,
he
will see that this
[27]
THOUGHT
IN
individual the will of
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
all,
the volonte generale. If you get that sort
of an expression, you have the basis for the organization of the
community. And Kant, as we have seen, tried to reach this
simply by making it the basis for a moral doctrine. That is,
Kant said, if you could make your act formally right, it
would also be right in content. And the illustration he gives
is his best illustration; it is that you cannot make a lie right
because you cannot make a lie universal; it contradicts itself.
You have that turned around the other way in the statement
of the Cretans. They had a bad reputation as to veracity in
the ancient world. It was said, "All Cretans are liars." But
suppose the statement that all Cretans are liars is made by a
Cretan. He belongs to the group that are liars. Therefore his
statement about the Cretans is a lie and the Cretans are not
all liars. That is, the proposition runs into a contradiction.
Kant conceived that you could use such a rule as that to determine all moral conduct. All you have to do is to try to make
the maxim of your act the truth for everyone under the same
conditions. The result seems to be that one should use this
universality of one's act as a test of
its
morality. This
is
Kant's
assumption, that
if
you would only make your act universal
you could
If
it
test
it.
involves a contradiction,
Kant did not succeed
reference to lying. There are
is
not immoral. Sometimes
case of the
someone.
man who
We
it is
wrong.
He did not succeed even with
many situations in which lying
in that.
it is
highly moral, as in the typical
deceives an assassin trying to murder
talk about morality in warfare, and, of course,
your enemy. The
general, the military strategist, succeeds by deceiving his
enemy. And then we have the whole list of white lies that we
always tell cases where we feel we are justified in deceiving a
person who insists on knowing something he has no right to
know, where we give a reason which is good but which is not
the real reason, in order to save somebody's feelings. There are
all grades between the whiteness of truth and the blackness of
lying. It is not possible to draw a hard and fast line between
warfare
is
game in which you have
[28
to deceive
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
them. If everyone insisted on telling the truth
society itself would perhaps
tried to
work out other matters on the
gorical imperative, such as the case of a
mit suicide
and
disease
or the case of the
I
the time,
principle of the cate-
man who wants
to
com-
order to relieve himself from suffering from a
in
his friends
competence,
all
become impossible. When Kant
from the care they
man who
is
too lazy to
think the principle broke
What Kant was
will have to give him,
work although he has
down
appealing to were values.
sidering simply the universal form.
He was
pretty definitely.
He was
not con-
considering also
what the values are that give significance to life. These were
what Kant really came back to. What the problem is, then,
to come back to my former position, is to give a universal
form to the interests of man in society. We can do that in the
very abstract case of property in such a form that that which
you possess is something which you want every other person to
the desire to have
community. We say
the person has a stake in the community. He cannot want to
preserve that which he has without at the same time willing
that others should preserve what they have. So the conservative who wants to keep the present order is anxious for a relatively wide distribution of property so that everyone, having
a definite stake in the preservation of that order, will also want
to preserve it. The interests of such a community must be universal in their character, which means that they shall be of
such a form that when a person wills something for himself he
is willing the same for others.
possess.
property
familiar illustration of that
itself
widely distributed
But, of course, the difficulty
It
is
is
in the
in stating that specifically.
can be stated, as we have seen,
in relation to property and
by the spreading of enlightenment.
a community where it has universal
also with reference to truth
Truth
is
valuable only in
acceptance. If a thing
not function as true
nize
it if
is
not recognized as true, then
in the
they are going to
it
does
community. People have to recogact on it. For example, we expect
a person to be familiar with the laws of the
[29]
community
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the essential, fundamental principles.
People have to be
fa-
mihar with these and recognize them as universal. We are
anxious to have universal education so that everyone may
recognize the operation of natural laws. We depend on other
persons knowing what we know. Otherwise knowledge has no
advantage. Of course, I can get special advantage by knowing
something in advance of someone else as regards the stock
market; but in order to get advantage from even that type of
information, it must become part of the knowledge of others as
well. If I shut away my knowledge, I might get a certain satisfaction out of knowing something that would be of value if
others knew it; but to give it actual value it has to become a
part of the knowledge of all. There is a story of Frederick the
Great, who was much beset by people who wanted honors given
them. One man in particular, whom Frederick did not consider
worthy, requested a particularly desired post. Finally he was
told, "You can have this post on one condition." The man
said that he would take it under any condition, and the emperor
said, "I will grant you a privy counselorship, but under the condition that you shall never tell anyone of it at any time." The
value of holding an office is in its recognition by other persons.
So the knowledge which you have is of value only in so far as
it is
universal in character
everyone
will
accept
it.
only
The
in so far as,
being affirmed,
perfect form of your knowledge
is
that you can put it to proof; it is that which everyone everywhere must accept. That is the ideal, although it may never
be reached with reference to truth; but that is the goal toward
which knowledge proceeds.
What our different states undertake to do, so far as they are
democratic, is to give rights which shall be universal in their
character. Our laws try to state the rights and the privileges
of individuals in such a form that they are universal not that
everyone now possesses them equally, but that everyone under
the same conditions would have the same rights.
But Kant took this position not only in regard to man's
will in society, that
is,
that
man
[30]
gives laws to society through
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
the extension of his will; he also affirmed that
man
gives laws
Pure Reason he approached this
principle from another angle and carried it much further. There
Kant undertook to show how it is possible for us to build what
he called "synthetic judgments a priori." The beginning of that
is that one should be able to state that a straight hne is the
shortest distance between two points. There you have a proposition in which "straight line" is subject and "shortest distance
between two points" is predicate. You can analyze the idea of
"straight line," and you will not find in it that of the shortest
distance between two points; and you can analyze "the shortest distance between two points," and this will not convey the
idea of "straight line." Yet, you make the judgment that a
straight line is the shortest distance between two points. This
is a synthetic judgment because it puts together ideas which are
not already contained in each other. When you say that man is
a rational animal, you have already defined man as rational,
and it is no great trick to ascribe the same predicate that you
already have in the subject. That is an analytic judgment.
But the synthetic goes further than the analytic. It takes two
ideas, neither of which is contained in the other, and affirms
to nature. In his Critique of
that these ideas belong together.
But where do we
sertion?
Critique of
because
get our intellectual authority for this as-
How are synthetic judgments
a priori possible? In the
Pure Reason Kant contends that they are a
in this connection, as in the categorical
priori
imperative, he
came back to a type of experience which determined in advance
what the forms of things should be. This lies both in the forms
of space and time and in those of the understanding, that is, the
logical forms. Those which belong to the sensations he called
the "aesthetic," and those which belonged to the understanding
he termed the "judgment." In this division, and in the argument
that flows from it, Kant was trying to meet the skepticism of
Hume. He said that Hume had wakened him from his dogmatic slumber.
Hume's skepticism
said that
all
[31]
our knowledge seems to be
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
simply an organization of our impressions and ideas impressions meaning sensations, and ideas mainly images. Sensations,
as such, are simply the states of our own consciousness. Locke
had recognized this in regard to secondary qualities color,
sound, taste, and odor. These do not belong to the object
outside; and if they convey those characters to the object, we
ought to recognize that they come from us. Berkeley went a
step farther and said this relation was true not only of secondary qualities but also of primary qualities of extension, of motion, and of solidity
that is, of those qualities pertaining to the
occupancy of space. When one feels of a desk, one gets a sense
of
its solidity, its
extension, and
a feeling of the individual. It
tween
this sensation
is
its
mobility.
But
this
is
just
impossible to distinguish be-
and that of the color of the desk, as sensa-
Locke admitted that the color did not belong to the desk
but was simply an impression made upon us through light that
reaches us from the desk. Berkeley says its extension is just
tions.
another impression of the same kind.
In other words, Berkeley,
went
a step farther than
who
is
called a subjective idealist,
Locke and said that the world of
nothing but a world of our impressions.
He
ex-
asked
tension
is
why we
should assume that this spatial order, which comes to
us both through vision and the sense of touch, should not be regarded as relative to our sensitivities as well. What is the space
about us but the impressions made upon us of things that we
will say are ordered in a certain fashion? What evidence have
we that that which causes these impressions has any other character than that given in our experience? We say that a vibration of a certain amplitude is responsible for the color red. That
is, red is the feeling or the experience which we have when the
retina is hit by those particular vibrations. With another vibration you have the impression of violet. Well, Berkeley asked,
why should we assume that that which causes in us the sensation
of extension is extended, if that which causes in us a sensation
of red is not itself red? If this latter is not the case, why should
that which causes in us impressions of extension in three dimen-
[32]
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
any reason
any particular authority to the primary qualities
which we deny to the secondary qualities? And being sure that
the answer to that question was in the negative, he went on to
seek what the cause of our impression could be and, being a
sions itself be extended in three dimensions? Is there
for giving
bishop, found
it is
who produces
the Deity
in us sensations of
not extended. Berkeley was very
such
a power, for he said that there
that
there
must
be
sure
could be no effect without a cause and that our attitude toward
extension though he himself
is
these impressions, whether primary or secondary,
attitude. Therefore,
it
could not be a cause.
a passive
is
No man
can create
The sunset is there. One can recall sunsets he has
number of them, and picture in his imagination some-
a sunset.
seen, a
thing that he has never seen on land or sea; but the pigments
he uses are those which he has taken from past experience.
Man
is
passive with regard to these sensuous experiences; there-
fore the cause of
them must
lie
outside of him, in God, said
Berkeley.
Hume
pushes on and asks where Berkeley gets his evidence
His only answer is that we have been in the habit
of expecting things to happen in the future in the same order as
for causation.
they have happened in the past.
in the past,
and we expect
it
The sun has
to continue to
do
risen regularly
so.
But the only
result we can reach from analysis is the juxtaposition of two
events, sunrise and sunset, so that if one has uniformly succeeded the other we expect this succession to continue in the
future. In other words, Hume, in his turn, went one step farther
than Berkeley, and asked him what evidence he had that there
must be a cause. Why could not these things just happen? He
analyzed the concept of causation, and what he found was that
we expect those things to succeed each other which have suc-
ceeded each other
in the so-called
in the past.
That was
"law of causation."
all
Hume
If things
have succeeded
each other in the past in a certain uniform way, then
this relation to
continue in the future. If that
be found out about the law of causation,
[33]
it
could find
is
we expect
all
that can
does not take us
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
all. Locke assumed that we could
go outside of our experience of color and sound into a world of
moving physical particles which cause such impressions as those
of color and sound. Berkeley assumed that we could get outside
of our experience of an extended matter to a God which caused
in us the experience that we called an experience of extended
matter. Hume showed that the law of causation, which led
Locke to say that vibrations from outside produced in us a cer-
outside of our experience at
and that led Berkeley to asmust be produced by God,
of experience and that there is no way of getting out-
tain succession of color or sound,
sume that
lies
inside
the sensation of extension
side of that experience.
Hume also undertook to show that the so-called "self" is nothing but an association of certain groups of our impressions, our
which come to us
from our own body, and those which are associated with certain
other impressions, such as our own name, get firmly linked
together. But that is nothing but another object, another thing.
It is the most important thing in our experience, but it arises
states of consciousness; that especially those
as
any other object
arises.
From
the standpoint of empirical
philosophy this task involved nothing but the organization of a
certain succession of color, of form, of feel, so organized together
when you
that
see a color
We see these in different
what
differently,
the past.
you naturally think of a certain
situations,
and we
when they impress us some-
recall experiences that
Our organization of
feel.
these qualities
is
were true in
such a per-
in
manent fashion that they become, for us, a fixed object. Hume
assumed that the self arose also in this fashion. The baby has
sensations pleasure and pain, warmth. The sensations from
his own body get associated together. If he moves his arms, he
gets certain sensations; if he moves his arms again, he gets the
same sensations. These get permanently organized together,
particularly about the sensations which are pleasurable and
The infant finds itself addressed by certain words, cernames. Certain experiences come when it responds in a cer-
painful.
tain
tain fashion.
Out of
this arises the association of a set of ex-
[34]
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
periences which
make another
fant comes to call the
self.
object, an object which the in-
He
identifies it
with the "I," the
"me." From that standpoint there is no functional relationship
between the subject and the object. The subject is simply another object. It is a central object about which the experiences
of the individual develop. But there are other objects which
also become central under other conditions. Over against this
Kant brought
empirical conception
tal
in the idea of a
transcenden-
self which was a sort of functional unity. But the empiricist
comes back to the experience of a self. And the empiricist assumes that in order that there may be an object, there must be a
subject. The two involve each other. For Kant this subject-object relationship, however,
is
not static;
it is
not such a relation-
ship as that spoken of in which certain impressions are
the mind, in which physical things in
consciousness which
lies
made on
some fashion impress
inside the mind. It
is
not that sort of a
which we have one phase of a process
necessarily leading to another phase, and that phase leading
back to the first. This is the typical situation in a subjectrelationship, but
one
in
object relationship.
The
position which
Kant took was
more or
less
natural
development of the position reached by the English empiricists.
Their result was skeptical, at least it was in Hume's statement. He undertook to show that there could be no knowledge
of an object. Objects as such were broken up into sensations
and images, or impressions and ideas, to use his words. He
analyzed objects simply into a set of these impressions and
ideas, and the connections between them were those of associa-
The connectivity then also belonged to experience, and,
for Hume, was psychological in character. That is, there is no
way of getting from these impressions and ideas over to an obtion.
outside of them and is supposed to be the cause
analyzed the idea of causation and carried it back
to the simple expectancy that the succession of impressions and
ject
which
of them.
lies
He
ideas that has taken place in the past shall continue in the
future.
He
could find no ground for this except in a habit, a
[35]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
habit which he recognized as being so strong that
avoid acting upon
But
it.
in
we could not
no way could we get outside of
impressions and ideas.
Kant's reaction against skepticism was against the skepticism
of Hume. What Hume had pointed out was that the world
which
arises in experience
We
is
relative to the sensitivity of the
world of color, sound, taste, and odor.
But the world has color and sound only if the individual has
normal vision and hearing. If we had other organs of taste
and smell, the world would have other tastes and odors. We
individual.
live in a
can readily conceive that if the structure of the retina were
different the world would have an entirely different set of colors.
We can live with a person who is color-blind without discovering
that fact. He refers to certain colors, which exist for us as
And
yellows, as reds.
there
is
no way of detecting
you can
find out that a certain color
world
relative to our
is
own
we
different for him.
sensitivities.
those particular sensitivities to
of those sensations, and
is
what we
by
by which
this except
a set of colored yarns in the psychological laboratory
We
call
Our
can go back of
the physical causes
can, for example, identify different
colors with certain rates of vibration which are not dependent
upon our sensitivity. So we can go back to something which we
assume to be there in independence of this relation to our eyes
and ears. We feel hot and cold, and our theory is that there is
simply a movement of molecules which are imperceptible to
vision or feeling except in the sense of temperature. But motion
is not the warmth that we feel, and the lack of motion is not
we
We
assume, also, that there is a world of
physical things that have mass, that move, that have a certain
shape and form characteristics which Locke called the "prithe cold that
feel.
mary
qualities,"
while
the
secondary qualities
belong only within our experience.
admittedly
But the former,
too,
can be stated in terms of our consciousness, as sensations,
and as the images of those impressions which Locke
"ideas."
The
result of the
called
.^
Humean
skepticism, which was the natural
[36I
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
product of this view, was to destroy the passage from a subjective world over to something outside. With this went all necessary science. Our concepts of the laws of causation, of substance and attribute, to mention only two, are found to be
nothing but associations of ideas, in the Humean sense of that
term. But science seems to dispute this, and Kant undertook to
justify the approach of science. He insists that there is such a
thing as science and such a thing as necessity. And he tries to
how
find out
these are possible.
We have, we will say,
the state-
two
Accept Euclid, and you have propositions starting off
with certain axioms and reaching certain results. We accept
ment of
a straight line being the shortest distance between
points.
Kant asks. How is this possible? He
we do accept them and that out of such propositions
these as necessarily true.
insists that
all
our necessary sciences
certain forms of the
mind
His answer is that there are
example, space with its
structure so that that which takes
arise.
itself
for
and time with its
must occur according to the forms of that mind in which
they appear. Mind, then, gives these forms and, to that extent,
gives laws to nature. In this way Kant reached the same posi-
structure,
place
tion in regard to nature at large that
he reached
human
mind that
society,
namely, that
it is
the
in
regard to
gives laws to
we see again that he was the philosopher of revoway around.
end the problem boils down to this: Is necessity
nature. So
lution all the
In the
possible within the world of experience?
Hume
says that causa-
supposed instance par excellence of necessity, must be
considered as simply a set of relations between different experiences. Kant agrees that our world is made up of such experiences. But, from the fact that we do live in a world of experiences, Hume drew the conclusion that there could be no
tion, the
such things as laws of nature because the most famous of them
all, that of causation, is nothing but a set of happenings, connections in our experience, in which one impression succeeds
another according to our habit of expectation. That
that
we have always found
is,
we say
that swans are white, and wherever
[37]
'
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
we find the form of a swan we find the white color; so we lay
down a law of nature that swans must be white. And then someone goes to Australia and finds black swans. All our laws of
nature are nothing but certain uniform associations, certain
experiences which are invariably connected with each other.
There may be a succession which is contrary to that. This is
what was found in a somewhat intricate sort of fashion in the
case of observations recently
made
stars during an eclipse. Light
is
in
regard to the position of
susceptible to changes in direc-
In so far as light offers such response to a change in direction, it has what the physicists call "mass." Now, mass can
tion.
The path of the
edge of the sun ought to be shifted
a certain amount, depending upon the mass of the sun and the
mass of the ray of light, and so forth. On the Newtonian basis,
be measured in accordance with Newton's laws.
light of a star passing the
you can
how much
figure out
it
ought to be
has another theory of gravitation.
He
shifted. Einstein
says that the
amount of
the shift ought to be twice that predicted on the Newtonian
theory.
On
The only
it was found that Einstein was right.
you have in this case are the position of the
its relation to the rim of the sun. By means
observation,
facts that
light of the star in
of photography this can be measured. All facts, the so-called
"data" of any subject, are nothing but certain experiences
that the observer has in their relation to each other. The
relation which is found at any given time on the basis of such
investigations may be found to be all wrong a few generations
later. In fact, we can be pretty sure this will happen. More
recent theories of scientists have replaced older theories. Certain facts remain the same, but the theories have been replaced.
Can there be any such thing as universahty and necessity
which belong to the laws of nature in a world which is a world
of experience, a world of certain uniformities.'' You ask a scientist what a law of nature is, and he says it is nothing but
a uniformity. But when you ask just where that uniformity
is found, the answer is that it is found in the experience of
men who observe. They have certain impressions, and they find
[3^
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
Can you have such a thing as universaland necessity under such a condition?
Hume says it is evident you cannot; your statement boils
down to the fact that certain things happen and you cannot tell
that others will not happen. But the fact that things have happened in a certain order forms in you and me the habit of expecting them to happen in that order. That is what the laws of
nature causation, for example are. Now Hume described the
world as a world of experience in which the so-called laws of.
njituXQ^SlQ nothing but our habits of expecting things to happen
in the future as they happened in the past. Berkeley accepted
Locke and went him one better; Hume accepted Berkeley and
went him one better; and Kant accepted Hume and went him
one better, but along a little different line.
What Kant pointed out was that we have in the mathematical
sciences results that are necessary and universal. Yet they bethat these are uniform.
ity
long to a world of experiences.
We
believe that the angles of a
two right angles, that a straight
shortest distance between two points, that seven and
triangle are equal to
twelve.
We
we should
believe these things, and,
still
answer
brie
for
is
five
make
other people did not,
we should call .the
Kant took the position that these things are
But how can they be necessarily true? Kant's
continue to believe them;
others irrational.
necessarily true.
if
the
line
that our minds give laws to nature. If there
is only
pantry and you know that there will be pudding
supper, you know, a priori, that it will have a certain form.
is
mold
in the
what Kant would call a piece of "transcendental logic."
You know in advance what form the pudding must take because
That
is
You can give a law which will
puddings that are to be as long as you can control
the number of molds there are in the kitchen. Well, similarly,
Kant said that what we call space and time are nothing but
forms of our sensibilities. The experiences that we have, then,
will take on the forms of space and time, and we can argue that
all the experiences we can possibly have must take on those
forms because they are the forms of the mind. And he also asthere
is
include
only one form available.
all
[39]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
"judgment," as he called has certain
other forms, which he called the "categories." The two most
important there were twelve altogether are those of subserted that the
mind
it
stance and causality. Anything that
we
sense in terms of space
and time, because these are the forms of our sensibilities, we
have to think of in terms of substance and attribute, and cause
and effect. We think of them in terms of substance and causality as well as in terms of space and time because we cannot help
it. The former are forms of the judgment; the latter are forms
of the sensibilities.
Kant had another faculty, that of "reason," whose function
was higher than
trying to do here
refer to the
either of the
is
two mentioned. But all I am
which Kant could
to point out the sense in
human mind
as giving laws to nature. Just as con-
trol over the molds can give laws of the form of puddings, so the
forms of the mind can give laws to any experience which man
may have. These laws are necessary and universal for all possible experiences. They do not go beyond experience, but they
can give laws for
necessity
all
possible experiences.
and universality within the
Hume had set up.
Thus Kant
finds
limits of a world of ex-
perience such as
Kant's affirmations in regard to these forms of space and
time have been somewhat shattered by the non-Euclidean
geometries.
is
He assumed
that the
sum
of the angles of a triangle
equal to two right angles and could not be otherwise.
We
know, of course, that a spherical triangle does not conform to
this law. But we can say that he was not talking about a curved
line triangle but of one composed of straight lines. But if the
space on the surface of a sphere can be curved, why cannot all
space be curved? In fact, we are living on the surface of a
sphere. Our ancestors had to find out that we were not living
on a plane. If a man at that time had followed the line of vision
and kept on going until he came back to the point where he
started, he would have been put up against it to explain it. Is
there any reason why the space which is curved on the surface
of the earth should not be curved throughout?
[40]
One
of the con-
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
ceptions given by mathematicians
is
that of a
moving
collection
of planes, stacked up one on top of another. Suppose
planes were curved ones, because
we know
all
those
certain geometries
work out this way, then the axiom that parallel lines will not
meet except at infinity has to be abandoned and we have different geometries based upon the theory that you can draw
more than one line parallel to another.
Kant's supposition was that he could get hold of the forms of
the mind in terms of which experience must be presented, and
that, if he could, then he could give universal and necessary
laws to nature. So, he conceived of man's mind as giving laws
to nature itself. The starting-point was that man's nature is
rational; therefore
it
can give laws to society, provided those
laws expressed man's rights.
conceived of
He
man
He
generalized this position and
as giving laws to nature as well as to society.
accepted Hume's statement that knowledge must
experience.
But what he
insisted
lie
within
upon was that there are nec-
essary objects in experience, that there
is
universality in
it.
And he undertook to show, by a transcendental solution, how
these things were possible. By "transcendental" Kant meant
that he could form, in advance of an experience, a judgment as
to
what that experience could
be.
It
was transcendent
in the
His explanation
sense that it
of this was, as we have seen, that the mind had certain forms
into which this experience must fall, so that one could be sure
in advance that our experience would be subject to the structure and laws of space and time, because these were forms of
our sensibility, and subject also to the categories of substance
and attribute, of cause and effect, because these are forms of
the judgment. We cannot think in other terms than these.
Therefore, these forms are given in advance of experience, and
they are necessarily given because everything that occurs in
experience must take on these forms. The result of this process
is what Kant would call an "object."
In this way Kant assumed that he had rescued science as a
source of universal and necessary knowledge. We have geometranscended the experience
[41]
itself.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
try because the form of space is a form of the sensibility. We
have laws of arithmetic because these are involved in the very
order of succession as given in time. We have the laws of the
understanding, those which give us substance and attribute,
cause and effect, those which give us necessity and probability.
These are what give us the universal and the particular. They
are all forms of the understanding, and any experience which
we have must take these forms. Of course, there is a large part
of our experience which is contingent for us. That is we cannot
tell, in advance, what colors, sounds, tastes, and odors we will
have; but we do know in advance that, whatever particular
ones they are, they must occur in a world of space and time,
for nothing can appear outside these forms of the sensibihty.
We do not know, in advance, what the substantial character of
an object will be; but we know that we cannot think except
in terms of substance and attribute. We have to think of a thing
as having substance; and its qualities, its characters, are attributes which inhere in that substance. We cannot tell in advance what the cause of an event will be, but we know in advance that every event must have some cause. So there is
given to us in the very forms of the mind the necessity and universality of laws, particularly those of mathematics and of
mathematical physics. And our empirical experience, the content
of our sensuous experience, will all fall into these forms. But
forms do not determine what the content will be. They determine
how we shall experience that content when we do experience
objects, but we cannot tell in advance what particular experience we shall have. We do know in advance what form it must
take, because the forms of experience are given to the world by
the mind itself. In that sense Kant could legitimately speak of
the mind giving laws to nature as well as to society. We have
already indicated how this later is accomplished through his
carrying-out of the doctrine of Rousseau.
This notion of Kant's came back to a very subtle and
somewhat obscure analysis of judgment. Kant asked why objects are units, and where that unity comes from. He ac-
[42]
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
cepted the
Humean
analysis of the object into
its
various ele-
ments. Take such an object as a tree or a house. You can
analyze it into the different experiences you have. Color, feel,
extension, all the different sensations are associated with each
other; but the house or tree or animal
is
something more than a
compiling of such impressions and images. It is a unit; it has a
certain unity. A heap of sand has very little, if any, unity. Of
course, you can regard it as a single thing, but you are more
apt to consider it as a conglomeration of separate grains of sand.
A house, however, has a perfectly definite unity. All the different parts belong together; they have a definite relationship to
one another, a relationship which arises from the uses to which
An
animal has a definite unity. It has varied
organs, but all these are organized in the unity of its lifeprocesses. It is a living thing in which all the parts have certain functions. Any object that is a thing has a certain unity,
and Kant's problem is to discover where that unity comes from.
the house
It
is
is
put.
not a mere sticking-together of
difl^erent pieces.
If
you
break an object up into sensations and ideas and then stick
them together by the law of association, you still do not get the
unity of the object.
Now Kant
He
could find only one source of unity in experience.
found this in the judgment, in the statement, "I judge that
this is such and such a thing; this is a house." That is, one
judges the house from the point of view of its uses. There are
the dining-room, the kitchen, the bedrooms, the drawing-room,
all
looked at from the point of view of the processes of living.
sees house, thinks house, perceives house, in terms of the
One
life
that goes on in relation to
it,
just as one sees, perceives,
and
thinks an animal in terms of the hfe-processes that take place
through
all its
organs. This unity
is,
as
Kant
insisted,
some-
thing more than a mere association together of one experience
after another. It
is
an organization, a holding-together of experi-
we
is,
We see
when
when we cannot grasp what it
ences within an experience of a certain form.
are confused by some object,
cannot make any unity out of
[43]
it, it is
that
only a set of different
THOUGHT
sensations.
takes
its
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Then suddenly we grasp
its
meaning and everything
place with reference to everything
what the organization
is,
else.
what the purpose of
You can
it is,
see
what the
it is. Well now, that grasping of these different elements, these different parts into a whole, as Kant conceived it,
is an act of judgment. I judge this to be a table. I judge the
object which I see outside the window to be a tree. I relate all
the different parts of the object to each other, relate them in
structure of
certain definite ways, spatially, temporally, in terms of sub-
stance and attribute, cause and effect.
organize these wholes
in the process of my perceiving them. One of the experiments
of the psychological laboratory is that of a dark box in which a
spark
is
introduced so that suddenly
when
the spark
is
there
get a confused picture of something on the side of the box.
you
Then
is made again and there is another spark,
and you get a sense of structure. After a number of repetitions
you see a perfectly distinct picture. You have organized what
you see into the relations of a landscape, of a cathedral, or
of a castle. You see it as a whole; you put it together. Our per-
the electric contact
ception
is
just such a process as that. It
is
different elements of experience together.
thing;
and then,
as soon as
we
an organizing of the
We
get a clue to a
get that clue, things
fall
into their
different relationships to each other.
Unity such as this, Kant said, is essentially that of judgment.
found even in perception. We look at an object in the distance which is somewhat confused through the misty air, and,
by putting our attention to it, we finally get an outline, such as
a house; and then we can see it more clearly, grasp it for certain
as a house. We are looking for the face of an acquaintance in a
crowd, and we can finally identify it. There is the image which
we have of that particular face. Our perception is a process of
organizing different elements into a whole. It always has a certain sort of unity. And this is more than the mere sum of the
parts. If you break up your perception into different elements
Hke parts of a jig-saw puzzle and simply match them up together, you do not get a picture. You must get them organized
It is
[44]
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
Someone organizes the different notes in a
in a certain way.
melody, and we get the whole of the melody. One organizes the
ideas which come, we will say, in an address which one is hearing; and they begin to take shape, they begin to have relationships to each other, and one gets the line of the argument. So,
also, one gradually grasps the plot of a play he is seeing. Our
knowledge is a process of relating different elements together
and giving unity to them. That unity, in Kant's conception,
comes back
^ack
of
to the
all
this high judge.
ponderous
judgment
perception, of
As he did
as such.
all
to
thought, of
most of
construction to this, calling
a priori unity of apperception."
something which
is
It
is
all
conception,
his ideas,
it
lies
Kant gave
the "transcendental
a priori because
given in advance of experience;
it is
it
is
trans-
imposed on, and not derived from, experience it is necessary. That is, our experience consists in
judging. So far as it is an experience, it is an experience of
things having a unity which does not come from the content
but from the process of experiencing, as in perception and
thought. It is something that is given in advance of the actual
experience. We do not know what things we are going to see;
but, if they are intelligible experiences, everything will have a
certain unity which comes from our experiencing it. So, the
cendental because
it is
transcendental unity of apperception, as
Kant conceives
it, is
not simply the association of one sensation or image with another but the organization of them of the appearance of a
face into that of an acquaintance, of the dim outHnes of an ob-
ject into a house. It
is
more than perception,
having sensations. Our perception
called
it
Now
is
in the sense of
a structure,
and Kant
"apperception."
this transcendental
unity of apperception, Kant said,
comes back to the fact of judgment, to an "I judge." Such an
I or "ego" that judges is, as we have seen, transcendental, that
is, something given in advance of perception. In Kant's earlier
speculation he spoke of a transcendental self that he conceived
of as being given in experience. But he was committed to find[45]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
ing objects only in experience.
Forms of experience could be
given in advance, but they do not become an object until the
latter actually appears in experience.
self
was
for
Thus,
this transcendental
Kant just a function of experience, not something
The transcendental self was not a thing. The
actually given.
selves of our experience are empirical.
We have
certain memories.
We have
We have certain
feelings.
feelings of our bodies, the
images we see of ourselves in the looking-glass. We have the
experience of our relationships to others, family relationships,
friendships, national relationships. All these just
They
are empirical.
They
happen
to us.
within experience. These selves
lie
are like other objects that appear in experience, tables, chairs,
and houses. They are empirical in character.
These empirical objects are there in experience, but they have
reference to something beyond themselves. Such a thing as this
table before me, Kant would say, just as it is, is made up out
of our sensations and our memories of experiences we have had
trees,
in the past of similar
wooden
surfaces. It
gether in the forms of space and time, that
sensibilities; it is
organized as substance.
is all
is,
organized to-
in the
We
will
forms of our
say that the
wood is a substance and that it has certain qualities. One type
of wood has one quality, and another type of wood has another
quality. The wood has certain relations, and these we organize
into a table. But we always imply that there is something which
lies behind this actual experience which we have of the table. We
have the actual experience of a table whenever we come into
the room, and it ceases when we leave the room. We remember
it and expect to have the same experience when we enter the
room again. We think of a something that does not get into
experience, a something which is still there when we are out of
the room.
We
think of something which transcends experience,
something which Kant called a "thing-in-itself," a ding an sich;
that something which is not in experience but which experience
implies.
Our
science gives us a "thing-in-itself," though not quite in
the Kantian sense, of course.
We
[4^
think of the table as
made up
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
of molecules, of these molecules as made up of atoms, of atoms
as made up of electrons and protons. We say that they are
responsible for
the different experiences
vibrate in a certain way,
we
about the ultimate particle
we have.
If they
get a certain color. Well,
itself,
the physics laboratory and are
the electron?
We
what
go over to
shown a model of the atom,
with protons and some electrons at the center. We think of
atoms as little galaxies like the solar system, the sun represented
by a proton at the center, and the planets by electrons revolving
around the proton, little stellar groups. That is what goes to
make up the atom. We think of them in terms of spatial relations and of the color which they have. But they cannot themselves have any color, for they are responsible for color. They
could not be responsible for color and be colored themselves.
The electron is too small to subtend a wave of hght anyway. It
could not be colored, and it is too small to be felt. Now, such
objects could not possibly be experienced, and yet, in a certain
sense they are the things which we do experience. A thing that
could not possibly be experienced and yet is the thing that is
experienced is what Kant called a "thing-in-itself." It is not
dependent upon us for its existence. It is, rather, something
upon which our experience may be thought to depend. W^e
assume that there is a world of things-in-themselves and that
they are not experienced
conditions of experience.
plied in experience.
in fact,
they are supposed to be the
is im-
world of things-in-themselves
But Kant
insists that,
inasmuch
as they
cannot be experienced, we cannot possibly know them. If we
could know them, we would experience them, that is, they would
fall under the forms of our sensibiHty and no longer be the conditions of experience. Color is a process of experience. All our
knowledge is a process of experience. One says he knows; that
experiencing color, feeling, locality. If we experience
the particles of which the physicist and chemist speak, those
means he
is
lie beyond objects, we have
assume something which is responsible for that experience. A
"thing-in-itself," says Kant, cannot be experienced; we cannot
ultimate electrons or matter which
to
[47]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
We may assume such a "thing-in-itself," but that
it.
assumption cannot be an act of knowledge.
Kant accepted that position from Hume. You can have necessary knowledge in the world of experience itself. That is, you
know that our experience must always take on the forms of
space and time, of substance and attribute, cause and effect.
But you cannot possibly know anything beyond that experience.
You may have to postulate a world of things-in-themselves, but
you cannot know such a world. This is the result of Kant's
Critique of Pure Reason. He analyzed experience, coming back
to what was necessary and universal in it, that which made
know
science possible.
But that holds only for experience. If the mind has such forms
which we have been speaking, then our experiences
must take on these forms. Our judgments are judgments about
past experiences, they are not judgments about a world which
as those of
the condition of our having experiences; we are assuming a
world that we cannot possibly experience, and so one which we
cannot know. We can give laws to the world of our experience,
the laws of our own mind; but those laws hold only for experiis
ence, only for possible experience in the future.
We can make
judgment that any experience we have must evidence
these laws, but this judgment holds only for experience itself.
We cannot know a world which lies outside of experience. Kant
called this world of experience "phenomenal." It implies something beyond itself of which it is the appearance. Just as I have
said, we can assume that the world has order, is the appearance of something. But of what it is the appearance we can
never know. We cannot even know that there is anything there.
universal
We
but we cannot know it.
something that takes us over into
conduct. We are continually acting. Our experience has been
of a world composed of seemingly solid matter; but we can
analyze that into the space of sensibihty. Our world is spatially
can postulate
But
we find that organization is a form of the mind.
world in which there are uniformities; we find that those
organized;
It is a
it,
this postulation is
THE PHILOSOPHER OF THE REVOLUTION
come back
to the forms of cause
We
of the mind.
We
We
and
effect,
and that
a law
are putting our feet right into the future, so to speak.
are expecting that our experience will continue as
continued.
We
know, or at least we assume,
experience continues
But
will it
it
will
be of a certain
in
it
has
advance that
if
sort.
continue? Is there a world of "things-in-them-
selves" that starts this experience of the world
is
is
are postulating that experience will continue.
there for that?
Kant
says there
is
none.
.^
What
evidence
All our evidence
We are asking for a world upon
which experience depends. We will always postulate such a
world; and we will always postulate that that world is intelliholds simply for experience.
gible, is intelligently organized, just as
gently organized.
as this:
Our
Our conduct
intelligent
our experience
carries with
conduct
will
it
is intelli-
such a postulation
be justified by our later ex-
But will we have further experiences? That is somecannot
thing we
tell, although we postulate possible experiences
as having intelligent order.
What is more interesting from Kant's standpoint is that we
postulate a responsibihty on our own part for our own conduct.
perience.
conduct.
And
that acceptance of responsibility carries with
the postulate of freedom. If there
is
belong to this world of appearance
such freedom,
for, in
it,
it
it
must not
every event
is
caused by a preceding event, comes under the law of cause and
effect. If the self is responsible, it must be because that self is
noumenal, a "thing-in-itself."
Now we cannot know
says this reality belongs to a world which
a world which
is
we cannot
responsible for our experience.
[49]
that.
Kant
experience,
But we
'
we
we
That is, we
must postulate that we are free morally, that we can act as
feel we ought to act. Kant says we cannot prove that. In fact,
when we look at our conduct, we always put it into terms of the
law of cause and effect. We explain an act by saying that such
and such motives were acting upon us. As we regard the act itself, we explain it, bring it under the law of cause and effect,
and yet we continually accept the responsibility for our own
regard ourselves as responsible; and therefore
are al-
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
ways making a postulate that we
ries
with
it
are responsible.
Conduct
car-
a set of postulates which cannot be proved but
which we cannot avoid. We also assume that the world of
"things-in-themselves," which we cannot know, is an ordered,
intelligible world. Our very conduct carries that assumption
with it. We cannot help assuming that we are responsible for
our conduct, that we can act freely within our experience as
such. Our conduct seems to be determined by previous events.
If we can act freely, it must be because there are noumenal
selves not bound by this law of understanding. We are always
postulating that. In conduct we postulate selves which are
noumenal, not phenomenal, selves that belong to the world of
We
we may say
can never get
direct evidence of these in perception but, nonetheless, he assumes that there are such things. So we assume that there is
"things-in-themselves."
postulate that, just as
that scientists postulate electrons.
such a thing as a
effect
self
self
which
which
is
is
The
scientist
not bound to the law of cause and
responsible. This postulate of the self
involved in our action, in our conduct. It
not know, for knowledge
is
is
is
is
something we can-
confined to experience. Experience
always of things that are caused, as such. But our conduct
constantly postulates a free
self.
By way
of this
self,
then,
go over to an assumed world of "things-in-themselves."
50
we
CHAPTER
III
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN;
ROMANTICISM IS BORN
WE
HAVE
and the
of
it.
been considering the political revolution
roles of
Rousseau and Kant as philosophers
a popular vogue to its doc-
The former gave
trines; the latter incorporated its principles into a speculative
system..;
The
undertaking^ o f the revolution, as
we h ave seen,^
was t o substitute for the arbitra ry authority o f the old nstitution s one that was based upon rati onal pri nciples; one whic h
was found^as presented in the theo ry of Rousseau, in the rights
of man. The assumption was that one could deduce from the
essential rights of man the structure of political institutions to_
i
take the place of the older institutions.
we have
own right,
as
The
rights of
man
were,
seen, universal in that the individual in asserting his
very nature of the case, recognizes and asIn so far, then, as the legislation of a popular assembly is confined to the rights of men, one
can reach that volonte generale, that general will of Rousseau
serts the
in the
same
right for others.
which the individuals are both subjects and sovereigns; the
will which gives laws for all in the very form of the right as such;
and which also recognizes that right, accepts it as that to which
it must conform.
The undertaking of the French Revolution
was to establish a government, a state, a political society on the
basis of such rights. The assumption was that it was possible to
deduce the whole structure of the state from what were recogin
nized as universal rights.
But the
broke down. In France one conwas undertaken without the result of
a stable and secure government. Out of the insecurity arose
the opportunity of Napoleon. By the exercise of military power, which he controlled for the time being, he was able to set
political revolution
stitution after another
[51]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
up the imperialism which dominated France and Europe for
fifteen years. The hold imperialism had on France was that,
in a certain sense, Napoleon appeared as the champion of
the Revolution. The opponents of France were undertaking
the divine right of kings, the
to set up the old order again
right of the church in its medieval claim
and Napoleon was the
leader of the armies of France that defeated them one after the
other. For this reason he was regarded as the champion of the
Revolution. There was another sense also in which he was its
champion where the armies of France went, the old order
broke down, particularly in Germany. The old medieval order
had remained in the latter country more than in any other. In
France, at least there had been an attempt to introduce administrative efficiency. At least the feudal power had been centered
monarch. Although feudal privileges remained with the
whole upper class, the power had passed over into the hands of
in the
the king, so that administrative efficiency
became
possible. In
Germany, however, there was no central monarch. We must
remember that Germany, more than any other country, had
suffered from the conception of the Holy Roman Empire. The
German monarchs of earlier centuries had tried to establish
themselves as the
Roman
emperors; and, in doing that, their
eyes were constantly fastened on the lands beyond the Alps.
The
interest
which centered
in this
establishment of an empire,
crown on the part of the German
contestant, had detracted from the development of a national
German state, so that Germany remained broken up into an
in the securing of the iron
indefinite
number of
little
And
feudal states, with a few powerful
the monarchs of the
communities
made the same claims for themselves that the monarchs of the
Prussia and Austria made. Now, wherlarger communities
ever the armies of France went, this old order crumbled and
people rejoiced at the freedom that came as a result of this
breakdown. This was especially true in the Rhine Valley, so
that there was a strong sympathy with the movements of Napoleon and even a strong feeling of attachment to him. In that
states in the midst.
[52]
little
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
sense
we can speak of Napoleon as the champion of the Revoluwho undertook to set up the old order
tion as over against those
again.
But the order that he set up was Imperialistic. It was an
in which he was a dictator, and it became more and more
order
tyrannical in
its
character, particularly in suppressing popular
was identified with the militaristic regime. Only
so long as Napoleon was fighting could it live. He could not
establish himself in the sense of a French king, could not attach
himself to the older traditions of the French monarch. There
had to be fighting for him to maintain his place. And in the
nature of the case, the regime broke down as France was worn
out, as strong men were sacrificed on the battlefield.
This was the situation because of the failure of the French
Revolution. And out of this failure arose the imperialism of Na-.
institutions. It
poleon.
To
the extent that this imperialism did not go back to
the old order,
it
regarded
itself as
supporting the Revolution. It
went back to the acceptance of the community as such. That is.
Napoleon had the support of France behind him in the form
of a plebiscite. His imperial throne rested not upon the
divine right of kings but on the support of the people themselves. But the constitution of his state depended upon his own
will. He was the dictator. And yet, in very many respects he did
carry out the Revolution. Particularly, he carried out the principles of political revolution involved in the dispossessing of
the privileged classes, bringing the land back to the peasants
themselves. This was the most important effect of the French
Revolution and of the reformation under Louis XVIII. In that
respect there is a parallelism between it and the Russian Revolution. The Russian Revolution put the land in the hands of the
peasants, even though the communistic doctrine does not recognize private property.
In the same way,
we may say
that the
French Revolution put the ownership of land into the hands of
the peasants; and, although the old order was reinstated, no attempt was made to change that fundamental reconstruction.
Eiirtkermore,^ we
have seen that the imperialism of France was
[S3]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
military organization of France against her enemies, and one
which was triumphant for fifteen years. It made France the
dominating power in Europe and gave that glory to the French
army and the French nation which was so sweet in the mouths
of the Frenchmen of the period. But it was not an establishment of the state on the principles which were drawn from the
social contract as Rousseau presented it. In that sense it was a
failure; and after Napoleon finally was defeated, France went
back in some sense to the old order, as did the rest of Europe.
The French had undertaken to establish a state, apolitical
society on the bare principle of political equality, with such an
ideal of universal form as that of truth or of property. As we
know, they did not succeed. It is not necessary for us to follow
out the history of the failures of the different constitutions
which were established, or of the conflict of interests which led
to the final collapse of the French Revolution in its political
form. Out of it rose Napoleonism, the imperialism of France.
was a dictatorship which established order, security in the community, which was of primary importance. You
can get an organization of all where you have one single lawgiver who has behind him a force to enforce the law. It is the
First of
all, it
simplest
way
of dealing with politically disturbed conditions.
Napoleon was, first of all, able to make himself a dictator, by
the somewhat ruthless use of power.
But, of course. Napoleon was also one of the world's greatest
military geniuses, and France was attacked by the reactionary
governments of Europe. The victories of Napoleon over these
enemies, who were the enemies of the Revolution as well, were,
in
a certain sense, victories for the principle of revolution.
Actually, there was dictatorship and tyranny as there had been
before the Revolution. In
political tyranny.
But
some sense
the foes of the Revolution, that
is,
was more severe
was fighting against
there
after all,JMapoleon
against those
who wished
to
bring back the institution of the divine right of kings, of the old
feudal order, of the ecclesiastical power. Those who wished to
maintain this old order were fighting against the powers in
[54]
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
France which gave expression
Even England
English government was
to the Revolution.
joined with the others, although the
quite liberal in character, as indicated by Burke's reflections
on the French Revolution, which were very influential. And
Napoleon in fighting these powers was, from the point of view
of France and liberals throughout the world, the champion
of the Revolution, not because he himself was interested in establishing a democracy on the contrary, but because he was an
enemy of those who were determined to have the Revolution
wiped out. He was the enemy, at least, of the enemies of
France; and he was the victor over their armies. His power,
then, was,
And
first
of
all,
that of a dictator
who
established secu-
second place, he had the enthusiasm of victorious France behind him.
rity.
Of
in the
course,
it
was not simply the
principle of revolution
that was involved here. It was the principle of nationalism as
Medieval Europe and the remains of medieval Europe
that we find in the eighteenth century had very little place for
what we term "nationalism." Take Austria, for example. It
was composed of an indefinite number of different communities,
different races, speaking different languages. That which was
common to most of them was their religion. But the different
groups were racially, linguistically, historically, different; and
yet they were all organized into a single monarchy. There was
an economic ground for this organization which we are recognizing in the troubles of Europe at the present time. Those within
the communities bought from and sold to each other, produced
and distributed in such a fashion that the organization of this
Austrian empire did answer to certain very important economic,
demands. The process of setting up commercial treaties between the different communities and different states that have
arisen out of the Austrian empire is a very difficult thing. But
still there was a single state, made up out of different groups
which now make up a whole set of different societies, and
societies which had a vivid sense of their own entities and of
well.
their hostility to others.
iss]
THOUGHT
^he
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
beginning of this nationalism can be found
in the vic-
Napoleon, in the sense of the superiority of the French
armies and of the French nation. And this sense of superiority
which comes with the conflict of a certain group that is united
in its language, in its history
this sense of solidarity which we
call "nationalism"
might be said to have had its beginning in
the imperiahsm of Napoleon. There had been nationalism before, but no such vivid nationalism as that characterizing the
history of England in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries,
for example.
The breakdown of the old feudal institutions in France
helped the development of this nationaUstic spirit.' In so far as
it equalized everyone, it left everyone a Frenchman. The
emigres^ that belonged to the old regime, felt more at home
with their own class abroad than among the Frenchmen who
had driven them out. People of various classes might feel
tories of
more
at
home among
the same class abroad. Just in so far as
there had been a leveling process that
had brought everyone to
was the opportunity for the development
of nationalism. Nationalism is a leveling conception. Each one
the
same
level, there
We do
most vivid form where
castes, or classes, are present. We get the most vivid sense of
it in situations where everyone can stand upon the same level.
has his position simply as a
member
not get the sense of nationalism in
VRevolution, in so far as
it
breaks
of a certain nation.
its
down
social castes,
development of nationalismv
''What gave Napoleon his power, then, was,
is
favorable
to the
first
of
all,
his
capacity for introducing order, security, into the state; in the
second place, his victories over the enemies of France and the
French Revolution; and, in the third place, the power that
came with
ity to
these victories over
all
the armies of Europe, the abil-
stand as a dominant power on the Continent.
But the French Revolution
as an undertaking had definitebroken down. If the armies of Napoleon had crushed the
enemies of the Revolution, they had not established its principles in the French state.
They had established another
ly
[56]
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
empire, the Napoleonic empire. There was a definite sense of
was concerned. After the
defeat of Napoleon the emperors of Russia and of Austria and
the kings of Prussia and of England undertook to wipe out the
Revolution and put things where they had been before. Of
course, they could not do that; it was impossible to re-establish
the old housekeeping after the breakdown of the old, motheaten furniture of the medieval period. But an attempt was
made in that direction, going back to the old order of things.
There came a sense of defeat, after the breakdown of the
defeat, then, as far as the Revolution
Revolution, after the failure to organize a society on the basis
And it is out of this sense
of liberty, equality, and fraternity.
of defeat that a
new movement
general terms passes under the
I
have said
it
was impossible
things, passionately as
arose, a
title
movement which
in
of "romanticism."
to re-establish the old order of
many men wanted
it.
But that
desire
did lead to a very intense interest in that old order. England,
of course, was unwilling to accept the power of France, the imperialism of Napoleon. Prussia,
not
simply to re-establish the old order but also to drive the French
out of their country. Thus, owing to the revolution itself, natoo,
arose as a nation
But they were putwas out of that Revolution that Napoleon had arisen. In England the sentiment for the
revolution, as depicted in Dickens' The Tale of Two Cities and
in the eloquence of Burke, was in peril. (The revolution was supposed to be that which tore society down, the savageness of the
Days of Terror. It was supposed to represent the actual disintegration of society, and people turned from it in terror and looked
for those institutions which had been in existence before the
French Revolution had arisen. So there was a turning to the old
world with a certain passionate attachment. There was a retionalism had arisen in other communities.
ting
down
the French Revolution, for
it
vival of medievalisri^.yi
This revival was one of the aspects of romanticism^
member
that from the barbarians
Roman Empire we have
who came
in to
You
re-
destroy the
kept the term "vandal" as a term ap[57]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
community which destroys everything before it. The term "Goth" had exactly the same meaning, and
"Gothic" was appHed disparagingly to the architecture of the
plying to a barbarous
medieval period from the time of the Enlightenment as such, the
time of the turning-away from the obscurantism of the medieval
period. But in this latter period we find a return to the medieval
attitude, and the term "Gothic" took on the same meaning that
that of a certain type of architecture which we
it has for us
consider very beautiful. This
is
just an illustration of the atti-
tude that was taken at the time. With the breakdown of the
came this attempt to re-establish the old order. The
was turned back; the Holy Alliance was established between the monarchs of Austria, Russia, Prussia, and England,
revolution
clock
in
1
an attempt to safeguard this old order.
I want to point out is that this return to the old order
What
was very
different
from the old order as
it
had existed before
Men came
back to something
which was regarded through different eyes than before. It was,
the revolutionary upheaval.
in the first place, treasured in so far as it represented a security
which had been so rudely shaken in the revolutionary upheaval.
It was precious in a sense in which it had never been precious
before. Previously, it had been accepted as a matter of course,
as the normal status of society. The evils of it had led to the
revolution itself. But now it appeared as security, as that which
seemingly had been lost and now was recovered. Thus it as-
sumed a glamor.
But there was another aspect of this
'^
it its
reaction, that
peculiar, its romantic, flavor: this
is
that
which gives
men came back
to
it from the standpoint of new individuals, new selve^. Europe
had been through the revolution. As an undertaking to estab-
on the basis of the new political entity, the citizen,
who was supposed to stand on his own
movement
this
was felt not simply in France
feet, so to speak,
but in all Europe as well. It was represented by such vivid
lish things
the political individual
imaginations as those of the young Wordsworth and Coleridge,
by a feeling for a new life, an assertion of a self that could stand
[58I
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
its own feet, on its rights. There was the same movement
America, of course. Here had been the reflection of the
gospel of Kant, of the skepticism of Voltaire. Here too had
on
in
arisen a
new
England the revolution did
which it took place in France.
individual. In liberal
not appear in the violent form in
In the former, as
we have already
seen, the revolution had, in a
certain sense, taken place in the Puritan upheaval
the Stuarts out, brought William and
Mary
in,
which sent
and which
established a representative institution. Parliament, as the final
Parhament went over
authority.
to the people. It
might put
on the throne a monarch who ruled by divine right, but it was
Parliament that put him there, and he could remain there only
with the support of Parliament. Thus, in a certain sense the
revolution had taken place in England, but it had left an organization of diff"erent interests. It was not yet a democratic struc-
France the attempt had been made to set up a demoa man with
cratic structure coming back to the political man
rights. 5]he Englishman was still what he was by virtue of his
social status, because of his connection with the great organizature. In
and of trade. He did not take his position as a
human being who had political rights. The Americans came
and presented that doctrine in England at that time. There
were repercussions of the French Revolution in England, but it
did not sweep over England in any such sense as it did over
France. Still the sentiment was there and elsewhere in Europe
in Germany, in Italy, in Spain. And that spirit meant that
the individual looked at himself as having his own rights, regarded himself as having his own feet to stand on. This gave
him a certain independence which he did not have before;
it gave him a certain self-consciousness th at he neve r had
tions of industry
iieforeTl
him when he
world to which he was returning. He came back with a difi^erent self-consciousness from
that with which he had left it. He looked at it through differIt
IS "this
went back
ent eyes.
self-consciousness that he took with
to consider again the old
He
did not look at
it
with hostile eyes; he wanted at
[59]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
least the order, the security, of the old order re-established.
The
attempt to set up a new state on a democratic basis had failed.
People now wanted to get rid of that. They came back again
to the old order; but they came back as different individuals,
and they now looked at the old order from another point of
view. They had become self-conscious in regard to it.
/What the Romantic period revealed, then, was not simply a
past, but a past as the point of view from which to come back
at the self. One has to grow into the attitude of the other, come
back at the self, to realize the self; and we are discussing the
means by which this was done. Here, then, we have the makings
of a
new philosophy,
First of
all,
the
Romantic
philosophy..!
the discouraged self that
had undertaken to rehad followed
build the world on the basis of rights, the self that
gospel of Rousseau
attempting to reconstruct
society on the basis of what was universal in the individual, on
the basis not only of that which he found in himself but which
he recognized in others, found that the undertaking had failed.
It was not possible to build up a new community on the ab-
out
the
in
men. Of course, in a certain sense it may be
America succeeded in this attempt where France had
failed. One finds the same abstractions in the Declaration of
Independence that one finds among the doctrinaires of the
French Revolution. But the American community was not built
up on the Declaration of Independence. This instrument was a
banner of liberty flung forth to the world; but the government
that was set up was based on the liberal institutions that had
been carried over from England and had gone through the fire
of the long colonial period. When the Constitution was finally
formulated, it was an expression of the political institutions
which were an inheritance from the mother-country, institutions
the technique of which was to be found in the common law.
The American government was not an institution built up on
abstract rights. When the French undertook to do this, they
found that they did not have the material with which to work.
They broke down the imperialism of Napoleon and took charge
stract rights of
said that
[6o1
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
of the chaotic situation which resulted. But they had no basis
upon which to undertake to build up a new state whose authority
should be based upon the reason of the individual; and their
The individuals who undertook it returned from
plans failed.
the quest in the discouraged condition that characterizes the
breakdown of revolutions. This was the situation all over Euhad centered in France, the
rope, for, while the revolution
movement spread over
the whole continent.
But, though the self had failed in
there with
its
own
its
point of view; and
it
undertaking,
now turned
it
was
still
to the past.
almost passionate, endeavor was to get back to this
past, to get rid of the horrors of the imperialism of France and
of the collapse of the Revolution, to set up the old order again,
Its first,
and thus get back the security that came with it, get back the
lost. But when these were put
in place again, the house refurnished, the process was undertaken from the point of view of a sophisticated self that was aware
of its own defeats, that was interested not only in getting the
values that seemed to have been
house refurnished but interested in the inhabitant, in itself.
is a self-consciousness about the process which distinguishes this movement from the medieval situation that it was
undertaking to re-establish. There is that bitter attitude about
the beginning of the Romantic period, but with it there came
There
The old world was discovered, and it
was highly interesting, exciting, as presented, for example, in
Goethe, and in Schiller's Die Rduber. Thus we come to a new interest in a medieval world that had been thought to be nothing
but dust and ashes. Once again it becomes a living affair. It is
portrayed in the attitude of the pageant, of the drama, the attitude of living over the old life where one assumes now one role
unexpected treasures.
andnow another.
And with this came
the further discovery, not only of the old
world but of the self. Men had gotten the point of view from
which to look at themselves, to realize and enjoy themselves.
That is, of course, the attitude which we find in the romantic
individual, in the romantic phases of our own existence. We
\
f6il
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
come back to the existence of our self as the primary fact. That
Is what we exist upon. That Is what gives the standard to
values. In that situation the self puts Itself forward as Its ulti-
mate reahty. This is characteristic of the romantic attitude in
the Individual and of this peribdy
Of course, we have many llTuslratlons of it. For example, the
Byronic poetry; that affirmation of the
thrown aesthetically upon the heavens,
lows everything
cynicism.
The
else.
In Bryon this
attitude
perience, but in
it
is
is
which the eye is
which the self swal-
self in
in
presented with a certain
expressed in a Mephistophelean ex-
the self asserts
itself; it is
there over against
the world, against God, against the devil; it is there as the
primary thought with reference to which everything else must
be oriented. That is the starting-point in such Byronic experience, the attitude which is implied in the use of the term
Byronic.
The romantic
experiences to which
we have
referred are also
presented in Scott, and in the attitude toward Gothic archltec-
Those attitudes are a
-ture.
tHe past. It
!
suming the
is
result of the journey'ortHFself into
a reconstruction of the self through the self's as-
roles of the great figures of the past.
That
is
what
gives the peculiar flavor to romantic literature, a character that
we
recognize at once in contrasting the novels and poetry of
Scott with Malory's Morte d' Arthur or his Chronicles. In these
latter there
is
a simple, direct attitude, while in the hero of
Scott you have a self-consciousness which
is
historically out of
place but which gives a flavor to the whole romantic experience.
own
There the
self is
reconstruction.
used as the point of orientation in its
Scott, as over against
What we recognize in
the figures in the Chronicles,
self,
an attitude which
is
is
self-consciousness, awareness of
entirely out of place in the naivete of
those medieval knight-errants.
The hero
of the Scottish novel
would have been perfectly at home in the period of Scott himself, had he taken his armor ofi^. He has the consciousness, the
background of a modern individual; and, largely for this reason,
he was all the more picturesque when put into the garments of
f62l
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
the medieval period. This whole thing is caricatured in Mark
Twain's A Connecticut Yankee at King Arthur s Court.
Perhaps the most vivid and the most moving picture that we
can get of this in English literature is to be found in the writings
of Carlyle. He, as well as Coleridge, De Quincey, and a small
group of Englishmen, came under the influence of Romanticism.
His early contacts were with Goethe, who, Hke Schiller, was
Romantic philosophy. The influence which particularly moved Carlyle, though, was that of
Schelling, although Fichte too had his influence, as is shown particularly in Sartor Resartus. If you read that, you will get a
more or less emotional reflection of the Fichtean philosophy.
The responsibihty which is depicted as lying in man, and which
makes him a creative center in the universe, which identifies
very
much
influenced by the
the individual with the Absolute Self in the universe,
is
',
Fich-
tean.
Europe discovered the medieval period
riod, then;
itself first.
in the
Romantic pe-
but it also discovered itself. In fact, it discovered
Furthermore, it discovered the apparatus by means
of which this self-discovery was possible.
to the reflexive
mode.
One
self
belongs
senses the self only in so far as
the self assumes the role of another so that
subject and object in the
The
same experience.
it
becomes both
This
of great importance in this whole historical
is
the thing
movement.
It
Europe, at this time, put themselves
they could come back upon
themselves. When they had done this, they could contrast
themselves with the earlier period and the selves which it
brought forth. As a characteristic of the romantic attitude we
find this assumption of roles. Not only does one go out into
was because people
back
in
in the earlier attitude that
adventure taking now this, that,- or another part, living this
exciting poignant experience and that, but one is constantly
coming back upon himself, perhaps reflecting upon the dulness
of his own existence as compared with the adventure at an
earlier time which he is living over in his imagination. He has
got the point of view from which he can see himself as others
[63]
'
THOUGHT
see him.
And
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
he has got
it
because he has put himself
in the
place of the others.
From
the standpoint of the earlier period the structure of
was moth-eaten, riddled with worms. It was breaking
down and people were looking for something new to take its
place. When, in its turn, this new order had proved itself
to be a deception, they tried to go back to the past. But when
they came back, they were different individuals. They were
now looking for something in the old order that was precious,
something that had never been recognized in it before. And, in
things
doing
they were in an essentially self-conscious attitude.
they were aware of themselves in the whole process.
this,
That
is,
Now,
it is
this self-conscious setting-up of the past again that
made the past a
who had hardly been
constitutes the romanticism of this period. It
different past. In the first place, people
it now, and
gave them an emotional experience
which was novel, exciting. It created a different past from that
which had been there before a past which was discovered, into
which a value had been put which did not belong there before.
This value was security, the security of an old order which
people thought they had lost and which they now had recovered
again. But this was a value which had not been recognized there
before, and it gave to the self which discovered it a content
which it had not had before. That content, as I have said, was primarily an emotional one. It was the feel of the thing that men
got out of this experience. And there was also the freedom that
came to the self in traveling back into the past, assuming one
role after another, fl am particularly anxious to bring out this
difference in the attitude of men toward the old order. They returned to it with a sense of rej-ief because the French Revolution
willing to accept
to accept
it
it
before were willing to accept
as a pageant. It
had meant disturbance, the most considerable war that had
been waged in Europe for a long time, together with all that goes
with continuous warfare. What followed it was a return to the
security of the past, a setting-up of that again, so that
came back
to the past with an appreciation
[64]
men
which they did not
THE REVOLUTION BREAKS DOWN
have of it in the earher period. Furthermore, the self that examined this past and savored it, enjoyed it, was a different self
from that of the period of revolution.
We have been discussing the romantic period as a passage
from the period of the revolution. The latter undertook to find
in
the rational nature of
man
the authority for institutions,
as over against the arbitrary authority
medieval conception of the institution
the state, the school, or the family.
which belonged to the
-whether of the church,
The
pevolu-tioivufide^:
took, in -its--QppDsLtiQn-tQ--tb4sa^^trary-authomyy to find an
authorlty^iiithe rationa l na ture of
matt- himsclf. Of course,
this
turned particularly about the- political revolution. In this connection-an-attempt .was jnade to set up a state on the basis of
what-were-considered the -rights of man; to develop rationally,
from the theory of these natural rights, what the order of the
state should be, to find that which was universal, which was
recognized in the attitude of every member of the community.
What do you find in the attitude of every member of the community which he asserts as his right and which he recognizes as
the rights of others.'' What do you find there as the basis for the
organization of the state? The answer to that question was the
undertaking of the revolution, in an attempt to set up the state
on the basis of universal rights. But, as we have seen, the revolution broke down and we find the Romantic period taking its
place.
As representatives of this latter movement in Germany we
have Schiller and Goethe, especially in their earlier productions.
Their presentation of the medieval period which was so attractive, so vivid, so full
of color, and, on the other hand, that sense
came from the assumption of differwhat constituted the romanticism of this
of novelty in the self which
ent roles, that,
period.
say,
is
65
CHAPTER
IV
KANT AND THE BACKGROUND OF
PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
THE
Romantic movement is attached to the
Kantian self with which we have already become acquainted. We have it very interestingly presented in
self of the
Schiller's Aesthetic Letters^ which is one of the early romantic
developments of the Kantian doctrine. The Kantian self, as we
have seen, had two aspects. One aspect is purely formal as it
appeared in the transcendental unity of apperception, that unifying power which holds together, constructs our percepts, makes
them different from bare sensations, and gives unity to them.
But this unity was a pure function from Kant's standpoint, it
was not an entity, was not a spiritual being; it was just a function of unity. The other aspect of this self, we have seen, appears
in the Critique of Practical Reason. Kant reaches it by way of
his postulates.
ourown
We :fimi-jQ.urs_dves.-SLCeptiiig.
actioiis^
We could
responsibility for
not lay any such responsibility upon
we were free, unless actions were our ownCFrom
Kant's standpoint, the very fact of the acceptance of respon-
ourselves unless
with it the postulation that men are free. But
world of experience the Kantian world of experience
everything is subject to the laws of the mind, those of the
sensibilities
space and time and those of the understandsibility carries
in the
ing
the
categories.
What
takes place there takes place in
accordance with the laws of cause and
effect.
Every
effect is a
necessary result of its antecedent causes. Thus, freedom cannot
be found in the world of experience as we know it. Kant's
assumption is that we must postulate a self which, so to speak,
lies in a different realm from that of the phenomenal, namely, in
the noumenal world of "things-in-themselves." He has proved
I
66
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
to his
own
a world.
we cannot know anything of this
but we find ourselves continually postulating such
satisfaction that
latter world,
self,
then, that belongs to the world of "things-in-
themselves," the noumenal world,
Critique of Practical Reason. It
is
is
the implication of the
a self that
postulated and that cannot be known.
must be constantly
What
took place
in the
Romantic period along a philosophical line was to take this
transcendental unity of apperception, which was for Kant a
bare logical function, together with the postulation of the self
which we could not possibly know but which Kant said we
could not help assuming, and compose them into the new romantic seff. ;
Kant's nearest approach to this came not in the first two
critiques but in the third, the Critique of Judgment. What he
points out in that critique is that in Hfe, in vital phenomena, we
cannot help assuming some sort of an end which determines the
nature of the process that goes on. That is, he brought up the
conflict between what is known as the teleological and the
mechanical interpretations of nature. Our physics and chemistry undertake to state the nature of the Hving process in
terms of the necessary succession of cause and effect. What
what has occurred before. On
hand, the biologist talks about functions, about
the life-process maintaining itself. He deals with all the funcrespiration, the circulation of the blood, the assimilations
from the point of view of the maintenance of the
tion of food
species. There is an end, that is, which lies ahead. The life that
takes place does so because of
the other
is
to
be lived by the species
is
to
be maintained;
it
exercises a
Kant pointed out that in our
perception, our judgment on living things, we are always assuming some sort of an end which determines what takes place.
control over the living process.
What he
is
referring to here
is
not any metaphysical conclusion
but that the very object as we
is perceived as carrying with it
its future ends and purposes. We perceive a plant as something
more than a mere congeries of atoms and molecules. W^e perthat can be
know
it,
drawn from
this,
the animal or the plant,
[67]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
ceive a tree as getting moisture from the earth, constructing the
starch necessary for the building of
its tissues,
sugar, and so forth, as processes essential to
turning
its
it
being a
into
tree.
These processes together are what a tree is. There is something
more in this than in the sort of statement, the mechanical
account, that the physicist and the chemist can make.
And
then Kant turned his attention to the
field
of aesthetics,
of beauty. There our process of perception constructs that
which is itself pleasing, agreeable to our aesthetic taste, and
which is not the same as perception. It goes out beyond the
mere physical object, the mere sensations themselves, and creates them in such a fashion that one shall get a certain sort of
delighted response in connection with the object. There is a
creative process that puts things together in such a fashion that
we can enjoy them. And
volved
in
that enjoyment
our aesthetic appreciation.
then, which is involved
The judgment,
is
a thing
which
is
in-
in the recognition of
the life-process of plant and animal, the judgment in our recog-
which is in itself beautiful, is, in a sense, something which seems to go beyond the world as it is presented in
the Critique of Pure Reason the world of science, with its necessity, which is a priori. It even goes beyond the mere affirmation
of responsibility which we find in the Critique of Practical Reason. It reconstructs the world from the observation of certain
ends and purposes those involved in the very processes of living, on the one hand, and those involved in art, on the other
nition of that
hand.
\
As
have
said,
it
was, perhaps, from these three different
new doctrine of Romantic idealism grew, or to
attached itself: first was Kant's transcendental unity
points that the
which
it
of apperception; second was the
self,
the free self which our
moral attitude postulates; and third was the experience as
depicted in the Critique of Judgment which sets up a sort of
end or purpose as determining the life-process of living things,
and which determines the structure of that which dehghts
our aesthetic tastes. These were the points around which
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
grew up the philosophy which succeeded Kant,/ One of the
it is found in Schiller's B'riefe iiber die
asthetische Erziehung des Menschen. These are a study of the
aesthetic experience in so far as it expresses this new or romantic
self. The new self, as we have seen, appears actually, in the
experience of Europe, at the time when people deliberately
opened their chests to regain the treasure which belonged to the
past but which people now felt, for the first time, might be
earHest expressions of
valuable.
I
In this connection
perHaps
it is
for the first time,
That
attitude.
is,
we have,
modern
an expression of our
historic
interesting to see that here
people were turning back to the past and were
means of appreciating present condiThe philosophical representative of this historic phase of
the movement was Herder, with his presentation of earlier conditions which were to be found among more primitive people.
interested in that past as a
tions.
There was a going-back to the earlier legends and stories and
myths that gather around histories, such as the Cid in Spain,
and the early French heroes; a going-back to those figures which
lay in the
memory
of the race, of the nation. This process
is
be found in the early history of the Romantic movement.
England
Table.
it is
found
in the legends of
King Arthur and
his
to
In
Round
This historical interest attaches itself to the same movement
of the self back into the past. What one has is just such a transcendental unity of apperception as Kant's phrase implies. That
is, the self looked back at its own past as it found it in history.
It looked back at it and gave the past a new form as that out of
which
had sprung.
itself back into the past. It
and achievements of those old
heroes with an interest which children have for the lives of their
parents taking their roles and realizing not only the past but
it itself
It
put
lived over again the adventures
the present itself in that process.
back
in their archaic form.
The
old stories were brought
That form had the same
fascination
people that old garments have for children. People turned
back into the past, became interested in it, and got an interest
for
[69]
THOUGHT
which showed
the myth, but
itself
the present
have
in that the
It
had
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
not simply in the pageant, in the story, in
also in getting the historical connections, seeing
how
est.
IN
had grown out of the
past.
As
have
said,
we
beginning of our whole modern historical inter-
on
its scientific
technique,
all its
periods; but
it
not, as yet, taken
not yet gathered together
had
it
was the begin-
ning of that scientific movement.
What
want
to bring out, in this connection,
that this
is
new self going back
new self had gone back
interest arises only through the
past. It
is
only because this
past that such an organized past arose at
all.
We
into the
into the
know,
for
between the histories which are written
at the present time and the old chronicles, and we marvel that
people could have been wiUing simply to put down a set of
events, the accounts of certain battles, the crowning and death
of kings, a mere statement of the meetings of ecclesiastical councils, all these being bare bones without flesh. And yet we have
example, the
difi^erence
to recognize that history does not exist except in so far as the
individuals of the present in
into the past. It
people,
if
you
some sense put themselves back
only in a process of memory
is
like
that
memory of the
history can be created.
And
such a
is possible only when we have, so to
some such point that we can become aware of
ourselves. Thus, all the moments which come with the development of adolescence are what make adolescence a romantic period. The child up to the age of twelve does not have a past in any
such sense as a child who perhaps only two or three years later
reconstruction of the past
speak, reached
has a very definite past. There have been, of course, a succession of days, seasons, years, of periods of vacation out of school,
but the past
lie
behind.
tic
period,
this past.
is
there simply in those detached events which
When
if
you
He
he goes through the later period
the child more or
like
discovers
it
less
the roman-
suddenly discovers
in his reaction against the order of
things in the family, the school, and the community.
more
or less of an attitude of opposition;
and
He
is
in
in this attitude
he
goes back over the past, and generally he has a set of grievances
[70I
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
which he recognizes. This attitude which belongs to adolescence
is essential if the past is to have a definite structure. Otherwise,
it is just taken for granted, it is just there; but now it becomes a
part of the individual himself.
Romantic period
new
He
creates
it.
Thus
in
the
an adolescent, self-conscious self. It turned back upon its past, lived it over again,
took up this and that incident and presented them from its own
a
self arose,
prsent standpoint.
What I want
make
is that such a past as that of which
always the creation of a new self, one
that has attained content that it did not have before. I want to
attach that romantic attitude as we find it in Europe to the
attitude which we all have passed through in our own romantic
eras. It is a perfectly natural development. It is that of a self
that has become aware of itself and turns back upon its own
past in order to hold onto that self and, so to speak, create that
V
to
have been speaking
past as
its
period. It
is
own. This was the atmosphere of the Romantic
presented vividly in the discussion of Fichte and,
more particularly of
Philos opJi^T
The
clear
is
Schelling, in Royce's The Spirit of
Modern
'/
revolution had attempted to define the principles for the
reconstruction of society as these are found in the rational nature
of the individual.
in the
mind of
generalized this and undertook to
find^
the individual the principles for the organization^,
This position of man had been abandoned in|
breakdown of the French Revolution, but the
that turned to the old order as a result of this breakdown
of nature
itself.
one sense
in the
self
Kant
was a very different one than existed originally under this old
order. It had taken on a critical attitude. It was in that sense
independent. It looked upon the old order, as it accepted it
again, from the point of view of one who had rejected it but was
again taking it up with more or less definite acceptance.
There is a story of the transcendental period in this country
which is illustrative of this. It is a story about Margaret Fuller,
one of the transcendentalists gathered about Emerson. This, of
course, was the Romantic period as it found philosophical ex[71]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
pression in America. Margaret Fuller said, "I accept the uni-
To
verse."
this Carlyle rejoined,
"Begad, she'd
Romantic
represents the attitude of the
better!'
vJ^s
period. It accepted an
order of things that was there. Its acceptance was a part of the
romantic attitude itself. The mind went back to the old order
but in a different sense. It went back to it and found something
which the mind accepted, and in this the self that accepted the
old order was a very different self from that which had existed
under the old order, a self which had accepted that order without questioning. It is this different self which is the important
cliaracteristic of this
A good illustration
toward
Romantic period^^
of
religious ritual.
The
can be found in the aesthetic attitude
This is the romantic return to the old
it
sought for that which was aesthetic,
it was not interested in the dogma
of
the
church
was accepted, but the interas such. The dogma
est of the individual did not he in the dogma. It lay in the
ritual, the form which united people together in the process of
worship, which was expressed in the architecture of the church,
religious order.
self
attractive in the ritual itself;
in the
pageantry of the ritual
the religious response and
itself.
became
This appealed directly to
characteristic of the rehgious
response during the Romantic period. This response comes back
to the individual, to his aesthetic approval or disapproval. In
the end, one gets to the point at which he says, "I like this or
do not
like this."
Of course,
there
is
a great deal
more than that
judgment; but at the bottom, one does reach
is, one gets back to the direct response of
a
the individual as
basis for judgment. There may be an objective beauty, something that is there independently of the man
who appreciates it; but it exists for him only in so far as he is
aware of it. Dogma, of course, directly binds man's reason in
so far as he accepts it. And this acceptance, from the point of
view of reason, is not based upon one's own rational comprehension of the dogma. It transcends the reason of man. It was said,
in the aesthetic
that attitude.
"One
That
believes because the thing believed
is
impossible."
The
Trinity, the transubstantiation, were mysteries that transcend-
[72]
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
ed the reason of man. Yet, man accepted the dogmas. He did
not undertake to determine whether he should accept them or
not by their rational character. Dogmas are given by God. They
come to man through inspiration, through God's agent on earth
the church
and man accepts them because of his relation to
God. Thus dogmas do not appeal directly to man for their support, do not appeal to his reason for their acceptance. But an
aesthetic response, on the other hand, always depends upon the
individual himself. One responds to them or one does not. And
in so far as the revival of religious experience characterized the
Romantic
and in so far as its revival was one in which the
aesthetic element was dominant, it inevitably emphasized the
individual's response. One found within himself the emotional
reason for responding to this ritual. One found in himself that
which gave the basis for his acceptance of the churchT^
There is something of this same attitude in the response to the
old political order in so far as it still continued to exist. It had a
romantic flavor. Men brought back the pageantry of things.
They could not reinstate the knight-errant, for the methods of
fighting had driven him from the field; but still they were very
much interested in him. He became the object of romance.
Novels of the type written by Scott were written about the
knight and about the feudal order. And it was the aesthetic response to this order that was of peculiar importance during the
period. It was highly interesting, it was fascinating; and, where
one went back into it, as did those who had seen the revolution
fail, one was able to get a delight out of it which did not belong
to the earlier period itself. In that sense the Romantic period
rediscovered the Middle Ages. It discovered the aesthetic values in the past that gave the peculiar flavor to it.
Turning again to the philosophical aspects of romanticism,
we find the relation of subject to object more fundamental than
that of substance and attribute. The way to this lies, of course,
through Kant's doctrine. Substance and attribute, cause and
effect, are just categories of the mind. Kant did not speak of
them as expressions of an Absolute Self, but as forms of the mind
period,
[73]
THOUGHT
IN
The Romantic
itself.
Self that
is infinite,
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
on the other hand, comes back to a
one that inevitably has a
divine, absolute
school,
not-self as its object.
That is the nature of the
and this latter as an object
self,
that
it
is a not-self.
should have an object;
no self withother;
there
is
have
the
one
without
the
cannot
We
out its not-self. The self must have a world within which it
You can set up an absolute substance in the Spinozistic
make everything simply a part of it, and there is nothing
which is opposed to it as a not-substance. But if you make the
lives.
sense,
between subject and object the central one, you come
back to a self which is a subject. But this self cannot be thought
of without a not-self, that is, without an object. Furthermore,
this relation cannot be presented in static terms. If you are to
have an infinite self it must be all-inclusive; you cannot set up a
not-self. If you are to reach that outside, you will have to do it
in terms which are not static, but dynamic in import, in terms
relation
of a process.
set
it
with
up
must set up its own not-self. But if it does
not-self, it must eventually identify this not-self
The
as a
self
itself.
Thus, when we come back to the
conception of the Romantic period,
have a relationship with something
self,
which
we reach
else
is
the dominant
that which
beyond
itself.
must
The
self
does not exist except in relation to something else. The word
"itself," you will recognize, belongs to the reflexive mode. It is
that grammatical form which
the individual
He
is
we use under
both subject and object.
sees himself as others see him.
conditions in which
He
addresses himself.
The very usage
of the word
who is occupying the position of both subject and object. In a mode which is not reflexive, the object is
distinguished from the subject. The subject, the self, sees a tree.
The latter is something that is different from himself. In the
implies an individual
use of the term "itself," on the contrary, the subject and object
same
term "itself" is one
which is characteristic of a romantic phase of consciousness.
Romanticism turns about a vivid self-consciousness. The romanticist sees things through the guise of his own emotions. Not
are found in the
entity. This very
[74]
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
only that, but he himself bulks larger in his own experience than
do other things. He assesses them, evaluates them, in terms of
himself.
He
least his
own standard
sets himself
calculations.
That
Whether we
find
we
as the standard of values, or at
of values
that which
is
is
dominant
in his
characteristic of the romantic experience.
is
it
up
such a Romantic period as this which
in
are considering, or in the period gone through in our
lives,
that assessing of things in
one's assertion that a thing
able
terms of one's
is
is
valuable because
Romantic
characteristic of the
own
period.
is
valu-
self
some-
it
The
own
feeling,
times becomes inordinately prominent in the experience of
such an individual. We have to assure people, at that stage,
that
it
transient, that they will pass through
is
things will have a different value a
little later.
it,
[Ttl s
and that
a period in
which the self itself and the relation of things to this self are the
important factors in experience. I again want to refer to the
peculiar aspect of this self, namely, that it is both subject and
object. The individual under these circumstances, then, is apt
upon himself. I just
That
is perhaps not
used the words "turned in upon himself."
characteristic of the Romantic period. The romantic attitude is
to be subjectivistic, self-centered, turned in
rather the externalizing of the
self.
One
projects one's self into
the world, sees the world through the guise, the veil, of one's
own
emotions. That
The
attitude.
is
the essential feature of the romantic
self-centered attitude
thing but romantic. It
may
may
be a hard,
be one which
anyon the
is
selfish attitude, or,
other h and, a very conscientious attitude. Neither of these
romantic.
is
The r omantic
attitude
is
the ability to project one's self upon
is identified in some fashion with
world has value to the individual only in
the world, so that the world
the
self.
At
least the
terms of himself.
have
ject-object relationship.
referred, in this connection, to the sub-
At
least here in self-consciousness
one
has both the subject and the object given in the immediate experiencexand^_i.fj:pu think of it, it is an attempt to get the subject
and
the.
object together, so to speak.
[75]
That has been the goal of
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
epistemological thought in philosophy in so far as
it
has at-
problem of knowledge. How can we assure
ourselves of the validity of our knowledge? How can we be sure
that what we see and hear is there; that the meanings of things
that we grasp are really the meanings that belong to them in the
universe outside? That has been the search of philosophy, to
get the justification for our knowledge as it appears in experience. Philosophy, throughout its whole existence, has been
fighting with the dragon or bogy of skepticism that arises out of
the negative answer to this problem.
The philosophy of the Romantic period grew out of the last
two critiques of Kant, the Critique of Practical Reason and the
Critique of Judgment. In a sense these belong rather to the period of the revolution. They tried to define the rational nature of
man as the ground for his conduct and for the order of society.
tempted
to solve the
Kant generalized the position involved in the theory of natural
which was that one could claim for himself only that
which he recognized equally for others. And Kant gave a generrights,
alization of this as the basis for his
cal
imperative
that
moral doctrine, the categori-
every act should be of such a character
made
same
judgment was one which carried
with it the sense of responsibility. As a rational being, one found
himself responsible for making such universal judgments; that
is, one assumed the responsibility of acting as he would wish
everyone else to act under the same conditions. If he should act
in that way, he must have the freedom so to act; otherwise he
would not be responsible for his act. The sense of responsibiUty
in man, then, leads to the postulate that he is free. In Kant's
that
it
could be
conditions.
Kant
universal for everyone under the
said that this
theory of experience, however, there could be no freedom.
Everything came under the law of cause and effect. If man's will
is
free, it
must be that
the self embodies in
his will, his self
it-
must be that it belongs to the
world of "things-in- themselves," and not to the world of our immediate, our phenomenal experience. But the order of the world
as it appears in experience is a mechanical order. That is, it is an
self
such a responsible
will; it
[7M
KANT AN PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
order in which the effect
cause
in
person could have,
that
it
is
the necessary result of the preceding
which, therefore, the idea, the end, the purpose that a
the idea or purpose involved in
all
life, is
such
can have no causal value. There can be no final cause in
a mechanical world.
And
yet, as
Kant pointed
out, our whole
understanding of that which is living, and our whole understanding of that which is beautiful, which is art, implies ends.
There is a determining purpose. There is something in our comprehension of the world which transcends the order of the
world as science presents it to us. And this something would
have to be found in the realm of "things-in-themselves," the
noumenal world.
fWell now, the Romantic movement, as I have said, grew out
of this phase of the Kantian doctrine. Kant thought of a mind
which gives laws to nature. But these laws which the mind
gives to nature are simply the forms of the mind, the molds into
which experience inevitably falls. If the mind has a certain
form, then its experience must take on that form. We postulate
freedom on the part of the individual, but we cannot know it.
cannot know ourselves in our freedom. We cannot help
postulating that we are free, but our knowledge of ourselves is
always a knowledge of cause and effect. For example, if a person
considers one of his acts, he inevitably explains it in terms of the
reasons for his conduct, and those reasons are expressed in terms
of his motives. One's explanation itself is one which seems to
wipe out the freedom which he attaches to his own conduct. One
feels responsible for one's acts, and yet they are explicable in
terms of cause and effect. This is a paradox, one of the antinomies that Kant says we cannot avoid. One does not, then, give
laws to nature in the sense that the self is the source of them.
We
The laws
are already there,
the empirical
self,
embodied
the self which
is
in the
mind
itself
not in
the concern of psychology,
but in the one that ha^_to be postulated as lying back of the
forms, a self which
is
freeO
In other words, the problem that
lies
back of skepticism and
Kant gave his critical
of the empirical school, and that to which
[77]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
answer, was met by the romanticists by the indentification of the
object of knowledge and the very process of knowledge in so far
was found in the self. Kant had to postulate that the
must be a thing-in-itself; or, at least, he had stated that this
as that
self
was a postulate that conduct involved.
volves the assumption that the self
All our conduct in-
a cause,
is
and that the con-
duct which results from this cause is accompanied by a sense of
obligation. Obligation implies freedom, and freedom implies
causation on the part of the
this self could
But, from Kant's standpoint,
self.
not enter into the
field
of knowledge;
it
could be
only a postulate.
In dealing with this problem, the Romantic scho ol
wen t back
to the experience of a self as involving itself as an obj ect. This
the experience which corresponds to the reflexive
I
was
referring. In that
mode, you
present as a subject only in so far as
and
is
will
mode
is
to
which
remember, the
self is
it is
present as an object,
present as an object only in so far as
it is
present as a
There cannot be one without the other. Our self-consciousness involves both of these essential characteristics. If,
now, one can make this relationship of subject and object a
primary relation in experience, one more fundamental_than
those of substance and attribute, cause and effect, then it can be
subject.
said that
we
have, in self-consciousness, the self presented- as
both subject and object.
This relationship guarantees the reality of our knowledge. It
does this not simply in the sense that there are certain experiences there, certain impressions and ideas, but in the sense that
there
is
a self there that finds an object in
itself.
That was the
him from
position of the romantic idealist that distinguished
the position of
self
Kant
was postulated
or of Descartes. /JCant affirmed that the
as an ultimate entity. It
was a reahty, but
could not possibly be known. Descartes affirmed that the self
must exist because we think; and because we think, we must be.
it
But he did not
posit an
thinking. It
to the experience of the self as such that the
is
romanticist goes back
immediate experience of the
that experience
[78]
in
which the
self in this
self is the
KANT ANB PHIL#SPHIC ROMANTICISM
most
real thing, the
most poignant reahty
the romanticist undertakes to carry back
all
in experience.
all
Then
experience, at least
cognitive experience, to this immediate experience of the
All other experiences flower out of this one.
self.
Now,
the romanticist, on coming back to the experience of the
found not only the evidence of existence which Descartes
has signalized in his Cogito ergo sum^ that is, found evidence not
only of the ego or self, but also found in that self an object of
knowledge such as Kant affirmed could not be found through introspection. It is this which gives the peculiar character to Romantic philosophy. It comes back to an experience in which
both subject and object are immediately given. In introspecself,
tion
that
is,
in the introspection of the
English empiricists,
Locke, Berkeley, and Hume^ one is dealing only with states of
consciousness, with impressions and ideas, or sensations and
images, but not directly with the self. Hume undertook to show
that the empirical self
of consciousness. That
is
simply an association of these states
is, it is
not primary, but secondary. It
some importance, an importance that gathers about the significance that comes from the body. This
self was analyzed by Hume into a set of relations, of associations. It was not an object of knowledge. That is, it was not
is
a congeries of
given as an object of knowledge in the process of knowledge,
and there was no way of reaching
knowledge, in that
process. The states of consciousness were those out of which the
self was built up; they were simply associated together into a
self. The self was not given first with the states dependent
it,
as
upon it. The states of consciousness that is, the impressions
and ideas were present, and they became associated with each
other in a certain pattern which constituted the self. If you
undertook to analyze this group of impressions and ideas, you
saw that they were simply associated together as those impressions and ideas which, when brought together, go to make
up a table, tree, or any other object. Kant took this same position as far as the empirical self was concerned. Such an object
was simply the organization of our so-called inner experiences,
[79]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
although Kant said that these
fall
under the categories of sub-
stance and attribute, cause and effect. But these categories be-
long to the mind, they do not actually reveal the self as an
entity, as a composition of these impressions
The Romantic
and
ideas.
philosophers, like their predecessors,
came
back to the age-old problem of knowledge: How can one get
any assurance that that which appears in our cognitive experience is real? The skepticism to which we have referred had
shattered all the statements, all the doctrines, of the medieval
philosophy. It had even torn to pieces the philosophy of the
Renaissance. As we have seen, it had destroyed the substantial
structure which had been presented in such a magnificent
fashion by Spinoza. It had shattered the natural structure of
the world which the Renaissance science had presented in such
simphcity and yet such majesty, that causal structure that led
Kant to say that there were two things that overwhelmed him,
the starry heavens above and the moral law within. This picture of a world which was the expression of simple but universal
laws had also been shattered by the skepticism of Hume, and
the only antidote that
Kant could present was the postulate of
conduct.
This
is
the old problem of assuring one's self of the reality
of one's cognitive experience, that our world_was not such^stuff"
as
dreams were made
there again for this
of,
that
was there
it
new philosophy
the romanticists approached
as
we know
to try its teeth
it,
upon.
was
And
of course, from the point of
it,
which was not simply an associawhich they came back was the p resupposition of such an experience, a self which was the most
view of the
but a
self,
tive experience.
The
self
self to
real thing in the experience of the
first
of
all,
largely
temperamental
moment. The assurance was,
an emotional experience.
was the assurance that the adolescent has that he
is
It
the most
important element in the whole universe, an assurance which
leads him to test everything from the point of view of his own
judgment. It was that assurance, but it was something more
too. It was an assurance that was backed up by this discovery
I80I
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
that one can, by taking the role of the other,
come back upon
himself and secure himself as a given object of knowledge. It
was
this, I
say,
losophy; and
it
which was the center of the Romantic phiwas by using this point of view, this leverage,
that the romanticists undertook to deal with the problem of
knowledge.
It
is
interesting to contrast this philosophy with that of
Spinoza, because he exerted a profound influence upon thinkers
of this period
who were
not technically philosophers
such men
was Uke the phiwas monistic. That is,
as Goethe, for example. Spinoza's philosophy
losophy of the Romantic school in that it
it came back to the conception of a single principle, a single
divine principle from which
all
that appears in experience
be thought of as arising, or within which
all
must
that was found in
experience could be conceived of as placed and ordered, getting
from this fundamental principle. The Spinozistic approach was from the point of view of substance. Spinoza's
EthicSy his principal philosophical work, starts with the definiits reality
tion of this divine principle as the causa sui, the cause of itself,
that which is responsible for itself, which does not look elsewhere for the reason for its existence. This was conceived of as
a fundamental substance which had an indefinite, infinite number of attributes, one of which was extension and another consciousness, or thought, as Spinoza expressed it. I have brought
that out to show that the positions of subject and object are in
these different respective philosophies. Spinoza's conception
have said, of a divine, substantial Being which exhibits itself
form both of extension and of thought. The world as we
think it, as we are conscious of it, is the same God, under the aspect of consciousness, as is the world of extension. It is the same
reality from two points of view. There is then a necessary pointfor-point relationship between the two. That is the Spinozistic
doctrine. Here you see the relationship between a subject that
knows and an object that is known. That relationship of subject and object belongs to the attributes of the one substance.
The relation between them, then, must be a one-to-one relaas
in the
fSil
is(
/
THOUGHT
tionship.
also
That
appear
is,
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
everything that appears in extension must
in thought,
and vice versa. Here
is,
among other
things, the beginning of the paralleHstic doctrine so widely used
in psychologies of today.
But the subject-object relationship
is
one that follows from the attributes of this substance. Substance and attribute have to be accepted, first of all, as the
fundamental character of reality; and it follows from this that
there should be a mind that knows an object, but it is the same
substance expressed both in the mind and in the obje^.l
(if one wanted to make a statement to bring this out from a
more concrete psychological standpoint, it would be a distinction between the sensation and that which is sensed, or what
modern psychology refers to as the "sensum," and the sensation
as the sensing. We can take it from either approach, either as
]
that sensed or as the sensing. In
we may say
somewhat the same fashion
that Spinoza conceived of this fundamental reality
is extended, and as that of which we are conBoth
are
the
same substance.
scious.
The romanticist comes back to a different form of experience,
that which is referred to in grammatical construction, as I have
pointed out above, as the reflexive mode. In this mode of experience we have both the subject and the object given in the
same process. Then, seemingly at least, we have something of
which we can be sure. If we know ourselves, we seem to have a
case of knowledge which can be depended upon. It is going back
both as that which
one sense, of course, to Descartes' syllogism or inference, "I
think, therefore I am." But Descartes was simply assuring himself of the existence of himself. What the romanticist is doing is
in
assuring himself of the existence of the object of his
though^ In
Descartes started off from the knowledge that he
whether that which he thought about existed was
another question, and he had a long metaphysical probe before
he got an answer to that question which satisfied him, and
which, incidentally, has not satisfied most philosophers who
have succeeded him. All the romanticist maintained was
that this attitude to which I am referring is an attitude that
his thinking,
existed; but
[82I
KANT AND PHILOSOPHIC ROMANTICISM
assures him, not only that he exists in his
also that the object of his
thought
own
thinking, but
exists, or that
not only he
exists in his consciousness but the object of his consciousness
also exists.
Where Descartes could
assure himself simply of the
existence of consciousness itself in the process of self-awareness, the Romantic philosopher assured himself of the existence of that of which he was conscious. Not only the thinker that thinks, but also that about which he thinks, exists
in this reflexive mode. For Descarte s, I am conscious and there-
fore exist; for the romanticist,
therefore this
is
of which
am
am
conscious of myself and
conscious, exists and with
it
knows. The object of knowledge, in this mode at
given as there with the same assurance that the thinker
the objects
least, is
self,
it
given in the action of thought.
If
one can make
this reflexive situation the central position
one can come back immediately to the
instead of to substance and attribute, one
in one's philosophy, if
consciousness of self
can say that this consciousness of self is at the center of the unia philosopher's
verse. In this, one has, so to speak, a test
stone by means of which one can determine what is given in
knowledge. It was, of course, a very sympathetic attitude for a
Romantic age.CThat is just what a romanticist does. All values
are those whicnTiefeels as a part of himself. Out of this experience, in which the mind, the soul, the individual, is both
subject and object, the romanticist builds a universe.
of this
mode becomes
The
self
the assured center of the universe, that
out of which the world is to be buHp^
I have just pointed out the elements of this identification be-
tween the self and the not-self. The very unity is assumed in
our experience. It is a unity which comes from the very process
of experience. The latter may be composed of an indefinite
number of diff'erent elements, and yet it appears as a unit,
organized and related with reference to our own organism.
Thus, the very unity of the object is the unity of the self. The
great sphere of the heavens is a projection of the sphere of the
eye; the straight line is a projection of the line of vision; our
[83]
THOUGHT
sensuous world
We
is
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the structure of our very process of sensation.
cut out, so to speak, the world in which
content of perception
is
we
are to act.
taken back to the content of our
The
own
sensation; the organization and content of the object can be
taken back to the
the object
is
self.
not the
Yet, the perception
self.
is
not the sensation;
In fact, the self can appear in experi-
ence only in so far as there
is
a not-self which yet has this very
self. As I have been saying, the fundamental opposition to which these romantic idealists came back
was this opposition between subject and object, with the assumption of a fundamental identity between them. The self and
the not-self are opposed to each other, and yet they are identical. Whether you take it from the point of view of morahty, as
Fichte did, or from the point of view of the artist's intuition,
with Schelling, or from that of thought, as Hegel worked it out,
there is always this opposition between the self and the notself; and yet underneath this opposition lies the assumption of
content and form of the
their identity.
84
CHAPTER V
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
WE
HAVE looked at the movement which we have
been discussing, namely, Romantic idealism, from
the point of view of its philosophic background, that
is,
Kant's
philosophy.
critical
We
the standpoint of the political
first
undertaking.
The
have looked at
revolution, which
it
also
from
failed in its
after-effect of this revolution
was
to
emphasize the self-consciousness of the individual of the period.
In the first place, Rousseau had undertaken to find in man the
principles upon which he could reconstruct the state, substituting a rational form of the state for the arbitrary form which belonged to the medieval system. This, as we have seen, proved
an immediate failure, and the Napoleonic imperialistic regime
came in to take the place of this attempted rational state. I
have said that the effect of this was to throw individuals back
upon themselves. Theoretically, they undertook to go back to
the old regime. And, returning to the regime from the standpoint of their own self-consciousness, they discovered in it what
they had not discovered before, namely, what is called its "romantic tang." They discovered the medieval period and all the
fascination of
period
the
its
pageantry, of the characteristic figures of the
knight-errant, the saint, the magician, and the
learned
man and
with
They went back
it.
they discovered the adventure that went
into that old pageantry with a fasci-
had never had for them before. That is the
romantic phase of the movement, this return to the old world
nation which
it
from the point of view of the new self-consciousness.
On
meant the return to the old
Kant had left it, from the point
thing-in-itself. Just, as in some
the philosophical side, this
rationalistic world, especially as
of view of the self regarded as a
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
was reconstructed from the point of
view of their romantic imagination, so a return was made to the
transcendental philosophy of Kant from the point of view of
sense, this older world
the self of ScheUing, and that of Hegel, the rowhich was identified with the Absolute Self, in which
individuals were conceived as mere finite expressions of this
larger Self. An attempt was made to deal with the problem
that philosophy presented from this standpoint. And we can
find that out of which this problem arose, or at least the materials it used, in Kant's antinomies.
Those antinomies represented for Kant the attempts of the
mind, its reason and understanding, to go beyond experience,
beyond the phenomenal world, to a noumenal world which it
was necessary for Kant to postulate. Every attempt of that
sort, according to Kant, meant an antinomy, a contradiction
in the terms that were used. For him these antinomies served
as the sign of warning that the mind had got beyond the limit
of its own legitimate use. The only path, as Kant saw it, by
means of which one could leave the field of experience, with its
fixed forms, was through the postulates of conduct. Here one
did not profess to know, in that one knew that one could not
know; but, nonetheless, one postulated a world of things-inthemselves, and particularly postulated a free will, that is, a
self that is free and which could, for that reason, assume obligaFichte's
mantic
self,
self
tions.
The Romantic
from
idealist started
postulate but as something which
not only given
is
this postulate
not as a
directly given in experience
in the sense of obligation,
which Kant recog-
nized, but given also in conduct, in the experience of freedom.
Romanticism
also recognized antinomies, that
that the passage from the conduct of the
is, it
recognized
self, this free self,
over
into the field of experience took place over contradictions or oppositions.
There are three attempts
to deal with the
problems to which
those of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel.
this situation gives rise
In a certain sense these represent a progression, a development.
[86
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
an attempt to solve the problem of the self
of moral experience; Schelling deals with
terms
and
it from the point of view of aesthetic or artistic experience; and,
most fundamental of all, Hegel deals with it in terms of logical
That of Fichte
is
its object in
experience, the experience of thought.
In a certain sense, there
is
an advance
in these three
under-
takings. The common problem is that of bringing the world
which seems to be independent of the self into the experience of
the self. It is quite true that in any self-experience we have both
subject and object.
But
does not follow that the experience
that one has of one's self is veritable. One is often deceived in_
regard to himself. This is especially true in a romantic mood.
But
at least the self
is
it
there as an object in experience.
senses himself as there, and he
The
is
and the subject is
The two are brought together./But now the problem
has at the time.
can that
mode
object
is
One
there in the attitude which he
there,
there.
arises,
be used to bring over into the self the world
which is seemingly not the self? Can the world which is independent of the self be brought into its self-experience? The experience which we depend upon for the direction of our conduct,
that which we call "objective," has to do with things that are
not ourselves. We have to find out about them. They are in
some sense foreign to us. We have to learn their ways; learn
what nature is, what its laws are. CarLthis world of reality outside of uSj^ the world with which we have become acquainted,
be brought into this relation of subject and object which we have
in self-consciousness? This, I say, was the problem of the romjinticisti^.j This was the problem, the adventure which called
these thinkers. Given a subject and an object of knowledge in
the self-experience itself, can one go out to the great universe
that dominates the self, that precedes and antedates it, that
outlasts it, that is so independent of it, and capture that universe and make it a part of one's own self-experience?
The Romantic idealists came back to the process of the self.
We have seen the background of this. The self was looked at
not as a static affair; it was not conceived of in the medieval
[87I
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
body and
was endowed by a divine fiat.
Rather, the self was looked upon as a certain process, something
sense as a soul that was born into the world with the
changed the body, a
that
is
The
self that
going on.
first
characteristic of this process
upon was that
it
involved a not-self.
which Fichte
The very
self implies a not-self; it implies a not-self
tified
with the
self.
You have
laid stress
existence of the
which can be iden-
seen that the term "self"
is
a reflexive affair. It involves an attitude of separation of the
self
Both subject and object are involved in the self
exist. The self must be identified, in some
with the not-self. It must be able to come back at itself
from
itself.
in order that
sense,
it
may
from outside. The process, then, as involved
in the self is the
subject-object process, a process within which both of these
phases of experience
lie,
a process in which these different
phases can be identified with each other
not necessarily as the
same phase but at least as expressions of the same process. This,
you see, makes a different thing out of knowledge than does the
copy theory.
The copy theory of knowledge goes back to ancient thought.
It assumes that the object impresses its form on the mind. A
favorite analogy, of course, is from vision. In some way the form
of the object impresses itself on the retina, and from the retina
on the mind itself. The camera obscura of the eye has served
unwittingly on the part of philosophy as determining knowledge
from the impressions of experience. As Aristotle thought of it,
the form of the thing in some way floated through the eye into
the mind. It impressed itself there on the mind. Sometimes the
mind was spoken of as a wax tablet on which the form was impressed. This is an analogy of which the empiricist made use.
It is a static theory of knowledge. Knowledge is simply the reception of a certain form impressed upon the mind. The object
in this case
the
mind
does not necessarily involve the subject. It involves
as
the doctrine
The
first
something on which
is
it
can be impressed. As far as
concerned, that mind might be subject or not.
attack
made upon
the problem, the one
made by
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
Fichte,
was through the development of the Kantian
principles
into the philosophy of romanticism. Specifically, he utilized the
moral experience which was the center of the Kantian metaphysics. In this moral experience, as we have seen, the individual identifies himself with his duty. In this philosophy Fichte
took a step beyond Kant. Kant never got beyond the formal
character of conduct. Our conduct is moral, he says, in so far as
it is universal. We test it by seeing whether or not we can make
a universal law out of the maxim of our act. The Fichtean position is one that goes beYQnd this and identifies the self with the
task to be performed. fThis Fichte presents as the reality of the
moral experience that one finds before him something to be
done and then, in the doing, finds himself identified with it. It
is
not only a task:
it is
his task.
He
is
involved in
And
it.
the
accomplishment of the task, the doing of the duty, realizes the
is just in so far as one does what he has to do
that he becomes really moral. It is only in so far as he identifies
himself with an undertaking that he achieves himself. We speak
of this process as the "development of character," and we speak
individual. It
of "character" as the core of one's personality.
is
Now,
character
attained only in so far as one does identify himself with the
situation which presents itself before the moral vision. Selfhood
is
attained in a process in which the individual identifies him-
self
with his task.
The
individual
realizes
himself in
that
processT^
This
is
the point of approach in Fichte's philosophy. For the
individual the world
is
always a task to be accomplished.
It is
not simply there by chance, as something that just happens.
because one realizes it as a field for one's endeavors.
not a world simply in so far as there are sensations, in so
It is there
It is
far as there is the
movement
of masses of bodies. It
a real thing, just to the extent that one constructs
is
it,
a world,
that one
The objects about one are means
They take on meaning in proportion as one uses
them as means. The ground is something to tread upon. The
objects about one are all implements. The universe is a field of
organizes
it
for one's action.
of conduct.
[89I
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
is
the conduct of the individual; and
up
lies in
his
world as such a
the individual
way
in
it. Its meanwhen one has built
organized only in so far as one acts in
action. It
ing
who
field
of action, then he realizes himself as
carried out that action. \That
which he can achieve a
One does not
self.
is
the only-
get at himself
simply by turning upon himself the eye of introspection. One
realizes himself in what he does, in the ends which he sets up,
and in the means he takes to accomplish those ends. He gets the
rational organization out of
means and ends, puts
it
it,
sees a relationship
between
together as a plan; and then he
all
realizes that the plan of action presented in this situation is
expression of his
has such a
field
own
reason, of himseljll
an
not until one
is
what
is
continually taking place.
self throws up the world as a field within which action
must take
it
it is
of action that he does secure himself. This
process, according to Fichte,
The
And
place; and, in setting
up the world
as a field of action,
realizes itself.
This
is,
of course, just putting into philosophical form the re-
discovery of the medieval period as that in which the self could
imaginatively act and then come back upon
process
is
itself.
In this the
carried out in a dramatic fashion, under an aesthetic
mood. Fichte raises it to a process within a moral world in
which the individual organizes the world into a field in which he
must act.
However, the problem is not yet solved. It is true that the
meaning which our world has does lie in what we are going to
do with it. The meaning of the world is not to be found in its
atoms and molecules, in its electrons. Their framework, whether
they shall take on the form of trees or of men, depends upon the
experience of those who inhabit the world. You can look on it as
just a congeries of electrons, but that does not
that
we
inhabit.
pends upon living
eyes that paint the world in
resonances.
that live in
It is this
it.
make
the universe
meaning of Hfe is something that debeings, upon conscious beings, beings with
All the
And
its colors,
with ears that give
it its
world that arises out of the individuals
world of physical things is there,
yet, this
[90]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
comes into existence in
condition
for
the
seems
to
be
a
existence of the self.
it.
Fichte simply assumed that the Absolute Self, which is the organization of all selves, built up such a world, set it up as the
field of endeavor, that it might realize itself. But there is an independence about this world. It is the scene of endeavor, but
and
it is
there seemingly before the self
In fact,
still it is
it
a scene that has to be given before endeavor, in order
that the latter can take place.
Our
scientific picture of the
world
independent of the individual who inhabits it. He comes into
it, and it may be the scene of his endeavor. It may take on his
values, the values of society, but still it is there in advance of
him. It does not seem to be dependent upon him in any way.
is
This was the period
in which evolutionary thought first apwas presented first in the hypothesis of Lamarck,
later in that of Darwin. Thus, the conception was before men;
and that conception holds that man and all that man means
are dependent upon the prior
his self-consciousness, his values
development of a physical universe the appearance of continental masses which kept the earth from being completely
peared.
It
immersed. It is quite possible, quite conceivable, of course, that
the water might have covered everything. There is enough
water to cover the whole of the earth if the continents should
be plunged into the depths of the sea. Had this been the case,
man, of course, would not have appeared. What life there would
have been would be the vertebrates in the ocean, and perhaps
not even these. There might have been only unicellular forms
that float upon the surface of water. It would seem to be
simply by chance, then, that the world developed such a species
as man. After all, it is our scientific knowledge
the most clear
knowledge that we have that presents man as an accident and
not as an essential product of the nature of the universe.
Of course, it is true that on the moral side man is the center
of the universe. The moral world is there because of man, for,
if there was no self-consciousness, there would be no morality,
no claim that one could make upon another, no society with its
contentions, customs, and laws. Morality is dependent upon
[91]
THOUGHT
man; and
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Fichte remained within his moral phi-
as long as
losophy, he could conceive of the self as responsible for the
world. But
when he attempted
to
make
the development of the
world itself simply a phase of the moral experience of man, he
found himself in a clash with the surest knowledge that we have.
The attempt to build up science, knowledge, out of this moral
experience was not successful on Fichte's part.
Of course, Fichte had attempted this on the basis of the development of a dialectical argument which goes a step beyond
what Kant called his "transcendental logic." Kant, you remember, said that there was an analytic logic that simply breaks up
an idea into its different parts and then affirms one of those
for example, the conception of man as
having essentially an animal nature, and of that animal nature
as being, in its very essence, mortal. You cannot think of an
animal or of man without also thinking of mortality as a part
of them. That, says Kant, is the pure analytic process, a process
in which you are merely confirming an idea of an object which
parts of the conception
already belongs to
If
it
you say, "Socrates
in the
is
very conception of the object
man," you already
state, in the con-
ception of Socrates as a man, the idea of mortality. But,
contends,
when we come
started, that
Euclid,
is,
itself.
Kant
which he
the axioms of
to the sort of judgment with
the judgments that
we come upon judgments
we
find in
that are of a different type.
Kant's illustration was of a straight line being the shortest
distance between two points. You can analyze the idea of a
straight line as much as you want and you will not find in it the
idea of the shortest distance between two points. This latter is
something added to the former idea; and Kant asked how such
judgments, which he called "synthetic judgments a priori,"
could be formed. It is easy enough, he said, to see how we can
form empirical judgments involving something new. You find
out something about your friends, you add to your ideas about
them through experience; but that is not the process of synthetic judgments a priori but of synthetic judgments a posteriori. That is, they are empirical judgments, in which we find
[9^1
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
something that we did not find before, but something that has
been given through experience. But judgments such as the
Euclidian axioms are judgments that stand at the beginning of
your science. You have them as postulates with which you can
start. Kant's explanation of this is in the forms of the mind
which determine the nature of our experiences. They are, so to
speak, the capital with which our science operates. These forms
are given in advance of experience and make such synthetic
judgments a priori possible. Now this sort of logic Kant distinguishes from the other analytic type by calling it transcendental. Thus we can affirm everything of our experience which
belongs to the structure of the forms of the sensibility and of the
understanding. At least, Kant thought so. He was quite sure
that he had the whole structure of our possible experience, that
he had anatomized the whole of our experience and could show
just what its form was and must continue to be. But this description is static. According to it, the forms are all there and
nothing
is
added to them. They do not require any process of
development.
Fichte's world was not one of static forms. It was a world in
which there was opposition between the self and a not-self which
took the form of a task that had to be done, an obstacle that had
to be overcome^ He undertook particularly to show that moral
conduct consists in the assimilation of the not-self to the self.
He assumed that the self set up, posited, a world that was a
not-self and that this not-self had to become the self. That is
the antimony which Fichte says has to be overcome in moral
conduct. This is the central point in his position. The very
thing that we feel we must do is the thing that seems foreign to
us. It represents interests which we do not recognize, which are
not our own. And yet we feel the moral necessity of making
them our own. Effort that has to be expended is effort not
simply in doing something but effort expended in making something one's own interest which at first is not an interest. And
yet one recognizes that this interest which is not one's own
ought to be a part of one's self. One has certain obligations to
[93]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the group to which he belongs. These are duties which really
make him
a part of the
community. They cannot be divorced
from the person. He is a free member of the community, but
on the condition that he exercises the rights and the duties of
citizenship. It
is
this that
makes him a
free
member
of the com-
munity. There could not be any community unless the individual did do his duties, and yet he finds them to be a nuisance.
He does not want to take the trouble to vote, to enter into a
campaign. He wants to do other things that he feels are identified with himself, things which he is interested in doing. And
yet he wants to be a member of a democratic community, and
he wants to have the rights of citizenship, with all that citizenship means. That is something which is not the self and yet
which
is
essential to the self.
That
is
sists in so assimilating this
the attitude which
we
all
Moral conduct conobligation that it becomes a real
recognize as appearing in our moral
life.
and not just a disagreeable duty. It is
moral life that Fichte comes back in endeavoring to present this view of his in regard to the nature of
the self, namely, that it constantly transcends the not-self which
is to be made part of the selTT
^
The antinomical contradiction is there, but it is in a different
form from the Kantian one which indicates the limits beyond
which knowledge cannot go. Fichte says the contradiction represents an actual step in the development of reality, of the
self. The self grows by overcoming those obstacles, by making them its own interests. That assumption that reality is a
process of development, the development of the self, is the first
step in the idealistic dialectic. This is what reality is. And this
development takes place over obstacles or contradictions.
Fichte can, of course, point to other phases besides that moral
phase to which I have just referred, but this is the one that is
central to his position. He can point particularly to the very
nature of the self. The self is a type of experience which we attain only by becoming, in a certain sense, not-selves. That is,
we cannot get the experience of ourselves as selves except in so
interest of the individual
to that phase of the
[94]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
far as
we take
the attitude of another and regard ourselves from
that point of view. There
pain; there
may
may
be the experience of pleasure, of
be the presence of colors and sounds about us;
and yet these do not become ours in the sense that we recognize
them as ours unless we can in some sense distinguish ourselves
from other selves. We have to realize ourselves by taking the
role of another, playing the part of another, taking the attitude
of the
community toward
ourselves, continually seeing ourselves
from the standpoint of
not the self-consciousness that goes with
as others see us, regarding ourselves
those about us. This
is
awkwardness and uneasiness.
one's
own
It
is
the assured recognition of
position, one's social relations, that
comes from being
able to take the attitude of others toward ourselves.
recognize our rights in
We cannot
demanding them of others without being
ourselves in their place and recognizing their rights. W^e have to
put ourselves in place of the other to recognize the self. Here
again Fichte can come back to a character of the self which involves a not-self. There must be a not-self in order that the
self
may
exist.
CFichte's idealism, like that of others of this Romantic idealistic school, is what is called "Absolute Idealism." That is, it
an Absolute Self of which our selves are
expressions. We have seen that, for Kant, the con-
assumes that there
mere
finite
is
ceptions of the infinite and the finite represent one of the antin-
omies or group of antinomies that indicate the limits of our
possible knowledge. For Fichte it represents the relationship
between the finite self and the Absolute Self. He said that the
self could not posit itself as a finite self without at the same
time positing an infinite, unconditioned, and Absolute Self. To
posit one's self as finite involves identifying one's self with the
Absolute.
ate
God
As Fichte expressed
every day."
It is the
it
in a
picturesque way, 'T cre-
very experience of realizing one's
self as a finite self that involves the
assurance of the identity
or centering of the self in the Absolute
Self.'^
Fichte lived during the early part of the nineteenth century,
when Germany was under
the domination of Napoleon.
[95]
The
THOUGHT
French were
Germans
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
in control,
and naturally there arose among the
a national sense of opposition to this invasion of the
outsider within their borders; and there arose
national
movement which
finally, in
among them
the
conjunction with the move-
Germany and
Napoleon. It was a great national and moral
movement in Germany, and Fichte was one of its spokesmen.
In Berlin, where he had been appointed professor of philosophy,
he delivered a series of addresses to the German people, in which
he summoned them to their task. They were very stirring addresses, and called out echoes throughout the whole of Germany. They emphasized a new type of national life, one that
was not expressed in the relation of the Hohenzollerns to their
ments
in
other countries, drove the French out of
led to the defeat of
subjects.
Frederick the Great was the
man who
had, up to this time,
administered Prussia from the top down.
who
He was
monarch
recognized himself not simply as monarch of the state but
His control was absolute. He took his subjects with him into various wars in which they had no immediate
those
interest and which were of doubtful moral character
wars in which Poland was defeated, in which Prussia seized
Silesia from Austria, wars of the Austrian Succession, wars in
which Frederick was fighting for the aggrandizement of his
house and of his kingdom, but wars which were not an expression of a popular movement. They were not wars that grew out
of an expression of a demand of the people for an interest with
which they identified themselves. The immediate successors of
Frederick did not have his genius or his power; but, nonetheless,
there grew up under the conditions of the new period an ideal
of a national life that could defend itself against the invader and
estabhsh itself again on its own, new national basis. It was out
of this movement that the nation at arms arose. The army of
Frederick the Great was an army which he chose from among
the people for the purposes of his miHtary undertakings. This
new movement was the one in which universal military service,
with the nation as such in arms, appeared for the first time.
also as the state.
[96]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
Furthermore, there was behind this movement a recognition
that there must be intelhgence, a popular inteUigence, one that
did not come simply from the populace up or from the top
down, but which permeated the nation as a whole. With this
military service went popular education; and for a few intensive
years there grew up in Prussia a national Hfe which made an
entirely different power out of it, one that was able to cope with
the genius of Napoleon and with his armies.
The immediate political and social background of Fichte,
then, was the war in which the western and eastern states drove
Napoleon out of Germany and Austria. With this background,
Fichte appealed very vividly to the national sense of the Prussians, presenting this task to them as one which the people
themselves had to undertake. He pictured a German nation
which had certain definite duties before it which it must meet,
but meet with intelligence, comprehension, with a recognition
that morality rests upon intelligence. It was distinctly a historical situation in which the people had to create their own
approach, and create it in terms of a task which they had to
fulfil.
They had
course, in such a
past, a nation has
to reaHze themselves in that task. It
is,
of
movement of defensive warfare that, in the
come most completely to consciousness of it-
has achieved a national self-consciousness in fulfiUing such
a duty as that of meeting an enemy already within its borders,
an enemy already breaking down the organization of its own
self,
Here, then, is a task which has to be accomplished,
something that has to be done, in the face of danger and suffering of every sort. And in that there is attained national selfconsciousness which does not exist under ordinary conditions.
Under the latter, we buy and sell, we carry out our usual social
processes. In a vague sort of way we all know that we are
members of the same community, but we are not conscious of
it. We find ourselves in more or less hostile relations with our
competitors, and we do not identify ourselves with the comstate.
munity as a whole. But in other moments, such as this of
which I have been speaking, when the community has to defend
[97]
THOUGHT
itself against
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
an enemy that has already taken possession,
common undertaking, identify themand get that larger self-consciousness to
people get together in a
selves with each other,
which Fichte was appealing. This occurs in just that sort of a
situation which I have expressed metaphysically as the self
realizing itself in the not-self, finding its not-self in the duty
which it has to perform, and in doing that duty, in making it
its own, reaching a higher self-consciousness than it had before.
Warfare is not the only way in which that has been achieved in
the past, but it is one of the most common ways. It seems to be
the easiest way in which people can recognize themselves as
belonging to the same community, the same group. This they
achieve in that attitude of defense against a common enemy.
And it was just such a situation that lay behind Fichte and
which he put into his form of the Romantic philosophy.
This situation he conceived to be not only the very process of
national consciousness but also that of the universe itself. This
very not-self, this separation, so to speak, of the task from the
person who has accomplished it, is what Fichte comes back to,
to explain the world as something that is there over against the
self and which the self cannot control, or at least for which the
self does not seem to be responsible. [The moral situation to
which I have referred is one in which, to a certain extent, we do
create our own field in so far as we assume a certain task. But
the world itself is a world of physical things, is one which is not
the self. It is a not-self in a different fashion. The task which
one does not want to assume is a not-self. But that it is a task
at all is due to the fact that we accept it as a task. We accept the
universe. The moral universe, like the physical, is there because
we do accept it. If we did not have a moral attitude toward it,
it would not be there.
But, seemingly, the physical world is
there anyway, and that was the problem that Fichte had to
work out philosophically.^
How
could he take this moral point of view over into the
which the individual does not set up a not-self as
and then overcome it? How was he to identify this
situation in
a task
[9]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
subject-object relation with that of our cognitive experience,
with that of the world we are aware of about us? Can these two
be brought together? That was his problem. How could he take
our awareness of a world there independently of us and identify
it with this moral attitude in which the individual does set up
a task which, for the time being, hes outside himself but with
which he
later identifies himself?
That, as
of Romantic philosophy as Fichte presented
He must make
itself to Fichte.
say,
it,
was the task
or as
it
presented
the subject-object relation as
it
appears in our moral experience a relation of the knower to the
known, a relation between that which we sense and the organ-
ism which senses
the
it,
a relation between that which
mind that thinks
it.
Can one
we
think and
identify this relation with the
moral relation? Fichte undertakes to do this, and it is an undertaking in which he was only partially successful. The picture
he presents of the world is that of a task, a picture of a not-self
which in a certain sense is foreign to the individual. It is something that has to be overcome, and, being overcome, is made a
part of the self. If, now, Fichte could conceive of the world in a
moral sense, he could conceive of it in some sense as the creation
of that
self.
Remember how Kant
problem? For Kant there was
a world of science, of knowledge. Of course, science is nothing
but exact knowledge. The world is determined by the very
characters which the mind has stamped on it. The mind gives
these laws not by choice but because they reflect its structure.
They are parts of its own structure; they are molds, so to
speak, in which experience falls when it comes to the mind.
left this
But the mind does not give
in
which a
act.
man
Here he
itself
those laws in the
same sense
regards himself as giving the character to his
feels his
own responsibility, for he recognizes
own initiative. Thus he is responsi-
the act as coming from his
ble for his act in a
way
in
which he
is
not responsible for the
laws of nature which are given in the forms of his sensibility
and of his understanding.
But Fichte conceived of the world
[99]
as being essentially moral,
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
not simply as something that
is
known.
It
has moral significance,
presents kself as a task, as an accomplishment that must
be carried outQif the self could be free, if it could have initiative
for
it
in its
moral conduct, then,
could be the creation of the
its
task, just as
the world
self.
is,
That
born into
free in
the world
The
self
was
a moral world,
it
could be free in giving
doing or not doing
its
task.
And
yet
of course, independent of any one finite individual's
is,
it;
it is
if
self.
some sense we find the world given.
and it remains behind us. How is it
in
we
die,
to conceive of the self as creating such a world
From
We
are
possible
the moral
standpoint one does, in a certain sense, create his immediate
world.
That
is,
one makes
his
it
own
task.
One
finds himself in
the midst of an immediate environment, something that
is
from the point of view of his own
responsibility^ That responsibility may be infinitesimal as compared to the'whole universe, but still that universe exists for
one as that for which he is in some sense responsible. He has to
get his day's work done. He has to select out and organize
this world about him in such a way that he can carry out
his task. The ground on which he treads, the means of transportation which he selects, the building he enters, and the
apparatus that he uses are all organized by him with reference
there; but he organizes
it
to his particular function. It
only in so far as
is
it
is
there,
way that he can act on it, that he can do his
always organizing one's world with reference to
one's duty, with regard to the function which he has to carry
out. He looks at the world from the standpoint of the means
which he can make use of to carry out his function. That may
organized in this
duty.
One
is
be a small part of the world, but for him
the ground upon
mind, organized with
reference to carrying out the act which is his own.
So much for the world so far as the particular individual is
concerned. If we extend this response and take in all the individuals in society, we can see that they can all, in some sense,
create the world in which that society lives, caUing out the
ideas that belong to that society. All men are, in some sense,
which he can tread. Everything
is,
loo
in his
it is
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
organized in so far as they belong to a single society; and as that
society clears
its
ates a world in
land, sows
which
it
its
crops, builds its buildings,
can definitely
it
cre-
and each man has
live,
his part in that society as a whole.
Now what the philosophical imagination of Fichte did was to
go beyond this conception which united man with society, and
to conceive of the man as an integral part of the universal Self,
that Self which created the universe.
We
are
all
of us, as St.
Paul says, parts of one another. That is true. We all of us have
content which belongs to us only in so far as we share the self-
hood of
that
others.
we belong
We
see ourselves as others see us.
to gives us our peculiar selves.
The
society
We belong to that
We are what we are because we belong to that society,
and yet that society is nothing but an organization of selves.
TNow, what Fichte did was to conceive of an Absolute Self which
IS just such an organization of all selves; an in finite Self which is
the organization of all finite selves. Then, just as society sets
its^faskis fnrtermsljf'tlie act of all its members, so this infinite
and Absolute Self sets the task for itself in terms of all the funcsociety.
make
The
tions of
all
the finite selves that go to
as such
is,
then, the creation of this Absolute Self in the
it
up.
universe
same
sense as cultivated areas and great metropolitan areas are cre-
ated by the society that lives in them. This Selfjxeates
world, and
it
creates
it
as a set of things to be
its
own
donej Fields are
cultivated to be reaped, to grow the grain that can be harvested.
The means
of transportation, the tasks that have to be carried
out on the part of the personnel, everything of this sort, is an
some member of society. Now
then, enlarge this conception so that you can conceive of an
Absolute Self that is made up out of an infinite number of different selves, and the universe as the expression of that Self, as a
expression of the function of
casting-up, so to speak, of a place in which that Self can act, as
and
you get Fichte's conception of an Absolute Self of which all individuals are merely separate parts. In this view we are all parts
of God. We each have a finite part in an infinite creative power.
the expression of the task which that Self has to carry out,
[lOl]
THOUGHT
Organized
in the
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
one Self we, together with an
of other selves, create the universe.
is
And
infinite
number
for Fichte this creation
moral, for he conceives of the world as an obligation, as a
task which the Absolute Self has to carry out, has to
This, then,
philosophy.
is
fulfil.
the point of view from which Fichte built his
And we have
seen that
it
goes back to a point in
Kant's philosophy. Fichte assumed that the self is causal, prois, however, in the moral realm that these
characteristics apply to it. Accepting Kant's two postulates,
that in the moral realm we determine our conduct and that the
mind, through its forms, determines the character of nature,
Fichte turned to the moral world and found it to be the field
ductive, creative. It
of action. It
is
what
it is
in order that the self
may
act.
And,
without going back to the metaphysics of it, we do find that
situation in our own experience to a very considerable degree.
When we make
a moral decision, we have more or less definitely
determined the character of the situation. If a man, for example, assumes that he is under obligation to undertake a certain duty in the community that, for example, he should go
and be a watcher at the polls he places this over against each
of the other of his different obligations. He has to relate them
all to one another. If he carries out this duty, he may place
himself in considerable danger. He has to consider what that
danger would mean. He has to relate it to his other obligations.
He has to consider, on the other hand, what his duties as a
citizen are. In doing all this he constructs a certain definite
field which has the form which in some sense he gives to it.
That is, those values as related to each other are values which
express the man. What he does will be an expression of the man
himself. If he is of a timid nature, he tends to avoid obligations
that come to him from outside, and prefers to let somebody
else carry on the public functions of the community; and the
chances are that he will construct the sort of situation in which
his own immediate interests will bulk larger than any others,
while those of the public will be given an insignificant character.
The sort of a world in which he will live will be very different
102
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
from that of a man who recognizes his pubHc duties, who comes
forward even under conditions of considerable risk, standing on his own legs refusing to be jolted, taking the duties
that come with the occasion, and playing the part of a good
citizen. His world will be a different world from that of the
other. The comparative values which they give will make out
of their actions and out of the objects upon which they act two
very different sorts of situations. Each creates a definite field of
action by the attitude that he takes.
Now this is true, of course, in another sense in regard to our
sense perception.
Our
our attitude, our contact exsome sense the sort of world in which
vision,
periences, do determine in
but over this we have no control. If we have eyes, we
world of colors. If we are colorblind, these colors are
perhaps Hmited to only two. If we have islands of deafness,
there are certain parts of the sounding world that are shut off
we
live;
live in a
from
us.
In the other case, the moral case, the
termines the sort of world he lives
in.
terms of his duties, his obligations,
He
man
also de-
up the world in
and thus makes it of one
builds
sort or another.
It is to this sort
of constructive character of the world that
Fichte comes back.
And
here,
can say
in passing, his phi-
losophy branches off from Kant's, which was entirely formal in
character. Fichte recognizes this constructive character, as was
shown in the illustration above. A man builds up a world in
which the self-government of the community can take place, in
which the political rights of the individual are respected. There
are certain values which are identified with himself, and his
conduct tends to build up such a world as that. In this sense his
conduct is creative. What the situation is depends upon ourselves. We may have the souls of rabbits and retire from everything that involves risk, live in a little world which is secure
from danger; or we may have a sense of moral adventure and go
out to live in a broader, wider world^ It depends upon the individual as to what kind of a world he fives m.J Fichte, in going
back to Kant's self as a creative power, identified that creative
[103]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
power with the moral impulse, the impulse to map out a world
which constitutes one's duty.
And here Fichte comes back to that moral self that I have
already referred to by way of illustration. The duty that arises
before a
man
at the time of an election
is
distinctly a not-self.
He
does not want to take the time, run the risks, go to all the
inconvenience which the occasion requires. This is something
that distinctly
lies
outside of himself at the time.
He
inter-
is
ested in his immediate environment, in an immediate occupa-
and here
tion,
is
something which presents
itself
from outside.
For the time being, it is distinctly, definitely, not the self that
the man is up to that time. If he accepts this as a duty, builds
up this world in which he feels he ought to act, he is definitely,
perhaps, for the time being, unwillingly, identifying himself
What
comes back to in the end is that a man cannot
and not accept these obligations. He cansomebody else do what he ought to do. He feels that he
with
it.
keep
his self-respect
not
let
it
has to identify himself with this particular situation.
make
it
his
own. This
situation. First of
all
is
definitely
what takes place
has to
in
such a
the task appears as a not-self, as some-
thing outside of himself.
He
disagreeable, foreign to his
just through recognizing
has to come to terms with it.
own immediate interests; but
it as,
for the
It is
it is
time being, foreign to his
own interests that he can get an idea of himself,
come to a higher self-consciousness than he had
comes
He
that he can
before.
to see himself as a person shirking his duties in the
He
com-
munity, as a person "letting George do it," refusing to take
over the tasks that belong to him. He sees himself in this situation from the point of view of this not-self which he created
when he set up this particular task before him; and by identifying himself with the not-self, he definitely becomes a larger, a
more effective self than he was before.
It is in that sort of a process that the individual recognizes
and from the point of view of that not-self that he
recognizes the self that answers to it. Then, through the actual
doing of the duty, through the accompHshment of his task, the
a not-self,
104
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
individual becomes a larger
self.
process, a subject-object process,
Fichte assumed that that
was the fundamental one in
the universe. Therefore, he was not concerned with the rela-
and attribute. This dynamic process, which
opposed to Kant's static account of the problem, Fichte found
in the moral experience of the individual. If a self is to be a
tion of substance
is
self, it
must achieve
this in the identification of itself
with the
overcoming any opposition between the self and
that which lies outside of it. This is the fundamental process
of the universe from Fichte's point of view. In its duty the
not-self, thus
self recognizes itself as a not-self,
then
identifies itself
it
the not-self and so becomes a larger and
more
with
effective self.
Thus, from Fichte's standpoint, the relation of the subject and
the object, in the moral sense, is the fundamental relation in the
universe.
Of
course, the basic metaphysical relation
is
that of subject
and object. Fichte wanted to distinguish the philosophy of the
Romantic school from that of the philosophy which, in some
sense, largely influenced this movement, namely, that of
Spinoza. He found the distinction between these two in this:
for Spinoza, as has already been said, the fundamental relation
was that of substance and attribute, while for the Romantic
school the fundamental metaphysical conception is that of subject and object. Spinoza said that there could be but one substance. He defined substance as that which is the cause of
itself.
stance.
ticists,
From
this definition there
could be only one such sub-
Fichte's philosophy too, like that of the other
roman-
centers in the conception of one Ultimate Being; but
in this case it is described as
an Absolute Self
selves center. Fichte insisted that the self
is
in
which
created in
all finite
its
moral
The
our own
conduct. But what reference has this to the universe?
about us seemingly not as the result of
is there in advance of us and will
be there when we are gone. It has an infinite extent, and we are
finite and ephemeral creatures. In what sense, then, can we be
latter exists
experience, of our creation. It
its
creators?
[105]
THOUGHT
The
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
made
answer that question
are those of Fichtej Schelhng, and Hegel. The first attempt was
a severely moral one. It does not, perhaps, present itself in the
guise of adventure, the romantic attitude. The justification
which Fichte gave for this attitude is that which I have been
presenting. We are under obligation to identify ourselves with
this world which is there before us. That is, the world exists as a
field of moral endeavor. The reason that it seems to be so independent of us is that it is a duty, something that has to be done,
in a certain sense an obstacle to be overcome. But when the
duty has been done, then that which was foreign has been identified with the self. I have described this process in regard to the
duties of citizenship. The process is, of course, from Fichte's
point of view, a moral self-experience, that of meeting a world
which is not the self and making it the self. The duty which is
done ceases to be the not-self and becomes the self. And not
only is this true, but it is only from the point of view of what
was the not-self that one is able to realize the self. First of all,
one may regard one's self from the standpoint of disapprobation. He sees the thing he ought to do and does not want to do.
He sees that he ought to love, but actually he hates. This is that
division which St. Paul presents so poignantly. The "other
man" has to be overcome in some sense. One looks at himself
from the standpoint of duty. And then there comes approbation from the standpoint of the achieved self, the quiet conthree different attempts
to
science which indicates that the individual, the
with himself. Thus
it is
revealed that
it is
self, is
at peace
only from the point of
view of the not-self that the individual can reach himself. It
is not simply that one grasps the world in making it himself, in
doing his duty, but that one grasps himself in identifying himself
with that duty. He gets a standard from which to judge himself
when he identifies himself with the duty he ought to do. Then
he can pass judgment on himself. When the duty is done, he can
be at peace. He has in this way identified himself with the
object.
It is not
only an adventure in capturing the universe, so to
f
106I
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
speak, and bringing
also
it is
it
within the range of a self-experience, but
an adventure
mutual ex-
in discovering one's self, a
perience both for the world and for the self. That is an experience which we go through with unaffected by the sense of duty.
beyond the position of Kant. You remember, Kant
sets up a categorical imperative. One must make the maxim for
one's act a universal law, and one must act solely from his sense
of respect for law, not from inclination. For Kant, immorality
is only that conduct which is motivated without this respect for
law, this sense of duty. We must do what we are to do from a
sense of duty. From Kant's standpoint, if an act is done from
It
is
a step
inclination
it is
can
it
is
not moral. It
not necessarily immoral, but
is
non-moral. Epigrammatically, Schiller put
I
be sure
if I
am
and
right in loving
it
assisting
thus,
my
"How
friends?
it from inclination and may
must hate them. Then, at least,
I will know that when I assist them I do so from a sense of
duty." But the Romantic moraHst goes a step beyond Kant.
His doctrine is: So succeed in identifying yourself with your
duty that it becomes your inclination. Your friends are yourself, and you can assist them with the real affection that goes
do it from
be wrong. If I
If
affection, I
am
am
doing
to be sure,
with friendship. It
is
true that, at least in moral experiences in
which there is a problem involved, we go through exactly such
an experience as this to which Fichte comes back, the experience, that is, in which the world takes the form of a task to be
performed. If
it is
to be done, then everything takes its rela-
tionship to that task.
which the task
as
it is
to be,
is
is
The whole
thing
to be carried out.
is
simply a
The world
as
field
it
within
was, and
there as the field in which this very disagreeable
thing has to be gone through with. It
taking and endeavor.
and we have come
Now,
to realize
is
a field of moral under-
after the task has been
it
in
terms of our
attitude of separation, of division,
is
107]
performed
self,
then this
overcome and we do identiwe have gone into.
fy ourselves with the very interests that
[
own
THOUGHT
Take
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the situation, let us say, which
is
represented in the
who went
Hawaiian Islands and lived
experience of Father Damien, a Cathohc missionary
to the leper settlement on the
among them,
identified himself with them. It
least to the outside world, of a person
who
is
is
a picture, at
acting the part of
He
gave himself up to the case of those who had a
loathsome disease and shut himself up there practically for life.
In fact, eventually he died of the disease. This is a striking illustration of a sensational sort of the way in which duty may appear to a man as something which is utterly foreign to all his
inclinations. He is called upon to identify himself with that
from which he instinctively withdraws. Duty is that which is
outside of everything identified with the individual himself. In
the medieval period one of the ways of laying up treasure in
heaven was to wash the feet of a leper. That is the sort of
situation in which, seemingly, the duty is something which is
just a task, which is not a part of the individual self.
Take another picture; that of the scientist who is intensely
interested in the study of leprosy. He is interested in identifying
the microorganism responsible for it. He welcomes the opportunity to go and work, and to live among the lepers, to carry
out this task of his. He is dealing with a disease to be overcome.
He carries with him the modern weapons by means of which
this dread villain can be overcome, and he goes joyously to the
battle. It is not a task which is put upon him that is not himself. It is a task he has sought. He has asked for the opportunity to go out there and live among the lepers. It is true that
part of his panoply is defensive. He takes the proper aseptic
a martyr.
precautions against the disease; but, nevertheless, here
is
the
much more profound way than
The enthusiastic research man is com-
task of caring expressed in a
Father Damien could.
pletely absorbed in his duty, in the thing he has to do.
Put the two figures together, so to speak. First of all, here
is something that has been done that is not one's self, and yet
one can enthusiastically identify one's self with it. It is that experience which is at first something outside of one's self but
f
108I
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS FICHTE
which can become identified with one's self such an experience
as that which Father Damien seized upon, which accomplishes
the goal of the Romantic philosophy/It is the experience of
bringing the world within the range of the experience of
self-
consciousness, that experience in which the object of consciousness has the position of the self of which consciousness
is
the position in which both subject and object are one.
aware,
To
the
extent that this can be attained, the romanticist can put the
subject-object relationship in place of that of substance and
attribute?)
\This is the sort of situation that could be presented at the
time of Fichte because Germany, in its fight with Napoleonic
imperialism, was going through the throes of coming to national
The people
They were learning
self-consciousness.
conscious.
as a
whole were getting
self-
their history, the history of the
which they lived, learning it in terms of a
nation which was subject, which had lost sovereignty over itself, which was a vassal of Napoleon. They came to realize the
duty that the nation owed to herself to free herself from these
bonds. That duty had to come in terms of a national selfpolitical situation in
German.
the German people were calling them
consciousness, of seeing the situation in terms of being
And
Fichte's addresses to
become aware of themselves in this way. He presented it as
their duty to do so. Fichte had a very vivid sense of that mission which the German people have so definitely carried on.
And he called on them to have that sort of clear, objective consciousness which belongs to science, but to reach it through a
sense of national self-consciousness. How far those two can be
to
brought together
is
another question, but Fichte undertook to
arouse that national self-consciousness in terms of intelligence,
of scientific endeavor, as well as to arouse the people to a sense
of moral obligation:; There was, of course, even at this time,
more popular education in Germany than elsewhere in the
world and more satisfactory apparatus for bringing about popular training intelligence. Germany's political history had been
one in which she had been deprived of the national self-con[
109]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
had come much earlier to the French, the
Enghsh, and the Spanish. The Germans, having been deprived
of it, found this the time, at a somewhat belated period, for the
development of national self-consciousness. And they got it at
the moment of meeting the enemy, of throwing the enemy out
of their borders. It was at a proper time, then, that Fichte
sciousness which
presented this task of Romantic philosophy to the
people.
[no]
German
CHAPTER
VI
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
^ HAVE
been presenting the philosophical problem of Romantic idealism. It was^n attempt to state the world
-^
of knowledge, the world as known, in terms of a subject-
object relation as that appears in the experience of the
self.
The
statement that Fichte gave of this was that of the moralist.
The view we are about to consider, that of Schelling, was given
from the point of view of the artist. In each case the self is in
some sense responsible for its object. In each you can show the
And
self realizing itself in the not-self.
and the
not-self can be identified with the realization of the self
One can
in the not-self.
relationship.
That
identify that with the subject-object
the self as the subject
is,
the attitude for which
it is
foreign to the
formed. But
made
self.
when
a part of the
is
responsible,
something that
In each case
it is
for the
time being
a task that has to be per-
the task has been completed,
self.
it
first
of
all,
has been
In the moral situation, which Fichte
emphasized, this relationship of subject and object
which,
and
responsible appears definitely as the
not-self, as the objects It is
is
the relation of the self
is
one
in
the self realizes itself from the point of view
of a moral attitude, from the point of view of its obligations.
The subject-object relation, however, is one in which the task,
in
being accomplished, becomes essentially a part of the
That
self;
is,
self.
the duty one does identifies that experience with the
the self has
made
In the case of the
it its
artist,
own.
the attitude which Schelling
empha-
sized, the stress lies in the recognition that the self discovers its
ideas, its
meanings
in the world, in its object.
The
artist finds
himself in the object. In this he finds the meaning of the world;
and, of course, at the same time he finds his
[III]
own meaning. As
THOUGHT
an
artist
he
is
IN
creative.
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
He
constructs his objects, his world, and
yet that which he works on in this construction
But
it is
artist.
his
He
stands over against his material. It
meaning
is
is
the not-self.
his
own
is
that in which
own
Thus the ob-
to be found; he has to find his meaning, his
ideas, in the material with
ject
is
constructed in terms of the idea, of the meaning, of the
idea;
it is
which he has
his
own
to work.
construction. It
is
this atti-
tude which Schelling presented, with the constant insistence
is identical with the nature of the
that this meaning, this idea,
self.
we can get a background for Schelling's approach to
problem, we have to come back to another phase of the
Before
this
Kantian doctrine and the romantic development of it. Kant,
you remember, assumed that our knowledge, in so far as it is
reliable, belonged only to the field of experience. He assumed
that we can make certain judgments which are necessary
and universal, but only for experience, and that we can know
But, if,
nothing of that which lies outside of experience.
as he assumed, it is true, that there must be certain forms
of the mind into which our experience must enter, then we
can make certain judgments for all possible experiences. Just
because the forms are there which every experience must
take, we can say in advance that any experience whatsoever
will have these forms. So our necessary and universal judgments are judgments for experience only; they do not hold
for what lies beyond experience. In particular, they do not
hold for the noumenal world which we assume but of which
we can get no knowledge. Kant said that if we try to go
beyond the field of possible experience we are made aware
of that fact by falling into contradictions, antinomies. If we
transcend the
field
of possible experience,
we
find ourselves
caught at once in these traps, traps which seem to be there to
keep the unwary phenomenalist from treading upon noumenalistic ground.
For example, if one tries to get back to a cause which shall
be the cause of everything a first cause he finds that he
[111]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
When we extend our Hne of causation,
we always find an antecedent cause for
reaches contradictions.
as
we
do in experience,
every effect and we are always justified in assuming a prior
cause ad infinitum. That is as far as we choose to carry it.
Every event that appears in the field of experience is the result
some previous event or group of events. Well now, if we
say there must be some cause that is the cause of this experience but which lies outside of it, some primal cause, we force
of
by this same logic to set up some antecedent cause,
because we have brought the system within the field of causality. W^e set up a first cause, and yet we have to postulate anourselves
other cause as the cause of the
first
cause.
Thus we
find our-
one of Kant's antinomies.
Or, suppose we try to get behind our experiences to the
matter which is the ground of those experiences. As far as experience is concerned, we get hold of this matter and we crumselves entrapped
ble
it
in
in
our fingers, and then
we take
particles so small
we
can hardly see them and bring them under the microscope.
Finally,
we
get to the limit of ultra-microscopic vision and the
imagination comes into play, and
these particles, and
shall
be the
final
so on.
We
are
element. That
particles; at least, that
is
the
we imaginatively subdivide
moving toward a
is,
way we
the world
is
experience
it.
limit
which
made up
If
it is
of
any-
thing, it must be made up out of ultimate elements because
what we have in the universe as a whole is not a sum of nothings
but a sum of somethings. So, the
final
element that we reach
if we come to the final element by way
we can always continue the process of subindefinitely. To Kant, this shows the impossibihty of
must be something; but
of our crumblings,
division
getting
beyond the
field
of possible experience.
We can
imagine
ourselves getting at smaller and smaller units, continually sub-
dividing matter with which
tion of our experience
is
we
are dealing;
that things are
and yet the assump-
made up
of particles
that have some extension. Thus we find another antinomy
which results from the continued subdivision.
[113]
We move
toward
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the limit of the indivisibly small; and yet
particle so small but
And,
if
what
we undertake
it
to
could
move
still
in the
farthest Hmits of the stellar system,
we
we cannot imagine
be divided.
other direction to the
find nebulae which, ac-
cording to our present system of measurements, are millions of
light-years away.
And we
will
say that that represents the hori-
stellar world. But when we reach that boundary, we
more space beyond. There is not any limit there, and yet
our movement is always toward a limit. But the limits which
we tentatively set up can always be transcended. And so we
zon of our
find
reach another antinomy.
Then Kant
finds
still
another antinomy involved in moral
conduct, namely, that
all
cause and
we
effect, that
our conduct
is
explicable in terms of
express every one of our actions in
terms of the motives from which they spring, and yet we carry
a sense of responsibility for our conduct which implies that it
is
not caused by these preceding events but through the volition
So we have the impossibility, the antinomy, that
is due to the causal determination of our acts by preceding
events and at the same time the assurance of our own obligation, of the causal relation between ourselves and our acts.
Again, we assume that the world in which we are living is intelligible and ordered, and that this order which we find is due
to some plan or purpose. That assumption is deeply ingrained
and finds its expression in our views of nature. Since it is an
ordered affair, it must have been ordered by some intelligent
being. We set up the assumption of a deity, an intelligent
being, who is responsible for the world having the order, the
symmetry that it has. But when we try to come back to any
mind that itself has ordered such a world, we find that we have
put it outside of the very field of experience within which we
had located it. In order to understand such a being, we have
to locate it within the field of experience. But if we bring it
into this field, we have made God a part of experience and then
we must find a cause for God, since everything in experience
falls under the idea of causation.
of a free
self.
I114]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
^ Jiant's
general theory of these antinomies
is
that
we
are try-
ing to explain experience by getting outside of experience, and
is an attempt lying within the field
cannot be both inside and outside of experience at the same time. That attempt is, says Kant, the basis for
these antinomies. The moment we become involved in such a
yet every attempt to do that
of experience.
We
fundamental contradiction we can be sure that we are trying
know something that it is impossible for us to know, something that lies outside the limits of our possible knowledge.
When we reach such a point, we have to turn to faith rather
than to knowledge. And this faith, in Kant's sense, is the acceptance of the postulates of our conduict7\
We find ourselves acting, and inevitably our action does
present a transcendence of our immediate experience. The
latter stops at the moment in which it is taking place. The next
moment that is added to it does not lie in experience, and the
reasons for it do not He in experience. We have to get outside
of our experience in order to reach the moment into which we
are always entering. We are always putting our foot out into
a world which is as yet not experienced. Now what is the world
to
that continually
lies
just beyond, just over the threshold of
experience and knowledge?
The only
in regard to it is the postulate of
we can
thing that
set
up
our continually acting within
The human being cannot see ahead. He cannot see what is
going to happen. The only thing he can do is to look back and
then into the future. Then he can say something of what the
it.
future
to
is
know
going to be,
it
for, if it is
experience
that
as a part of the field of experience
is, if
he
it will
is
going
take on
own mind. But what the actual content of it is
be he can never tell. Our insurance companies try to
the forms of his
going to
make
a guess at it, and they can do it within sufficiently determinable hmits to put it on a business basis. Also, prudent
people can determine what, in general, their lives are going to
be. But our attitude toward the future is always of the statistical sort.
happened
That
is, it is
in the past
highly probable that things that have
like the rising
and setting of the sun, the
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
experience of colors, sounds, and so forth
We
future.
will
happen
in the
think these are probable future occurrences, but
we have no evidence of
When
it
outside of this statistical estimate.
things have happened,
analyze them; but what
we can
turn back on them and
going to happen
is something of
can
always
which we
never get hold. There is
some sort of
novelty about what happens in the most commonplace sort of
an experience and the most ordinary sort of an action, always
is
a tang of novelty about whatever takes place. That novelty is
something which cannot possibly be predicted. We can predict
something that is going to be strange and novel, but its very
strangeness indicates that there are some features about it which
depend upon its entering into experience before they can be
known. Even what can be predicted that you are going to
meet your friend at the station, that you are going to read a
book always carries with it something which is different from
what could possibly have been anticipated. Novelty is always
present. There is something in respect to the future in regard
to which we can only make postulates. We assume that it will
be of an ordered, intelligible sort; and yet with every breath we
are stepping into a world that has a novel element in it.
And that novelty, I should say, extends with regard not only
to what we call the future, it also extends to the past. We speak
of the past as irrevocable. What has happened has happened;
what has been spoken has been spoken. But when we come to
whose work it is to discover what actually was
spoken, what actually did happen, we find we get different accounts. This is particularly true when we look at what took
place in the past from the point of view of two succeeding genhistorians,
erations.
We
that
a part of the apparatus of each generation to recon-
it is
find that each generation has a different history,
struct its history.
different Caesar crosses the
Rubicon not
only with each author but with each generation. That
look back over the past,
it is
a different past.
The
is,
as
we
experience
something like that of a person climbing a mountain. As he
looks back over the terrain he has covered, it presents a conis
[ii6]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
So the past is continually changing
as we look at it from the point of view of different authors,
different generations. It is not simply the future which is novel,
then; the past also is novel. The world is continually changing
in ways in which we cannot predict. Of course, we may be able
to predict that it will change, but we cannot tell what sort of
world it is going to become. For example, it would have been
impossible, on the basis of the Newtonian theory, to have predicted the doctrine of Einstein. It would have been impossible,
on the basis of the old biologies, to have predicted the Darwinian hypothesis. No one could have predicted the Copernican
universe on the basis of the system set up by Ptolemy. The
world is continually blossoming out into a new universe, and in
this generation we have had fundamental conceptions brought
forward that entirely change the character of the physical universe. Take such experiences as those represented in the quantum theory, a theory in accordance with which reality has to be
regarded as both continuous and discontinuous. You are
brought up against something that in the nature of the case you
cannot predict. But we go right on without any disturbance
from that front. We are pleased to have these revolutions take
place in our theories, gratified to have our universe fall down
so that it is replaced by a new one. We erect institutions called
universities and invite research professors at high salaries who
wreck our universities and substitute others in their place. And
it appears to us to be perfectly right and natural.
It seems as if the world which lies beyond our actual experience will continue to be just the sort of ordered world we
live in, and we hope a better one. These are the postulates of
our conduct. We are always postulating something about what
is going to happen, something which determines our own conduct. That is the attitude which Kant says we have to take in
regard to the world of reality. We cannot know things as they
are in themselves. The moment we reach the edge of our own
knowledge, we find ourselves caught in an antinomy. But if we
go ahead as we should go ahead, as, indeed, we must go ahead,
tinually different picture.
[117I
THOUGHT
and act on the
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
basis of the assumption that the universe
to continue to be rational
and that we have our part
is
going
to play in
by being moral individuals, then we should take these postuwhich we make, but which we cannot prove, and make
them the basis of our action. This is, of course, the principle of
it
lates
Kant's Critique of Practical Reason.
(^ow, Kant
said there are certain postulates that go with this
assumption of our moral conduct. The
two
have indiand we
have to accept responsibility for our acts. Second, the world has
a rational character that transcends our experience. As I have
said, we take the world and set it in that rational order; and yet
we expect that someone in_ this generation or the next will set
That is, there is some sort of
it in an entirely different way(
an order that transcends any statement that we can make of
our experience, that goes beyond it. We find ourselves in an
ordered world, a world which requires an ordering inteUigence.
These two postulates come from our conduct: our freedom of
will, together with our moral responsibility, and the intelligent
God that directs the world in accordance with reason, knowledge. When we take this point of view, we always find that
the new world becomes rational. It is irrational from the point
of view from which we have taken it, outside of the field of
experience, but it is more rational than the other.
cated already. First,
we
first
are responsible, moral beings
Kan t's third postulate is rather curious. He said that, since
we are rational beings, our conduct must always be rational^
You remember the form which he gives to his categorical rrfiperative: So act that you can make a universal law out of the
maxim of your act. This categorical imperative is practically
the only one that Kant can set up, but there are some others
that can be drawn from it. The test in question is, you see, that
we should make our conduct perfectly universal. If we are to
make it universal, it must not depend upon our inclinations. We
must not act for our own interest or for our own pleasure. We
must not act for our own immediate, particular ends, for our
I
conduct must always be universal and the motive
[118I
for it
must
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
be respect for law. Universality
But our
morality.
they are very particular
sal;
is
the very core of Kant's
inclinations, unfortunately, are not univeraffairs.
We may
say to ourselves
when we are hungry we should eat; but Kant's reason for
must be that it is good hygiene, not because we particularly
want a beefsteak at the moment, not in order to get rid of a
gnawing sensation, not for the sake of pleasure or for the avoidance of pain, but because it is our duty to eat. This is the only
that
it
reasQji
why we should
we seem
rWell, here
ever act on anything.
to
have two
parallel lines.
One must
al-
ways~act with reference to a universal, while one's inclinations
are always with reference to some particular. But, says Kant,
what we look forward to is moral perfection; and that can be
achieved only in situations in which the individual's own nature
what his conscience tells him he ought to seek. Our nature
is made up of inclinations for particular things, and our conscience tells us always to act in a universal fashion and from
respect for law. Now how and where are we going to bring these
parallel lines together? Only in infinity. Therefore our conduct
seeks
we have an eternity within which to
The very break in our nature between
requires the postulate that
reach that perfection.
the particularity of our inclinations and the universality of our
conscience, of our reason, seemingly presents to us an immortality of the self, of the soul, because only in eternity
can
we
pos-
two such divergent tendencies as an inclination for particular satisfactions and a conscience that demands that we should act only from respect for law. These
sibly bring together
postulates, then, lead to freedom of the will, the existence of
God, and the immortality of the soul. But you see Kant's philosophy reaches these not by deduction but by postulation.
He
says these postulates are involved in intelligent conduct.
Thus,
it is
edge. If
we can get beyond experibeyond it, but this is not by knowlreach this end through knowledge, we find
only by postulation that
ence. In this
we
way we can
try to
get
ourselves involved in an antinomy.--
The
contradiction that Fichte set up
[119]
was that of the opposi-
THOUGHT
tion of
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
duty to inclination, the very opposition which Kant
made the ground for his doctrine of immortality. The thing that
we have to do, that we ought to do, is the thing that we do
not want to do. It involves an effort. From the point of view
of Kant we can never be sure that we are moral unless, as
others pointed out, we are doing something we do not want to
do. The moment you do something you want to do, you had
better look out. The chances are you are being immoral. Esseems to lie between what you have to
do and what you ought to do at times of great stress, at strenusentially, the opposition
ous moments in
That is the characteristic of our duty. Not
that everything we do not want to do we ought to do, but that
what we ought to do is something that we do not want to do.
We have to overcome the obstacle before us if we are to accomplish what we ought to accomplish. But, says Fichte, when
we have done that, it becomes a part of our own nature. We
have attained the knowledge we ought to attain. We have the
life.
we have forced ourselves to get;
we have made it a part of ourselves, it is what we really
want. That is, it is when we look back at it. That is the dialectical process by means of which the self is constantly creating
education, the training, that
and,
if
the world. There is a contradiction between what one wants
and what one ought; but if the contradiction is overcome, then
the individual advances to a
new
world.
Thus, the antinomy took on another character in the Romantic philosophy than that which it had for Kant, just as his
noumenal world took on a new character. Kant said we have
to postulate the self as noumenal, and the romanticists said
that that
The
is
exactly
what we
are.
We
are at the center of real-
element of the universe. The/frm-te
self is one phase of the Absolute Self, of God himselft(_Xhe
antinomies which Kant set up as indications that we are going
beyond the range of possible knowledge become, for the romanticist, the very process of creation. The antinomy in knowlity.
self is the creative
edge, instead of being the indication that
something that we cannot know,
[
is
120]
we
are trying to
the very process
know
by means of
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
which knowledge
The antinomy
itself arises.
is
a stage in the
process of knowledge.
This process
is
called after the
"the
term which was used
Of
in the
what "the
dialectic" means is a process of discussion, conversation in which
the ancient Sophist sought to entrap his opponent in a contradiction. That was the "outdoor sport" of the Athenian, discussing some question with the first person he met, and trying
to catch him in a contradiction in his statement. And the
old Greek speculation
who
Sophists were those
dialectic."
could play the
course,
game
to the best ad-
vantage. Socrates was the supreme Sophist because he could
catch the professional Sophists at their
own
Socrates the process was not simply a game;
it
getting back to certain fundamental realities.
would ask a man what
little
is; and when the man undertook
would point out contradictions in his
justice
to define "justice," he
statements. This
game
sections of Plato's Republic.
tice"
is
is
presented to us in the opening
The
man what
rendering to a
tricks. But for
was a means for
For example, he
absolute definition of "jus-
belongs to him.
This
is
a good
workaday conception. Socrates then asks, "Well, suppose somebody had given you his sword. It would be justice to give it
back? Certainly. But, suppose the person had developed a
suicidal mania and was intent on killing himself, would it then
be just to return the sword?" And his opponent has to admit
that it would not be just under that condition. In other words,
his definition breaks down. And so on. What Socrates undertook to show was that,
you are criticizing definitions of "justice," you must be criticizing them from some standpoint.
There must be such a thing as justice; otherwise you could not
criticize definitions
of
if
it.
You may
not be able to define this
you have some idea of a perfect justice
which is the basis for your very criticism. That is what Socrates
undertook to show was the case. He tried to show that there
must be "ideas" in the Greek sense of these moral perfections
or we would not be able to point to them as being such. The
very conflicts involved in these definitions indicate some perthing, but evidently
[121]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
feet definition. And then Socrates, in ironical fashion, said that
he did not know what this perfect justice was, but that evidently the person he was talking with knew, because he was criticizing every definition brought up. Thus, in asking the person for
the basis for his criticism, he caught the Sophist at his own
game.
What
want to point out is that here we have the dialectic
as a means of advancing from contradictions to a truth. That
is what the old process was, at least as Socrates worked it. The
Sophist used it continually. He undertook to tear it down by
means of the contradiction that he introduced. For example,
what is the reason for obeying laws.^ They are nothing but enactments of the people in power. If one man becomes dominant,
he
will
make
make
laws to suit himself. If the majority of the people
the laws, they
make them
in the interest
to the disadvantage of the minority.
advantage of those
in
power, then
The laws
of the majority,
are always to the
why obey them? To
avoid a
no such thing, then, as justice as
such. That is the way the Sophist proceeded. Socrates took
their method but utilized the contradictions as a means of reachpenalty, of course. There
is
ing the truth.
/As Kant
left
the antinomies, they were simply the indications
knowledge beyond the field of
experience. Wherever it did that, it got caught in an antinomy.
What the romanticist endeavors to show is that these antinomies
are really steps by which we are going beyond experience. Of
course, we do go beyond experience very day, every minute.
We go into the past; and, as we look at the past from the point
of view of the present minute, it is a different past from that
which we viewed from the standpoint of the previous minute.
The world is continually developing, says the Romantic idealist, by a process which he calls a "dialectic," a process which
involves these contradictions, but a process which overcomes
of the mind's attempts to push
them
its
in a continual synthesis?^'
Let us take, then, the steps^hich led from Fichte to Schelling
and Flegel. Is there a phase of self-consciousness which can be
[122]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
responsible for the world as an object? This
is
the question
which all the romanticists asked. The answer that Fichte gives
is found in the moral nature in so far as the world is the scene
of the duty of man. But the world is there before man; it is
prior to his duty. The moral aspect may be the most important
aspect of it after man appears. One may even conceive of it as
being the purpose for which the world exists. But you have to
presume the existence of the world before the moral self appears. Can the romantic attitude present the world as an object
which appears to us when we are not in the moral attitude? Can
the world be presented as an object for other than the mo
phases of our nature? That is, can you find that it has the same
many faceted existence that we have? This is the question that
the romanticists asked when it was found that the answer that
Fichte gave was inadequate.
The
first
He
ling.
answer to
this further question
takes the point of view of the
The
of the moralist.
was given by Schel-
artist rather
than that
artist discovers himself in his ideas, in
the material with which he works. For the function of the
artist
or rather,
should say, the process of the artist
not
is
simply that of taking dead material and fashj.oning his idea in
He
it.
form
discovers the idea in the material itself]
in the clay
which he
that he finds out
molding, and
what the form
have worked that out
terial,
is
in
is
in his
it is
He
finds the
only as he molds
own mind. He may
imagination before coming to the ma-
before getting his hands on the clay; but, as a rule,
it is
the process of working with the material that brings to the
artist's
mind what
it is
he
is
trying to present. [The artistic pro-
cedure, the experience of the artist,
is
a discovery of his
own
ideas.
What
was
Fichte was not able to do with the moral conception
known.
to present the world as
He
could present
it
as a
terms of knowledge, his statement was inadequate.1 He was faced with the
problem of finding the content of knowledge, or the object of
field
of duty; but when he
knowledge
tried to state that in
in the object of duty, starting
[
123]
with the Kantian
as-
THOUGHT
sumption that the
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
self is causal in its
conduct and that
it
be-
longs, in that sense, to the world of things-in-themselves.
He
found the essence of duty to
lie in
the presentation of the task
or obstacle that had to be overcome, and he identified this not
only with the moral act but also with the process of
consciousness, of being conscious of one's
self.
self-
In this process
self. But what has this to
do with the problem of knowledge.^ yTs^the object of knowledge
something that presents itself as a task, as an obstacle? On the
face of it, this does not seem to be the case. Our objects of
knowledge are about us; they are there as the world in which
we live, move, and have our being. As such, they are not there
seemingly as obstacles. There are, of course, tasks to be undertaken, duties to be done in which we have to recognize the
nature of things; and some of our tasks, including that of gaining knowledge, are severe and difficult undertakings. But is
knowledge, as such, of the nature of a duty that has to be done,
of a task that has to be accomplished? That does not seem to be
lay the possibility of realizing one's
the nature of
it.
Schelling recognized this and so he approaches the general
problem from another angle. For him the world, as over against
the Absolute, was that in which the artist found his idea,
realized himself.
He
took the artistic attitude, that of
ing to Schelling, the point of departure
artist,
the attitude of the
that experience in which the artist discovers himself,
discovers his
ing.
is
artistic
Accord-
intuition, as Fichte has taken the moralist's attitude.
The
own
idea in the materials with which he
artist gives
himself to nature and finds in
ideas which he himself
is
it
is
work-
the very
trying to bring to consciousness.
He
turns to the society about him; he finds in social relations and
which he
in the history of the past those ideas
press.
So Schelling conceived of the
x'^bsolute
is
.
seeking to exelf
turning to
nature or finding iruciature an objective expression, an external
expression of the self^
What
Fichte insisted upon was that this world as
identical with the self that knows.
[
124]
And
known
is
he carried out some
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS SCHELLING
very subtle and profound analyses to establish his point. Of
course, some of this work had been done in the empirical analy-
They had discovered in the ideas of
philosophy of sensations and ideas, the very stuff
of the English school.
sis
Locke,
in his
of the world. For them, however, the self was a mere organization of such experiences.
To some
of them the self was a mere
bundle of impressions, particularly those centering about the
body and about our social relations. Certain groups of these
impressions and ideas which remained relatively permanent be-
came the self in experience.
But the Romantic philosophy pointed out that
it
the
with
arises in the social experience, also carried
self,
it
while
the very
unity that makes society possible, which makes the world possible. At least from their point of view, it is impossible to reduce the self to the world, for the very unity of the world comes
from the self. It is our thinking, our perception of the world,
that gives it its unity. In our experience there is great diversity
and multiplicity of sensations and experiences, but in our cog-
nition these are
organized.
all
That organization, according
to
the Romantic idealists, taking their cue from Kant, comes from
the
self.
It is the self which organizes this world;
organized
itself, it
of
it, it
has really organized that which
has organized
its
nature, discovered
its
Here, as
have
we
will say,
color, of form, of
The
it is
in
back to the
artist's ex-
himself before a land-
and in this he finds all the multiplicity of
moving and stationary objects, and these
The whole
thing gets balance.
become arranged with
mind of the artist that has
different parts of the landscape
But
it is
the
into this whole.
He
has discovered in
reference to each other.
organized
it
and organization which belong to himself.
in it the sensations
which are
his
own.
only the landscape but himself as well.
his
has
another phase.
artist finds
take on a certain definite shape.
The
it
identical with
experiences. It has, in one phase
said, Schelling turns
perience for his analogy.
scape,
own
what
but when
is
own
He
that unity
He has discovered not
What he has hold of is
experience, the expression of himself.
[125]
it
has discovered
THOUGHT
Now,
it is
upon
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
grasps
it,
we grasp in our
our intuition, with the self that
this identity of the object, that
process of knowledge, that
is,
in
that Schelling laid his whole stress. It
is
there to start
with, but the process of knowledge identifies the content with
His position went under the name of Identit'dtsphilosoand his whole undertaking
was that of showing the identity of the object of knowledge with
the self that knows. Nature, for Fichte, was the process of the
the
self.
phie, "the philosophy of identity";
self
coming to consciousness of
relation
is
itself.
The same
subject-object
present in Schelling's philosophy, but for Fichte's
moral statement he substitutes the analogy of the process of the
artist. The assertion of identity on the part of Schelling came
back to the reality of the artist's intuition, his seeing nature
through his own idea, through that which gives the unity and
meaning
to
it.
126
CHAPTER
VII
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERSHEGEL
HFN HIS
Hegel
insisted that SchelHng had left out of his philosophy an acI
-^ count of the process by means of which this identification
of the self with its object takes place; he left out of his philosophy a statement of the process by means of which the identicriticism of this use of the artist's intuition,
fication of the self
and the object could be
criticism of ScheUing's philosophy
is
that
effected. Hegel's
is
it
a bare asser-
tion of identity instead of being an actual presentation of the
process by
means of which the
self
and the object can be
identi-
fiedj/
You
is
will
remember that
mentioned earher that romanticism
was the background
a philosophy of evolution, of process. It
development of the theory of evolution. Back of this
latter conception lies the assumption of a living process which
takes on successively different forms. The assumption of all
evolutionary thought is that life, as a physiological process, is
the same whether in a complex or in a simple form, in plant or
for the
And
in animal. It is a single living process as such.
takes on a multitude of different forms. This
for ScheUing's
is
this process
the background
philosophy of identity; the Hving form persists
and is identical, although it appears in different forms.
But what Schelling did was to assert this identity of the
process and its expression of the self and its object without
working out the detail of it. In another field Lamarck and,
with even more success, Darwin presented a picture in terms
of which the detail of the process could be worked out. Darwin
showed a life-process appearing in different forms; and he
showed these
this
differences as expressing the life-process
environment,
now
in that.
[
Then he was
127]
able to
now
in
show how,
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
through variations, a new form might conceivably arise which
would be better fitted to meet the exigencies of a new environment. Take such a situation as that which appeared during the
glacial epoch, when a great ice sheet came down over Europe
and America. It brought with it a different climate, different
hving conditions; and the forms that survived had to change
their characters. The woolly elephant, the hairy hippopotamus
forms of the sort of which we find the remains were adjustments to a new environment. In that gradually changing cHmate, those forms survived which were able to grow such coats
of hair as would enable them to withstand the cold. For some
reason forms that could live on certain foods survived over
Forms which belonged to marshy areas
swamps dried out, and those forms which could
those that could not.
gave way as the
migrate over greater distances took the place of those which
could not. Such a picture is presented by Professor Marsh in
his statement of the development of the horse here in America
from a five-toed animal which gradually gave way to one with
a single toe in the form of a hard hoof which enabled it to travel
farther so that it could live on more sparsely scattered grass,
and thus had a decided advantage over other forms. Back of all
these pictures lies the assumption of a life-process going on in
different environments in which it takes on first one form and
then another, wherein it has to become a different object in its
relationship to the world within which it lives. The world and
the form have, then, an identical content. The adjustment of
the one to the other gives rise to the appearance of the different
forms.
What Hegel
upon was that here is a process going
and that this process must exhibit the differences which we find in the world as we know it.
We cannot simply come back to the assertion that the world
is identical with the self that knows it.
We must be able to
show in the process of knowledge itself the identity which is
known to exist between the subject and its object, between the
form and the world in which it has to live. Hegel, then, lays
insisted
on, a subject-object process,
128
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
upon the
and Schelling.
He takes over, so to speak, the antinomies of Kant, those seeming contradictions into which thought was plunged when it
tried to transcend the phenomenal world and get over to the
standpoint of things-in-themselves. The antinomies from the
point of view of these Romantic philosophers were not simply a
warning that the mind had gotten beyond the limits of its
knowledge; they were the actual process by means oL^which
greater stress
dialectic than did Fichte
the object itself arose in the subject-object process. /That
is,
the fundamental contradiction, or antinomy, for this school was
that of the subject and object; and they were looking for the
process by
means of which they could pass over from the one
and achieve a larger self than that with which they
to the other
started as a result.
Fichte had attempted to solve the contradiction by reference
self, by pointing out
what is involved in doing one's duty. ScheUing attempted the
same thing through reference to the intuition of the artist.
What Hegel undertook to do was to show how this opposition
between subject and object could be overcome, in some sense,
by means of the recognition of the nature of the process of
thought itself. In biological evolution we overcome the opposition between the identity of the life-process in all forms and the
diversity of the living forms themselves by studying the process
to the nature of the experience of the moral
We
examine unicellular forms floating on
the surface of the sea; we find other bits like these become
colony forms living on the bottoms and in shallow water holes.
Out of these have arisen bilateral forms which move toward
their food with bilateral symmetry. We see how these have
come out of the water to live on land; how plants and animals
as
taking place7\
it is
adjust themselves, especially in regard to their chemical needs,
one another, taking on successively different forms during the
[Now, Hegel attempted to set up a picture similar to
this as it applied to the thought processes, to the process of
knowing, and possibly of all sensing, perceiving, and thinking.
He set out to follow this through as an identical process having
to
process.
129]
THOUGHT
IN
different expressions.
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
In this process
we have another
instance
of the contradiction between subject and object, but at the same
time
As
we
see an identity of the
t wo.\
statement in his
Phdnomenologie des Geistes^ which is one of his earliest philosophical works, in which he said that under the simplest situations a person simply identifies something as here. There is a
house here, and there is a tree over there. That is the only
thing one can say: "Here is the house; there is the tree."
But, if one shifts his position, he finds himself saying, "The
tree is here and the house is there." The only statement that
one can make under the new condition leads to the contradiction of the statement made before. One says the time now
is such and such o'clock, and writes this down as 10:30 o'clock.
Later one looks at the clock and finds that it is not 10:30 but
3:30, and the assertion made about the time now contradicts
itself. Evidently, in our perception the here and the now are
determined by the position of the observer. What was here is
illustrative of this fact, take Hegel's
there, and what was there is here. What was now is then, and
what was then is now. This shift depends simply upon the
location of the self. You have a process in which you have to
distinguish between yourself which is here and the object which
is there. But you cannot maintain that position, that distinction, because you shift your own position. It is only in so far
as you get back to the fundamental process of your experience
that you can get some sort of an expression of the identity of
these opposing positions. You have to bring back all these experiences, the experiences of this point and of that, of this
moment and of that, to a self-process which is continually going
on, taking on
now
we made
We
before in the previous situation.
selves at this
fore.
now that. When we pass from one
we are denying any statements that
this form,
situation over into another,
moment
in
opposition to ourselves of a
But we overcome the opposition of
that there
is
throughout.
are putting our-
moment
be-
an identical subject-object relation
by realizing
which persists
The
in
stuff of the process
[130]
is
this fact
the
same
both cases;
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
but now
it
takes on this form,
lutionists find this
now
that, just as biological evo-
animal a living form and
this
other animal
another living form. They are diverse, and yet each exhibits
the
same
living process.
Hegel took the identity revealed in the subject-object relationship and sought to show that this identity persists in all the
different forms of thought. This always brings him back to a
contradiction. But what he shows is that this contradiction, instead of leading to a simple destruction of thought itself, leads
to a higher level on which the opposing phases are overcome.
That is, in the total process he discovers what he calls a "thesis,"
an "antithesis," and a "synthesis." In other words, he adds a
third, a unifying, step to Kant's twofold antinomies. The most
abstract expression of this is that which Hegel presents with
respect to the very bare idea of Being itself. There can be no
more abstract conception than that of Being. We cannot say
that it has any sort of being. We cannot describe it. It has no
particular quality or quantity. We can say nothing of it but
that it is. We have to empty out everything that could be put
into Being in order that we may get back to just Being itself.
But that, said Hegel, is not a definition of Being, but one of NotBeing. If you have given up every possible qualification which
you can give to the idea of Being, you simply have a statement
of Not-Being. The very idea of Being, taking simply the bare
idea, brings with it the conception of Not-Being, of Nothing.
Being and Nothing are identical, and yet in sharp contradiction
to each other.
But this opposition does not, from the Hegelian standpoint,
lead simply to the destruction of these ideas. Being and NotBeing are simply the two phases of Becoming. What becomes
is Being, but what was before the Becoming is Not-Being. As I
say, then, if you try to define Being from the Hegelian point of
view, you find a situation which is practically a description of
Not-Being and seems to contradict and destroy Being itself.
But,
if
you can get hold of these as moments in a process instead
them as the same, you find that you have a con-
of thinking of
[131]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
what was previously a pure contradiction. In and of themselves, Being and Not-Being are contradictory; taken as moments in a process, they represent Becoming. Here we get a synthesis. It is in this process of bringing together subject and object that Hegel finds contradictions,
but finds them as phases which lead to a synthesis or a higher
ception which harmonizes with
expression of the
self.
Hegel undertakes to carry out in detail the process by means
of which the object appears both as the construction of the self
and also as the not-self. He undertakes to carry this out in detail, and he calls it "logic." If we want to get an illustrative
instance of this point of view of Hegel's, we can find it in the
attitude of the research scientist. As I shall point out, Hegel
does not do entire justice to this position; but still, it is the position which he is trying to present.
Let us take, for example, the discovery of the typhoid-fever
germ. Before it was isolated, typhoid fever was known simply
as a contagious disease. That is, it was spread through contact.
A person who had the disease carried it to someone who did not
have it. That was the theory of it. It was not known just what
the nature of this contagion was, but it was assumed that where
the disease spread there had always been contact between the
person who had the disease and the person who became infected.
Now let us suppose that a sporadic case of fever appears, that
is, a case in which there has been no contact. No one else in the
community has it, and this individual is a person who lives in
the community, has not come in from the outside. He has had
no contact with an infected person, and yet he comes down with
typhoid fever. There you have, we will say, a contradiction between the actual experience of the physician or the health officer
and the theory which is current with regard to the spread of
typhoid fever.
There is a conflict there. The scientist under such circumstances sets out to find out what the meaning of this contradiction is. He gathers other instances, in so far as he can find them.
He finds sporadic cases not only in his own community but else[
132]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
where. As other cases come up, he plots them on a map. He
puts a pin on the map at the location of every house in which
the disease appears. Then, let us say, he finds these pins all
run along the line of a water course, or a milk route, or along
the paths of persons who go to a certain market. That suggests
to him that there is some sort of cause for the disease which is
not necessarily given by contact but may be carried in the
water, the milk, or the food from the market. And we assume
that investigation is carried on until the microorganism which is
the carrier of the disease, the cause of
it,
is
finally identified.
That is, the research scientist starts from a conflict, a contradiction. The contradiction in this case is that between the accepted
theory in regard to the transfer of a contagious disease and the
facts of the disease as
it
appears. There
is
a contagious disease,
and yet no contact. This involves a conflict, for
with a disease which
You
see, the
is
we
are dealing
both contagious and not contagious.
is one in which he goes
procedure of the scientist
from what we may call the thesis and the antithesis to a synthesis in which both the others are taken up. It may be true
that the disease is directly conveyed from one person to another.
The microorganism may be transmitted
sense that
may
directly.
It
is
also
may
be considered contagious in the
by
the organism through a stream
be conveyed
possible that the disease
is, by means of a carrier where
no direct contact is made between the person who has the disease and the person who becomes infected. The conception of
the microorganism is, you see, one which synthesizes these occurrences of typhoid fever so that the conflict which we first
come to is overcome. In the former instance the appearance of
a sporadic case was in direct conflict with the theory of contagious disease. If, now, we assume or can prove that the disease is conveyed by a microorganism, we can bring out and explain all the cases that have been explained by contact and also
of water or through milk, that
seemed to be in conflict with the
constructed which takes up the opposing
and unifies them.
the thesis and the antithesis
the sporadic cases that have
theory.
situations
synthesis
is
^33]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
The
abstract statement of this
The
definition, the thesis, in the case of contagious diseases
have given above
in the first movement of the HegeHan logic. In this Hegel attempted to present Being, showing that the definition which he
gave of it also, and inevitably, presented the definition of NotBeing. Being and Not-Being seem to be in conflict with each
other. Yet, if you take bare Being by itself, you give it no
content; and what you have defined as Being is also Not-Being.
But the conception of Becoming is definitely one in which both
Being and Not-Being appear. That which arises, which has
arisen, is Not-Being as over against that which exists, which is
Being. Thus a synthesis of the two opposites is established.
This is a highly abstract statement of the type of problem
which I have just given.
is
the one
is
one which does not take into account the sporadic case. If you
try to bring the latter into the statement, you have a carrying of
disease without contact. In other words, you find yourself in a
contradiction. Well, now, the passage from one of these to the
other through the conception of the microorganism enables you
to state both the contact experience, where the disease is actually transferred from the one who has it to another who has not,
and also the sporadic case, in which no direct contact between
persons is made. The difference between Hegel's abstract statement and the illustration I have used is that Hegel assumes that
the statement which is made of Being carries with it the opposing statement of Not-Being. That is, he assumes that his universal will always have in it the opposite of itself. The opposition which is found in the case of the illustration I have used is
not between two universals; it is not between the theory of conis, the carrying of the disease by actual contact,
and the very opposite of that. That is not the conflict. It lies
rather between the theory of contagion and the actual incident
tagion, that
in experience, the sporadic case.
That
is,
the conflict
lies
be-
tween the universal and an exception to that universal. That
where the problems in science always arise. They do not arise
between the theory expressed in a law, for example, and the very
is
[134]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
opposite of that law.
the law and
The
conflict arises
between the theory of
some particular observation, some particular
called "fact" which
is
in conflict
with that law.
so-
It is a conflict,
then, not between universals but between the universal and the
we put it into the terminology of logic, it is a conbetween a universal affirmative and a particular negative
proposition. The sporadic case is an instance of getting a disease without contact, but you do not set up a universal proposition which says that no cases of disease are conveyed by contact.
What you show is that, while there may be some cases in which
it is conveyed by contact, there are at least some in which it is
not. The scientific problem appears, then, in the form of an
exception to an accepted law. And the conflict which the scientist, the research man, undertakes to solve is that between the
exception and the law not that between one law and another,
OQ-universal and another.
\ The general criticism of this point is, as I have already indicated, that Hegel assumed that our development, including the
development of science, takes place through the conflict of universals, of ideas with each other. Actually, it takes place
through the conflict of universals, or laws, and some particular
particular. If
flict
some exception.
event,
we make this reservation
we may still say that Hegel
If
to the Hegelian doctrine,
in the
in
regard
is
correct
assumption that the development of our knowledge takes
place through conflict. It takes place through the appearance
of problems and the solution of these problems.
thesis
and an
Reflection
is
antithesis,
a process of solving problems.
"reflective intelligence"
tion to
and then you advance
brought out
is
what we have been
in
You have
to a synthesis.
What we
call
our
regard to some excep-
in the habit of believing.
We put
all
our views, our ideas, our methods of conduct, into universal
form.
We
recognize that these universals are likely to be sub-
ject to exceptions, but
We
we
are in the habit of acting in that way.
expect things to happen in a universal fashion. But
when
an exception arises to that, then we are presented with a problem; we have something which we have to think out reflec-
THOUGHT
And
tively.
pothesis.
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
that thinking involves the presentation of a hy-
Themustration which we used before made use of the conception of a microorganism in water, milk, or food stuffs. These can
be ingested by a person together with the organism and so convey the disease. Another highly interesting, sensational illustration of this situation
disease
is
is
the case of yellow fever. In this case the
conveyed from one person
to another through the in-
The person having the disease
takes the organism into his own body, and there this microorganism runs a certain portion of its Hfe-cycle. Then it is conveyed to some other victim at a later stage. The assumption
termediation of the mosquito.
was that yellow fever was a filth disease. That is, if you clean up
a district, you can keep it free from yellow fever. Senator Wood
went to Havana and cleaned up the city. He cleaned up the
houses, the streets, the sewers everything. But yellow fever
continued. It was already known that the mosquito was a carrier of malarial fever. Therefore, the hypothesis was presented
that this might be true of yellow fever, and it was tested out and
found to be the case.
The Hegelian synthesis, in these cases, is the hypothesis
which will reconstruct the older theory, harmonize it with the
facts.
The hypothesis
He
does not spin
his
web.
He
it,
is
a construct in the
mind of the
scientist.
so to speak, out of himself, as a spider spins
takes facts that are there, meanings that are as-
some suggestion that will give him
new hypotheses, new ways of looking at the situation in question, in such a fashion that it will take up both the facts belonging to the older law and these new exceptions. Out of these two
the new hypothesis is made. In this sense, then, Hegel is correct in his assumption that our knowledge grows through the
giving of problems problems which arise out of contradictions
in our knowledge. But, as I have said, he was not correct in
sured; and then he finds
assuming that this conflict is one between universals. It is not
that. It comes when there is an exception that conflicts with
a law and leads to the appearance in the mind of the scientist
[136]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
And the hyout of the mind of the thinker, the scientist.
It is a creation of the self. And when it has been created, it
carries with it a new world.
Thus the world has been rebuilt over and over again. Since
of a hypothesis which will solve his problem.
pothesis does arise
new conceptions of
the period of the Renaissance entirely
matter and of motion have come to take the places of the older
conceptions given in the Aristotelian doctrine. We have
changed the world from a Ptolemaic to a Copernican one. The
sphere of the heavens has changed from a most limited universe
an indefinitely great universe. During the last half-century
we have been busy at the task of reconstructing the universe
all the way down in terms of space and time. We are continually reconstructing the world. That reconstruction is something
to
that comes out of men's minds, out of their heads. It comes
from the process of thinking. It involves the thought of Copernicus, of Kepler, of
Newton, of Einstein,
views of the world, these new worlds.
process of advance consists in thinking out
that will solve a given problem.
thought out,
it
When
sit
back
take the place of the old.
can create a
the facts of experience; and,
it
sun does not
if it
becomes the world
move about
do not mean that
new
and then he can take that idea out and see
experience,
some hypothesis
in his chair to create a
He
as
the earth,
others.
hypothesis has been
this
has to be tested, of course.
the scientist can
new
We did not stumble upon
men were not simply more open-eyed than
them. These
The
to give us these
if it
new world
to
idea of the world,
corresponds with
does agree with the facts of
we
we
live
it.
When we
say the
accept this contradiction
of the senses because of the thinking of such
men
as Pythagoras,
They had to think things out before
world which revolves on its own axis could take its place
Aristarchus, Copernicus.
the
in
our experience as a great sphere in heaven revolving about
the sun.
Which
it is,
the one or the other, depends upon the
actual thinking of scientists.
of theirs and bring
it
Then they
take this thought
into the field of experience
[
137]
and
see if
it
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
agrees with the facts.
But the idea
is
theirs, their creation, the
product of their creative intelHgence.
( All this is what Hegel really comes back to. The world of our
ex^rience is a world which we are continually creating in our
thought. The astonishing thing is that such rapid reconstructions have taken place in recent times, such rapid reconstructions of fundamental ideas, such as those of matter and motio
These changes go on without our being disturbed about thexru
We naturally think of matter simply as subdivided stuff
such as we can get between our thumb and finger. We break
it up as far as we can under the microscope and with the
we always come out with something that we
might get between our thumb and fingers if they were only
small enough. But now we have come to conceive of matter
in terms of energy. Mass itself has to be stated in terms of
imagination, but
electromagnetism.
We
conceive of motion as that which goes
on with certain velocities. Motion has been recognized for some
time as relative; but now we find that motion itself varies in
terms of distance covered and time passed in reference to the
observer, and it also depends upon whether or not the observer
is himself moving. The very distance covered is greater in one
consentient state than in another. Such fundamental contradictions as that go into the very structure of the most primordial
things in the world. This reconstruction is going on all the
time. We expect it. We build our science on the theory of research. We assume that the world we know today will not be the
world of our grandchildren. If it is, our descendants will have
been poor scientists; if they cannot prove that we are wrong,
they will be poor progeny. The business of science is to continually reconstruct its world. Science is a research procedure. Research does grow out of problems. Problems are exceptions to
laws, rules
exceptions
to the theory of the universe that
we
have accepted in the past. And the solution of these problems
and the new worlds that come with them have to come out of
the minds of men.
f
Tn the philosophy of Hegel the development of mind is the
^'"~-
[138]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
development of the world. Fundamentally, it
is the position of absolute idealism that this relation between
the mind and nature constitutes things, that all relations, as
same thing
as the
such, are essentially aspects of that relation. It
relates
things.
This
is
is
thinking that
a statement of absolute idealism, of
course, because the world ultimately goes back to the Absolute
which constructs and continually maintains the world
through a process of thinkTngTti That is the metaphysical printhe woria is the expression of the thought
ciple of this idealism
Self
of^he Absolute.
/^s_an object, then, the world answers to the subject, which is
self. And the relationship between the object and the sub-
the
ject, as it
appears in these relations,
the object; and this
ess, so
is
is
just that of the subject to
a process. Just as thought itself
the world to the Absolute
going on; and that process
is
is
the
is
a proc-
essentially a process that
mind
of the Absolute.
process that constitutes things, and the process
is
is
It is a
one with the
Absolute SeTfry
The romantic phase of this idealism, as we have seen, places
emphasis upon the self, and especially upon the emotional expressions that belong to the self as such. Of course, there have
been idealisms prior to that of the Romantic school. There has
been the idealism of Plato, of the Neo-Platonists, of Leibnitz;
but in the idealism of none of these was the center of reality
the self, although for them, too, the relations of things were the
relations of thought. \Ttls the self-process, the realization of the
self
through the not-selfT^nd the construction of the latter by
the former which gives the peculiar romantic character to the
idealism of which
[The world, then,
process of thinking.
am
is
speaklnjg./
a creation of thought;
That
is
it
arises
out of the
the subject-object relation as Hegel
which the self finds conflicts
world and then reconstructs this world through a synthesis, through a hypothesis, and finally advances to a new conflict. This is a statement of what goes on in science, in the
presented
it.
It is a relationship in
in its
process of the evolution of thought. It parallels the process of
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
we have forms, animals, and
that have certain habits, certain ways of living in the
And then something happens, some geologic change oc-
organic evolutiog. In the latter
plants
world.
curs so that the animal can no longer get hold of the object that
it
eats as food. It meets a problem in obtaining nourishment;
meets a new enemy, a parasite, a microorganism. Something
happens in its world which makes it run counter to the world
in which it has been living. If we can conceive of a sufficiently
successful mutation, we can perhaps find the solution of this
problem within a single generation. What seems most often
it
actually to take place are gradual changes, but the result of
these changes
which
is
is
that there arises a
new type of animal
or plant
adjusted to these changed surroundings. But with this
new world,
animal or plant determines its world,
its environment, in terms of its life-process. If an animal has
eyes, it has an environment that has color; if it has ears, it lives
in a world of sounds; if it has taste, its environment is sapid;
if nostrils, its world is odorous. Change the animal and you
arises a
for the
change the environment, the world in which that animal lives.
Give the animal a different digestive tract, and you have a new
food. You may say the object is there before the animal, but
it is not there as food. The animal comes with a stomach that
can digest only certain things, and so determines its own world.
Its
own
sensitiveness, its
own methods of reaction, its own
make a new world out of it.
fashion of dealing with the world
Thus we
problems.
advance means the solving of
put up to the individuals, to plant
and death; and the solution has to
see that evolutionary
The problem
or animal, in terms of
is
life
come in the appearance of some new form, a variant that springs
from the older form. And with the new form comes another environment, an environment that is dependent upon the new
form itself.
This is an opposition which appears in another manner in our
thinking. It appears, for example, in the modern theory of relativity. The world within which the individual finds himself is a
world in which he finds himself at rest while objects about him
[140]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
are in motion. Those objects which are at rest belong to the
same consentient frame as the self. To a man on Mars the
planet Mars would be at rest instead of in motion. The earth
would be moving about the sun and spinning on its own axis.
To a man on the sun, the sun would be at rest and all the planets
and suns would be whirling about it. And it could not be said
that any one of these structures is the correct one. If you say
that the position of a hypothetical
man on
the sun
is
the correct
you have to ask as to the movement of the sun itis moving. Then you say, well, we will take the
co-ordinates of the fixed stars and set them up as a fixed frame of
position, then
self, for
the sun
moves within that frame. Then
are not fixed and that you cannot
reference while everything else
you soon find that the stars
any object at rest which can be made a co-ordinate within
which all motion can take place. Absolute motion is gone; absolute rest is gone. Motion and rest are to be stated from the
point of view of the observer. That, in some sense, determines
what the world in perspective shall be.
I bring up this modern situation simply to indicate what lay
back of the Romantic philosophy. It is a statement of the world
from the point of view of the individual, varying as it appears
get
groups of individuals. Yet, the
fundamental assumption is that the world is the same world
for all. The world that we see is the same world that a man on
Mars may see if there is a man there, the same world that would
be seen by a man on the sun. And yet all these worlds are dependent upon those different individuals and their positions.
in the experience of different
The
process of perception, of thought, of organization, deter-
mines what the world shall be; and yet these different worlds,
from these different standpoints, are in some sense identical.
You can see that the problem remains the same.
The problem remains the same, but it is differently approached. We have left behind the Romantic philosophers'
solution to it. The problem with which they were dealing now
appears in a different form. There are different worlds in the
experience of different individuals, and these different worlds
[141]
THOUGHT
are determined
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
by the very process of
sensing, of thinking, in
our thought, our perception, which determines the world in which we live, so that the world of each is in
some sense different from that of the others, and yet it is identical.
the individuals. It
is
It is the same world; it must be the same world. There would
be no meaning to our conversation, no coherence in our own
thought in regard to the world about which we are all of us
conversing, if it were not the same. If that in the perception of
the individual which gives different persons different worlds
were not, in some sense, organized into a single process, there
would be no meaning. The opposition, then, between the world
as it appears as an absolute object, if there is such a thing, and
the self that knows it, is a real problem, a problem differently
stated from the point of view of different philosophers at the
present time. Einstein, for example, gives one type of state-
ment, which
is
followed by Eddington; Whitehead gives an-
The problem is stated differently at
attempt at its solution. The general problem now is presented in the form of an Einsteinian statement.
We find the assumption that each sentient individual puts a
certain frame of reference on the world so that the world has
that particular form, just as if one looked through a curved
glass. Then the world is subject to the curvature of the glass.
If we look through plain glass, the world is another world. The
world itself is dependent upon the perception of the individual.
Yet the assumption remains that these worlds are all identical.
There we see the fundamental problem which was present
for the Romantic philosophers in the opposition between the
subject and the object. As I said before, what they were doing
was to give a philosophy of evolution, because such a philosophy assumes that the development of the world is a process
of meeting problems. We carry the conception of evolution over
into life and even into inorganic processes. We speak of the
evolution of a star out of a nebula. First it is a whirling mass;
then it breaks into a double star; finally the stellar body passes
from its neighborhood and branches out into spiral form. Each
other sort of statement.
different times in an
[142]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
one of these steps is the solution of a problem presented to this
particular form. Evolution is the process of meeting and solving problems. What the Romantic idealist attempted to do was
to take this idea over into the field of thought. He recognized
that what the human intelligence does is to meet problems and
solve them, and that in doing this the individual mind is constantly recreating its world. Thus, what gives the peculiar character to this Romantic philosophy is the assumption that each
mind is only a phase of an Absolute Self, so that our thinking is
just a phase of the thinking of the Absolute Self. The process,
however, that is, the important part of it, at least, is one in
which conflict arises. In the philosophy of Hegel this appeared
as the conflict between the thesis and antithesis, which is overcome in a synthesis. As he worked it out, Hegel's dialectic is a
very abstruse, a very complicated, theory. But it is one which
can be applied to every phase of life, and not only to the theory
of knowledge. It can be applied to the theory of the state, the
theory of law, to history, to theology, and, of course, as we have
been showing, to science. It is a grandiose statement that had
astonishing success for a time, during which it seemed to be the
last
word
in
philosophy.
There was, however, a surprising lapse of interest in this
Hegehan dialectic. I have pointed out that this dialectic failed
to agree with the scientific method. Hegel undertook to show
that advance took place through conflicts between universals,
whereas scientific procedure is the result of conflicts between
universals and exceptions to them. Hegel undertook to show
what the development of science must be, but he made himself
ridiculous as a result of certain rash assumptions which he made
as to what the development of science must be. The Hegelian
dialectic did not devise a statement of scientific method. His
method was one worked out in science itself, that is, the method
of the scientist was worked out in science itself that of the appearance of the exception and the statement of this in terms of
the definite problem, the working-out of some hypothesis, and
then the testing of that. That is the scientific method, and it
[143]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
cannot be stated in terms of the Hegelian dialectic. After all,
the world is essentially a scientific world; and any philosophy
which fails to express, to make use of scientific method, is a
philosophy that is out of place. And the Hegelian doctrine, notwithstanding its astonishing success for the moment, lapsed
simply because there was no real use for it.
C Ho wever, there was one field of endeavor in which it did
obtain a more lasting success, and that was in the theory of
the state. Hegel's assumption was that we are all parts of the
Absolute Self. Any view that the individual has is, however,
finite, limited, incomplete, and consequently untrue when taken
by itself. It would have to be supplemented by those of all the
other selves organized in the Absolute Self. Hegel assumed that
the community was a closer approach to the Absolute than was
the individual. The highest form of the Absolute on earth
was, in his mind, the state, so that the state represented a high
form of intelligence, higher than that which the individual possessed. On this basis it was the duty of the individual to subject himself to the state. Hegel's doctrine
was
the Prussian court, which agreed with
absolutistic attitude,
its
well received
by
with the absolutistic philosophy which lay behind itpit was a
statement which expressed some of the organization and discipline of the Prussian community
a government of the individual, an intelligence higher than that of the individual him-
self,
did
a
fit
government from above down. The Hegelian statement
in
very well with the theories of the Prussian state, for
was very highly organized from the point of
view of its trained intelligence. It was a bureaucracy. It had a
monarch. As Hegel said, a monarch was just as necessary as the
the Prussian state
dotting of the "i."
The
real state
was the organization of the
bureaucracy itself with the trained intelligence that was behind
it. This was worked out pretty definitely in the Prussian state
by Frederick the Great. It was not autocratic but bureau-
having
bureaus highly trained servants of the state
came to represent in the minds of the
members of the community a higher type of intelligence than
cratic,
itself,
in its
so that the state
144]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
that found in the individual.
And
there
was a devotion on the
part of the individual to the state, a willingness to subject him-
seemed to represent this higher
type of intelligence. This, you see, was quite in accord with the
Hegehan conception of the Absolute Self, and of the state as a
higher expression of that Self than was found in the individual.
(^\\e Hegelian doctrine was successful, and exercised considerable influence in another field also. This other field was
history, especially the philosophy of history. This whole Romantic movement was a very vivid stimulus to historical research and interest. It started off with a romantic interest
and led on into an interpretation of present conditions in
terms of past changes, and a correlative interpretation of past
self just
because the state
itself
changes in terms of present conditions. This new historical
had been going on leading up to present conditions, this backward look over the process from the
interest in a process that
point of view of present conditions, was
what gave a peculiar
and vividness to the historical sciences in all fields. It
had back of it, of course, the evolutionary theories to which we
have already referred. I have stated that the Hegelian dialectic
was essentially an evolutionary theory, a recognition, that is,
interest
that
new forms
arise
out of conflicts of old forms. In order to
explain present forms,
it is
necessary to recognize the function
of the old form and to discover the point at which
it
broke
down, so to speak. This breakdown opened the door to the
appearance of new forms. The Darwinian doctrine of evolution afforded an excellent hypothesis for the statement of
this in concrete biological
processesTlThe history of institu-
tions could be explained similarly.
tions
On
the basis of this doctrine
what the function of the old feudal instituwas, what the function of the organization of primi-
you could
find
tive society was.
You
could identify their functions in
all
the
and then you could show
down and a new form
For example, you have the blood revenge as
different forms of these institutions,
how
the institution in one form broke
arose out of
a
it.
method of control
in the interrelationship of clans within a
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
tribe, then the repression of the attack of one individual upon
another through blood revenge, and the recognition that this
very revenge is one that attacks the life of the tribe itself, for
it sets up a vicious circle in which the punishment of one murder
the shedding of blood had itself to be again
avenged. Out of this arose a method of rude justice, the court,
leads to another
with the taking-over of the administration of justice, of its own
assessment of the crime and a penalty that should attach to it.
There you have a
conflict of interests,
and yet you can trace the
And
then you have arising out
same function through them
all.
of this the next form, which takes up the interest which lay
back of the avenger's mind and the interest, later, of the community in the life of all its members and of fusing them into a
body of law, with courts and their functionaries that should enforce that law.
I
have pointed out that Hegel
starts in his logic with the con-
ception of Being and Not-Being, with the advance from this
to
Becoming.
We find
the
same
opment of his own thought and
is
dialectical process in the devel-
in the history of the race.
There
an advance from quality to quantity, from quantity to meas-
from measure to the physical thing, and so on up to the
You have in the individual the
development of one idea into another. That is the process
of the history of philosophy. You also find the development of
one cultural movement into another. That is the process of the
philosophy of history. In other words, we find the same process
ure,
"idea" in the Hegelian sense.
in tlie history of
^^^CTlliis
man
that
we
find in Hegel's logic.
conception of the philosophy of history and of the his-
tory of philosophy
sumption
in this
is
important
connection
same
is
in Hegel's philosophy.
that the development of
His
as-
human
which appear
in logic. Reality develops, as we have seen, through Being,
quality, quantity, measure, physical things, and so on up to
the "idea." When we come to analyze the object of knowledge,
we find that it passes through these difi^erent stages. In other
society follows the
set of categories as those
words, the categories develop themselves.
[146]
To
return, for a
mo-
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
ment, to Kant, you remember he conceived of the categories as
forms of the mind given in advance of experience. Hegel assumes that the categories are forms which themselves arise
through an inevitable process which shows their implication
from one to another. This is, of course, the most general statement that could be given to evolutionary principles, and in this
sense we can refer to one philosophy of the Romantic movement, that is, Hegel's, as definitely a philosophy of evolution.
He traced the development of our ideas as they appeared in human history, following out the appearance of Being, as he conceived it, in the Milesian school of Greek philosophy, and followed it all out in detail from then on.- 'He had to force matters a bit to get the historical development into the framework
of his own logic, but he succeeded fairly well. He not only undertook to do this for the development of ideas in Greek philosophy and in the Greek community but was able also to give a
statement for all the essential Christian dogmas as these appeared both in history and in logic.
I have tried to trace the historical background of this position. It reflects the importance that the self had reached after
the French Revolution, when men were thrown back upon
themselves, after the warfare of the French Revolution, and
their return, perhaps with the sense of defeat but still with a
heightened sense of themselves, to the old world which they
had left behind, and to a rediscovery of this world when they revisited
it
in this character of the self.
That
is
what
constitutes
the romantic character of this period, the emphasis
self,
making the
as that
self the center of reality,
which the
self sets up,
and
sets up, so to speak, for the
purpose of reahzing itself, of putting
order to realize itself.
In a very definite sense
itself into the not-self in
we can speak of
this
philosophy also
not only as an evolutionary one but as one which
character.
Its
terest taken in
most important
human
of these institutions.
upon the
conceiving the world
result
is
to be
is
social in its
found
in the in-
institutions, especially in the evolution
Remember
[147]
that these institutions had
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
been thought of in the medieval period as given by God. They
were there as forms of social organization which were, in some
sense, given in advance of man, in the mind of God. They were
fixed, just as Kant's categories were fixed. This latter important effect of the Hegelian doctrine was one not so evidently
dialectical in its character. It found its expression in the study
of social institutions; it laid emphasis upon history as that within
which the forms of society have arisen, upon the study of ancient history not simply for the recording of bare political events,
not simply as the scene for the appearance of great historical
characters, but as that process within which the very forms of
later society had arisen through a really evolutionary process.
This approach to history was very much stimulated by the
HegeHan doctrine; and although the Hegelian character was
largely lost, the impetus which it gave was of very great importance.
/What Hegel
was
ess.
to
It
undertook to do, and
show that
is
in
in a great
measure did do,
institutions, as such, arose in the social proc-
this
process itself that institutions
come
into
being. Of course, this gave a new standpoint from which to
interpret, to understand, to criticize, these institutions. You
can go back to the history of them, see how they have arisen out
of particular conditions, see that they represent ideas that take
on different forms in different situations. Then you are in a
position to consider the form which the institution has at present, to see how far that form may be changed. One can study
the institutions as he can study animal and vegetable forms.
One can realize that the form of the institution is an expression
of the period, and that, as each period demands change, that
change can be brought about in the institution itself. /
There was a very vivid interest in the study of human
institutions. I have pointed out the vivid interest in history as
such. It was carried over to the study of institutions. The
Roman law, which was the background for the whole legal
practice on the Continent, was presented from this standpoint;
the ancient city was studied from this standpoint. And the
[148]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERS HEGEL
laws of institutions, the family, the various governmental forms,
the schools, were all looked at from the point of view of such
a process of evolution; they were
all
looked at from the stand-
point of structures which arose in a process, and which simply
They were strucwhich carried within themselves contradictions, prob-
expressed that process at a certain moment.
tures
lems jyhich must lead to further reconstructions.
'Crhis, of course, was carrying over revolution into evolution.
What the political movement had undertaken was a revolution
which should sweep away the old forms and substitute rational
structures for them. Its leaders sought a state built absolutely
upon the
What
principles of reason,
upon the
such a philosophy as the one we are
rights of
man.
now examining
presented was a long history of institutions which were adjusting themselves to the changes which were constantly taking
one could get into the structure, the movement, the
current of the process, so to speak, then not only could one
recognize in that a very gradual change but one could become
a part of that change. One could recognize what the change
place. If
must be, and set out to bring it
Thus evolution was brought
about."!
conception which was
very important from the point of view of the institution. Anin as a
other very important development which
in greater detail
There we have
was
to go
we
will consider later
that of the economic structure of society.
back to the so-called Industrial Revolution.
In the period of Hegel that revolution had, in a measure, taken
and Karl Marx undertook to interpret it from the point
of view of what we call "socialistic propaganda." W^e will come
back to that later. This was, however, one of the phases of the
H^elian dialectic which lasted after Hegel.
<The two most important expressions of the Hegelian philosophy were to be found, then, in the interpretations of human
institutions, and, more particularly, in this Marxian theory of
the state which was both socialistic and communistic. The
latter found its expression in the Communist Manifesto of 1847.
These are the two fields within which the Hegelian dialecplace;
149]
THOUGHT
tic
did maintain
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
itself.
One was
that of economic doctrine,
the economic interpretation of history, as expressed in Marxi-
an socialism, the dialectical materialism which has had added
impulse of life through the control which the Communists,
the Bolsheviki, have obtained in Russia\
new
On
the other hand,
was given the Hegelian dialectic in England, not in the labor group, which answered relatively late
to such a movement, but in the universities. Among them there
grew up a definite Neo-Hegelian school that found in the dialectic something of a program which was not only philosophical
but also social. T. H. Green is the representative of this latter
phase of it. The religious field also came to be regarded as a possible field for the development of the dialectic. The interpretation which Hegel had given of ecclesiastical and doctrinal hisa
lease
on
life
tory appealed to the liberal theologian in England, especially to
those within the established church. Anything can be explained
by
pNot only that, but a great deal could also be
away while still seeming to keep the meaning of that
this dialectic.
explained
which could be regarded as having one form in one age and another form in another age. The dialectic opened the way toward
a comparative history of dogma, of ecclesiastical institutions. It
opened the way to the history of religion, with the interpretation of earlier religious forms and beliefs in terms of their function in the life of the community,
That sort of interpretation ofliTstory, then, in which there is
found a continuance of function in organic process with the continual appearance of new forms, was a recognition which came
very naturally through the Hegelian dialectic. It was carried
over, as I said, in English thought in these two interests one,
a study of old institutions on the ecclesiastical and doctrinal
i
side, the setting-out of the function of the doctrine, as
against
its
over
form, the interpretation of the particular form that
doctrine took under particular conditions; and, on the other
it opened up a new world through a new approach to the
problem, the relation of the individual to the community,
which was expressed particularly in the Neo-Hegelian philosophy
hand,
social
[150]
THE ROMANTIC PHILOSOPHERSHEGEL
of Green at Oxford.
individual with the
Here we have the identification of the
community made a process not so much
for the subordination of the individual to the state, as
it
was
philosophy of Hegel, but as an identity of the
in the political
individual with the community, with a sort of inspiration for
individual endeavor toward social ends. This identification of
community was very characteristic of
was used in the political philosophy of
the individual with the
the philosophy which
Hegel
for its
statement of the subordination of the individual to
One
could turn this the other way, recognize that the
was what he was through his relation to the community. He owed himself to the community itself; he had a
devotion to the community. And not only that, but one could
recognize that in the reaction of the individual in the community arose those situations out of which changes took place.
The individual could become the social reformer, one who could
stand out in inadequate situations and point the way to higher
the state.
individual
syntheses. It
is
possible to take either attitude in the identifica-
tion of the individual with the
community
either
the sub-
ordination of the individual to the state or the recognition that
the individual
is
the
means by which advance takes
place.
There was, then, a very considerable revival of interest in
England along these two Hnes; and the Hegelian school not only
became, for the time being, the dominant school in English
philosophy but it remains a very strong influence up to the
present time, though more recently, of course, it has been displaced by the Realistic movement.
What I wanted to point out with reference to the labor movement and with reference to this history of institutions in
society, particularly its development in England, was a continued
life
of Hegelian doctrine. After
it left
the philosophical
Germany, it lapsed quite suddenly in German universities; but it had new Hfe in England and in America. Royce, for
example, is one of those Neo-Hegelians to whom we have
referred. Dewey, in his early development, was another. The
Romantic school was represented by the Concord school, by
chairs in
[150
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Emerson and others of that group. They were
parallel, really,
with the interest reflected in England, first of all in Coleridge
and then in Carlyle. However, the real Neo-Hegelian movement belonged to a somewhat later date than these last-mentioned men,
when
it
came
Hegelian doctrine from
as a sort of transplanting of the
German
munity.
152
soil to
the Anglo-Saxon com-
CHAPTER
VIII
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
PASSING
tic
as
ideahsts,
we have from Kant over to the Romanwe proceed from a conception of static forms
which are originally given, and which serve as the whole
basis of Kant's transcendental philosophy, to an idea of the development of the forms through a process, an evolutionary process. Kant conceived of the basic forms of the world as being
given in the character of the mind itself. The forms of space and
time given in the sensibility, the forms of the understanding
given in the categories, and the forms of the reason, all there are
in advance of experience. If the object, as such, arises under
Kant's doctrine, it is because of certain contents of the sensi-
bility passing into these forms.
That
is
what makes
it
an ob-
not an object for our cognitive experience unless it
has these forms that give it its reality. Sensuous experience itIt is
ject.
unless it takes on some form, has no meaning, no reality; it
cannot be known except in so far as the experiences have some
form. And in the Kantian doctrine, the form is given in adself,
This
what Kant expressed
terms of the "transcendental logic," the term "transcendental" meaning the logical
pre-existence of the form to the object. This concept, you see,
vance.
is
belongs to pre-evolutionary days.
The
in
logical pre-existence of
the form to the object cannot be stated in terms of process;
therefore
it
falls
outside of evolutionary ideas. In order that
there might be an object there, Kant, as over against the empiricists,
The
must be there originally,
undertook to show how an object might
said that the form
in
advance.
arise
out of
the mere association of different states of consciousness.
Kant
latter
insisted tha t, in order for there to be an object, the
be there
first.
',
form must
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
But the Romantic
changed
idealists
all
For them, the
that.
forms arose in the very process of experience,
in the process
overcoming antinomies, overcoming obstacles.
We are responsi-
of
ble for the forms. In other words, we have, in experience, not a
pouring of the characters of our sensibility colors, sounds,
tastes, odors
into certain fixed forms, but a process of experi-
ence in which these very forms
arise. fUogic, as
conceived of it, was a dynamic, not a
sTatic,
the romanticists
affair not a simple
mapping-out of judgments which we can make because of the
forms which the mind possesses, but a process in which these
very forms themselves
its
arise./
The process of experience' according to these ideahsts,
own forms. Now this has a very abstruse sound, of
creates
course;
but what I want to call your attention to is that it is nothing
but an abstract statement of the principle of evolution. These
Romantic idealists were undertaking in the field of philosophical speculation what Darwin and Lamarck were undertaking in
the field of organic
phenomena
Romantic
and Hegel
idealists,
at the
same
in particular,
that the world evolves, that reality itself
is
period.
What
the
were saying, was
in a process of evo-
lution.
This was a different point of view from that which charI have previously
acterized the Renaissance science of which
spoken. This Renaissance science started off with just as simple
elements as
Newton
it
could. It started with
defined "mass"
first
mass and motion. And
as a quantity of matter; but, as
that involved a conception of density and there was no
telling just
definition.
its
of
how dense your matter was, he had to get another
And he found it in terms of inertia, that is, the re-
sponse which a body offers to a change of state in either
or
way
its rest
motion. If you want to measure the mass of a body, you
measure
its inertia.
You
see
how much
force
is
necessary to set
and so forth. And in that way you measure its mass,
so that mass is really measured in terms of accelerations, that
is, accelerations that you add to motions of a body. We come
back to these simple conceptions of mass and motion; but we
it
going,
[154]
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
really define our
is,
mass
in
terms of certain sorts of motion, that
velocities, accelerations.
With these very simple conceptions
up a theory of the world. New-
the physicist undertook to build
ton gave the simple laws of mass and motion, and then, on the
basis of mathematics,
worked out an
entire mechanics,
which up
to within a very short time has been the classical theory of the
physical world.
On
the basis of this physical theory, there
is
much motion; there is just so much mass; there is just
much energy in the universe. When the system was more
just so
so
fully
worked
out, as
it
was
ciples of the conservation of
in the
nineteenth century, the prin-
energy were added to those of New-
were implied in his system anyway.
Now, such a world as this is made up simply of physical particles in ceaseless motion. That is all there is to it. We speak of
the different objects about us
trees, houses, rivers, mountains
all varied, all part of the infinite variety of nature
but what
this science does is to break them up into ultimate physical particles, molecules, atoms, electrons, and protons. The object is
nothing but a congeries of these; and, as already stated, the relationship between the particles in one object and in another
object are just as real and just as important as the relations
found between the particles within any single object itself. For
you, the tree is something that exists by itself. W^hen it has been
cut down, it is so much lumber. The stump continues to exist
as a thing by itself. And yet, from the point of view of mechanical science, the relationship between atoms and electrons in
the stump of the tree with those in the star Sirius is just as real
as the relations existing between the electrons in the trunk
of the tree. The trunk is not an object there because of the
ton, although they
physical definition that you give to
that surrounds every electron
is
it.
Every
field
of force
related to every other field of
whole universe. We cut our objects out of this
world. The mechanical world reduces to a mass of physical
particles in ceaseless motion. So far as such a world can be said
to have any process of its own, it is that which is represented in
the term "entropy."
force in the
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
With the appearance of steam engines, people tried to work
out the theory of them. And a Frenchman, Sadi Carnot, had
the happy idea of thinking of the heat which was responsible for
the formation of steam as flowing
degrees of temperature.
When
down
hill
through different
its expansive
the steam was hot,
power was great; and then, as it lost heat, it lost its power to
pand. As it flowed down the hill of temperature, it lost
power.
Of
course, energy
is
not lost in the universe.
exits
It is just
dispatched into surrounding objects. Thus, Carnot was able to
work out a theory of steam engines which hinged upon
this
knowledge of energy flowing down a temperature hill. You put
your piston rod into this stream and it will work the engine;
but when it is at the bottom of the hill, it can do no more work.
The mill cannot be turned by water that has passed. Well, now,
this presented a picture of the whole universe as just a congeries
of atoms in the sort of motion that was called "heat." If you
set any sort of motion going, you know that you use up energy
by friction in some way or other that you produce heat. The
whole universe seems to be running down toward a condition
in which this motion will be evenly distributed through the entire universe. All manifestations of energy are due to the fact
that they are on high levels, so to speak; but, given time
enough,
in the
evened out and
course of millions of years, everything will get
all
the particles will be in a fairly quiescent con-
even motion of a Brownian sort distributed
throughout the whole universe. That is the conception of entropy. That is the goal of the universe, if it has one, in which
there will be some kind of energy evenly distributed throughout.
We can be very thankful that we do not exist at that time. Of
course, we could not exist then in any meaningful sense. That
mechanical conception which science presents has no future or
a very dark one, at best. Not dark in the sense of catastrophies,
for those are always exciting; but dark in the very monotony of
the picture. The conception of entropy is anything but exciting.
Such a universe would answer only to an infinite sense of ennui.
The scientific conception, the mechanical conception, of the
dition, with a slight,
[156]
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
world did not seem to be one that gave any explanation to the
form of things. As I have said, science does not justify us in taking a tree, a plant, an animal, a house, as separate objects by
themselves. As we know, from the scientific standpoint there is
no difference between Hfe and death- simply a shifting of energies. From the scientific standpoint, the forms of things have
Of
if you start off with a certain
you can use scientific technique to
analyze it; but your abstract mechanical science, that to which
Newton gave form, does not account for any object, does not
account for the acceptance of one object rather than another.
It was Kant who took the first step toward a theory of the
heavenly bodies. He was very devoted to the mechanical
science of his period; but his imagination carried him a step
farther, and he tried to conceive how the present form of
the heavens might have arisen out of earlier forms. His statement was one that really got its scientific formulation in Laplace's conception of the solar system as a great nebula, intensely hot to begin with, and which gradually cooled down.
Kant had to assume a whirling nebula which cooled down and
resulted in a series of rings moving about the center as it condensed, gradually developing into a system of bodies of unspecific form. The velocity of the bodies on the outside of the
system would keep them from moving in toward the center, and
out of these rings the planets would arise. That is the suggestion which Laplace took from Kant and made into an explanation of the way in which the solar system arose. This was
the first step toward a theory of the evolution of the heavens.
But what I now want to present is something different from
this picture which mechanical science gives of the universe. It
is an attempt to state an object in a certain form, and to show
how that form might arise. If you think of it, that is the title
of Darwin's book. The Origin of Species ^ "species" being nothing
but the Latin word for form. What is the origin of these forms
of things.^ Mechanical science does not offer any explanation of
them. Anyway, from the point of view of mechanical science,
no
real significance.
course,
thing, given a certain form,
[157]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the form has no meaning. All that this science says about a
particular form
is
that in referring to a certain object you are
isolating a certain
by themselves.
cles.
group of physical
particles, taking
Really, they are related to
But the universe that we know
is
all
them
off
physical parti-
more than
particles.
world of forms. Now, the question is, where do these
forms come from? Certain of the principal forms, Kant said,
come from the very structure of our own minds. The theology
of the period said the forms of animals and plants go back to
It is a
He gave the earth its form and all the
forms and their motions, as well as those
a creative fiat of God.
stellar bodies their
And
that, of course,
was
the point from which the descriptive sciences of the time
bi-
of the plants and animals on them.
ology, botany, and zoology
started.
They assumed
plants and animals which had been created
made the earth.
What Darwin undertook
to
species of
by God when he
show was that some of these
forms must conceivably have arisen through natural processes.
But how could the forms as such have arisen? Mechanical science could not explain them, because, from the point of view of
mechanical science, form does not exist. There are only two obone the world as a whole, and the other the ultimate
jects^
physical particles out of which
it is
made. All the other so-called
"objects" are objects that our perception cuts out.
That
is,
we
and ignore the relations between them because we want to move them about, we want to
sit on the one and write on the other. For our purposes, then,
distinguish the chair from the table
we
distinguish
them
as separate objects. Actually, they attract
each other as physical particles, parts of a single, all inclusive
electromagnetic field. The forms are not explained by the mechanical science of the period.
such
The
biological
and other sciences
as cosmology, astronomy
all explained certain forms
which they found, in so far as they did account for them, by
saying that they were there to begin with. And even Kant assumes that the forms of the mind are there to begin with.
Now the movement to which I am referring, under the term
[158I
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
"theory of evolution,"
the forms of things
is
may
one which undertakes to explain how
arise. Mechanical science cannot ex-
up forms, analyze them into physical
cannot do more than that. Biological science
plain that. It can break
particles; but
it
and astronomical science both start with certain forms as given.
For example, Laplace's conception is of rapidly revolving, hot
nebular bodies which were present to start with. Biological science started with certain living forms; geology, with definite
types and forms of rocks. These sciences classify things in accordance with the forms that are found. But they do not gen-
undertake to show how the forms
There is, of
But this
is a recent science. It accounts for the way in which the adult
arises out of the embryo. The older theory of biology assumed
the form already there; it even conceived of a complete man as
given in the very cells from which the form of the embryo developed. The assumption was that the form was there as a precondition of what one finds. This is Aristotelian science. It is
also essentially Kantian. We have seen how we conceived of the
erally
arise.
course, the science of the growing form, embryology.
forms of the mind as given as the precondition of our experience.
Now, Lamarckian and Darwinian evolution undertook to
show how, by a certain process, forms themselves might come
into being, might arise. Starting with the relatively formless,
how
could one account for the appearance of forms?
Lamarck
started with the hypothesis that every activity of the form al-
and the form then handed on the change
As a picturesque example, assume that
the progenitors of the giraffe wanted, or had, to feed off the
leaves of trees, and so stretched their necks. They handed this
stretched neck on to their longer-necked offspring. The inheritance of so-called "acquired characteristics" was Lamarck's
suggestion to account for the appearance of forms. He assumed,
as did Darwin, that you start with relatively formless protoplasm, and he went on to show the process by means of which
forms might arise from that which was relatively formless.
In the previous chapter we were discussing Romantic idealtered the form
itself,
to the next generation.
[159]
THOUGHT
ism, and
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
we pointed out
that
it
was
development or an ex-
pression of the spirit of evolution, of the definite entrance of the
idea of evolution into Western thought. Indeed,
we spoke
of
Hegel's philosophy as a "philosophy of evolution." This highly
abstruse speculative
movement toward
movement
is
simply a part of this general
way
which the forms
it was not
helped out by the physical science of the time. It had to make
its own way, and this it did to an amazing extent. In later genthe discovery of the
in
of things arise, of origins. As a scientific undertaking,
erations
it
became
a guiding idea in practically all investiga-
tions.
I
mentioned
earlier the distinction
between the conception of
evolution that belonged to the older, the ancient thought, that
which got its classical expression in the Aristotelian doctrine,
and the evolutionary theory of this period. The Aristotelian
evolution was the development of the so-called "form," the nature of the thing which was already present. It presupposed the
existence of the form as something that was there. In this conception a metaphysical entity was thought of which existed in
and directed the development of the form. The species
which is the Latin word for the Greek term "form" was ac-
tually conceived of as a certain nature that supervised the
development of the seed of the embryo into the normal adult
form. Under the conception of Christian theology this form was
thought of as existing first in the mind of God, then as appearing
in the plants and animals and various other objects that he created, and finally as arising in our minds as concepts. The form,
however, was not thought of exactly in the Aristotelian sense as
existing in advance, as being an entelechy, the nature of the
object existing in advance of the actual animal or plant.
The difference between that conception of evolution and the
modern conception is given, as I have already pointed out, in
the very title of Darwin's book. The Origin of Species, that is,
the origin of forms. It
is
an evolution of the form, of the nature,
and not an evolution of the particular animal or
this theory
is
interested in
is
plant.
What
the evolution of the nature of the
[160I
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
object, of the form, in a metaphysical sense. It
is
this
which
distinguishes the later theory of evolution from the former,
namely, that the actual character of the object, the form or the
nature
itself,
should arise instead of being given.
As you may remember, Darwin got
the suggestion for his
hypothesis from Malthus' doctrine of population. This was an
attempt to show the relationship which exists between population and the food supply, and what effect this relationship may
have on the future of the race. Of course, Malthus' statement
was greatly disturbed by the introduction of machine production; this upset
whole. Yet,
many
it is
of his calculations,
if
not the theory as a
interesting as an attempt to state in definite
ways what the experience of the race
single factor in its environment, that
will
is,
be in the light of a
the food supply.
Darwin became very much interested in this problem, and it
led him to undertake to explain certain variations which take
place in forms as being due to the pressure of population. In
nature there are always more forms born into the world, more
plants and animals, than can possibly survive. There is a constant pressure which would lead to the selection of those variants which are better adapted to the conditions under which
they must live. This process of the culling-out of these betteradapted forms would, in time, lead to the appearance of new
forms. What lies back of this conception is the idea of a process,
a life-process, that may take now one, and now another, form.
The thing of importance is that there is a distinction made between this life-process and the form that it takes. This was not
true of the earlier conception. In it, the life-process was thought
of as expressed in the form; the form had to be there in order
that there might be life.
The idea of which I have just spoken I have referred to as
Darwinian. The same idea lies back of the conception of Lamarck. He assumes a life-process which may appear in one form
or another, but which is the same process whatever form it takes
on. The particular form which it does assume depends upon the
conditions within which this life-process is run. Thus we find
[i6i]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
same fundamental life-process in plants and in animals in
the amoeba, in man, and in every form between. It is a process
that starts in the separation of carbon and oxygen. These two,
in the form of carbon dioxide, exhaled by animals as a by-prodthe
uct of the assimilation of food, are found in water solution in
plants as carbonic acid.
of chlorophyl
and
cells
Through the mediation of the action
light this eventually
becomes food,
in
the form of various sugars and starches. These starches are
then carried to tissues that expend energy, that burn up and set
free
energy
ucts, set
waste prodon from one
in the life of plant or animal, get rid of
up the means of reproduction, and
so pass
plant or animal to another, from one generation to another.
The
essentials of that life-process are the
forms.
We
The only
find
it
same
in all living
in unicellular forms, in multicellular forms.
difference
is
that in the case of the latter
we find a
we find
differentiation of tissues to carry out various functions;
different groups of cells that take
life-process
and
specialize in that
another group of
cells
up one of the phases of the
the lungs take
in air,
oxygen;
becomes the means of the circulation of
the blood; others take over the functions of ingestion, of loco-
make
and reproduction possible. In other words, separate groups of cells carry on
different parts of the life-process. The whole process, however,
is the same as that which goes on in unicellular forms. That, you
motion, of secreting fluids that
see, is
involved
in this
digestion
conception of evolution
that flows through different forms, taking on
that.
The
cell,
now
life-process
this form,
now
as a single entity in the whole, remains funda-
mentally what it was in the unicellular form. All living cells
bathe in some fluid medium; those cells on the outside of us are
cells are those which are bathed in the fluids of the
body, such as the blood or lymph. They are the only ones which
dead. Living
and they carry over into the body some of the original
sea from which our original unicellular existence migrated.
These cells went from the surface to the bottom, and there multicellular forms arose. From the bottom of the sea to man, they
had to bring this precious fluid in which alone cells can live.
are alive,
162
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
This was
first
found
in plants.
upon the plants; but the
And animals
then came and lived
life-process has flowed
through
all,
and
remains the same life-process.
Given such a conception as this, it is possible to conceive of
the form of the plant or the animal as arising in the existence of
the life-process itself. It is very important that we should get
the conception of evolution that is involved in it and distinguish
from the earlier conception, especially if we are to understand
the appearance of this conception in its philosophic form. We
are concerned with a theory which involves a process as its
fundamental fact, and then with this process as appearing in
it
different forms.
Romantic ideahsts, who first developed a philosophy of evolution, came back, of course, to our experience of our-
Now,
selves
the
that
reflexive experience in
which the individual
real-
some sense, he sees himself, hears
the glass and sees himself; he speaks and
izes himself in so far as, in
himself.
He
looks in
hears himself. It
is
is
the sort of situation in which the individual
both subject and object. But
in
order to be both subject and
The self innow one form
a subject-object relationship which is dynam-
object, he has to pass from one phase to another.
volves a process that
and now another
is
going on, that takes on
not static; a subject-object relationship which has a process
behind it, one which can appear now in this phase, now in that.
ic,
To
get the feeling for this
Romantic ideahsm, one must be
able to put himself in the position of the process as determin-
ing the form.
And
it is
for this reason that I
have said what
regard to evolution. That does not get us as deep into
our experience as the subject-object relationship does. Logical-
have
in
of the same character, namely, a process in this case, a
life-process, going on that takes now one form and now another.
ly, it is
The
process can be distinguished from the form; yet
place within the different forms.
gestion has to be there; the
The same apparatus
same apparatus
circulation, for the expenditure of energy,
takes
for di-
for expiration, for
have
to be there for
the life-process to go on; and yet this life-process
[163]
it
may appear
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
now with
this particular apparatus and now with that. In your
thought you can distinguish the process from the form. And yet
you can see that there must be forms if the process is to take
place. We have spoken of the unicellular animal as having no
form in that sense. That statement is not entirely correct. We
know that there is a high degree of organization of molecular
structure in the cell itself. We can follow it out in a vague sort
of way. There is also structure there. You cannot have a process without some sort of a structure; and yet the structure is
simply something that expresses this process as it takes place now
in one animal and now in another, or in plants as over against
animals. That life-process that starts off with carbon dioxide,
with water and carbonic gas, goes on through plant and animal
life and ends up as carbon dioxide, in the carbonic acid gas and
water that we breathe out. That process is something we can
isolate from the different organs in which it takes place, and
yet it could not take place without some sort of organ. We can
separate the process from particular organs by recognizing them
in one or another animal, in one or another plant. But we could
not have the process if there were not some structure given,
some particular form in which it expresses itself.
ilf, then, one is to make a philosophy out of this evolutionary
movement, one must recognize some sort of process within
which the particular form arises. In the biological world this
process is a Hfe-process, and it can be definitely isolated as the
same process in all living forms, because in the scientific development of physics and chemistry, as well as of physiology,
we are able to find out what this life-process is, that is, to think
of the life-process apart from the particular form in which it
goes on
to separate, in other words, such a function as the
digestive process from the digestive tract itself;) to be able to
realize that the ferments essential to digestion, the breakingdown of starches and proteins through these ferments, and the
organization, the synthesis, of these into organic products which
the animal can assimilate, goes on in the amoeba, which has no
digestive tract at all. The importance of the digestive tract is
[164]
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
dependent upon the life of the particular group of cells that go
to make up an animal. The problem presented to the animal
form is the conversion of edible protoplasm, which is found in
plants, into an assimilable form. The plant had to protect its
fluid by cellulose. In order to get at the fluid, the animal has
to be able to digest away the cellulose. Such an animal as the
ox has to have a very complicated apparatus within itself; it
sets up a whole series of bacteriological laboratories and brings
into
them microorganisms that
set
up ferments
to get rid of the
protoplasm in its food. The
then, an adaptation to the sort
feed upon. The animal has to
cellulose that surrounds the edible
digestive tract of the animal
is,
of food which these hving cells
have a structure which will enable it to get at the edible protoplasm itself. On the other hand, the tiger, which lives on the ox,
has a rather simple assimilative problem on his hands. The ox
has done the work, and the tiger can feed on his flesh. Of course,
we are in the position of the tiger, except that we take the ox
from the stockyards! The point is that our digestive system,
like that of the tiger,
Our whole
life-process
can be much more simple than the ox's.
not devoted to digesting away cellulose
is
that surrounds food.
This indicates the
way
in
which the form arises, so to speak,
is dependent upon the
within the life-process itself.'lThe form
conditions under which the life-process goes on. It
sorts of difficulties. It has to
it meets all
apparatus in order that
process, but
is
the
same
have a par-
it may meet each of these upSuch a life-process as this, which is the
same in all these forms, was entirely unknown to the ancient
physiologist. He could look at the animal only from the outsideT'He could see what were the function of the mouth and the
feet, of the various limbs and external organs; but he could not
get inside the animal and discover this process that was flowing
ticular
cropping
on, that
difficulties.
was taking on these
diff"erent
outer forms as the plant
or animal needed a certain apparatus to enable
certain conditions. It
phy of evolution that
is
it
essential to science
and
it
to live
should recognize as basic to
[165I
under
to the philosoall
a certain
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
process that takes place, and then that
show the way
in
it
which the forms of things
should undertake to
arise in the operation
of this process.
\The question as to whether a Darwinian or Lamarckian hypothesis is to be accepted is not really of such great impor-
The important
tance.
thing about the doctrine of evolution
the recognition that the process takes
another, according to the conditions under which
That
is
the essential thing.
is
now one form and now
One must be
it is
going on.
able to distinguish the
process from the structure of the particular form, to regard the
latter as being
simply the organ within which a certain function
takes placgjCLLthe conditions call for a certain type of organ,
that orgaiTmust arise
if
the form
is
to survive. If conditions call
an organ of another sort, that other sort of organ must arise.
is what is involved in the evolutionary doctrine. The acceptance of the Darwinian hypothesis is simply the acceptance
for
That
of Darwin's view that selection under the struggle for existence
would pick out the organ which is necessary for survival. The
heart of the problem of evolution is the recognition that the
process will determine the form according to the conditions
within which it goes^om] If you look at the life-process as something which is essenttaTin all forms, you can see that the outer
structure which it takes on will depend upon the conditions
runs on.
ujftdeiLjwhich this life-process
Now,
if you generalize this, make a philosophic doctrine out
of it, you come back to some central process which takes place
under different conditions; and the Romantic idealists under-
'^^
took to identify this process,
self process in experience,
first
and then
of
all,
to identify this self-not-self
process with the subject-o,bject process.
make
these one and the -same. |
The
with the self-not-
They undertook
to
subject-object relationship
from the philosophical standpoint, and especially from the
epistemological standpoint, the more fundamental one. But the
self looms up very importantly here, as you can see, for it is a
self that is a subject. As I pointed out above, the object was in
some sense explained by the empiricist. [If you are to put the
is,
166I
EVOLUTION BECOMES A GENERAL IDEA
object into the subject-object process, you have to find a subject
that
is
involved in the presence of the object.
The
old doctrine
assumed that the world was there and that human beings
came into
was there
later
In other words, according to this view, the object
it.
before the subject. The appearance of the subject
seems to have been purely accidental, incidental. The object
might just as well be there without the subject being there. But,
what the Romantic idealists insisted upon is that you cannot
have an object without a subject^ You can see very well that
you cannot have a subject without an object, that you cannot
have a consciousness of things unless there are things there of
which to be conscious. You cannot have bare consciousness
which is not consciousness of something. lOunexperience of the
self is one which is an experience of a world, of an object. The
subject does involve the object in order that we may have consciousness. But we do not as inevitably recognize that the subject is essential to there being an object pres*rt-.' According to
our scientific conception, the world has arisen through millions
of years, only in the last moments of which have there been any
living forms; and only in the last second of these moments have
there been any human forms. The world was there long before
the subjects appeared.
assume that
ject.
What
the
Romantic
idealist
for these objects to be present there
does
must be
is
to
a sub-
In one sense this might be said to be reflecting the philo-
sophical
dogma
that the world could not be present unless
created by a conscious being. But this pfoiil^i^
more profound than a philosophical dogma.^
is
It is the
something
assumption
that the very existence of an object, as such, involves the exist-
ence of a subject to which
Well,
if
we
it is
an
object.,'
are to find an instance ofthat in which the object
involves a subject, as well as the subject involving an object,
can come back to the
far as
it is
a subject.
objects for a subject.
Romantic
idealists
self.
The
self
can exist as a
self
we
only in so
And
significant objects can exist only as
We
can see that the self-process of the
two phases of experience,
this fusion of the
the self-experience on the one
hand and the subject-object
[167]
ex-
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
perience on the other hand
sist
was one which enabled them
to in-
not only that the subject involved an object but also that
the object involved a subject. This, then,
was the
central proc-
them: the self, the not-self, are expressions of a single
process, and in this also is found the subject-object relationship
in which both terms are always mutually involved. Just as there
can be no self without a not-self, so there can be no subject
without an object, and vice versa.
rOne more word about evolution. We have a statement of the
human animal as having reached a situation in which he gets
control over his environment. Now, it is not the human animal
as an individual that reaches any such chmax as that; it is soess for
ciety.
the
This point
Romantic
is
cogently insisted upon by Hegel, the last of
idealists.
The human animal
as an individual
could never have attained control over the environment. It
control which has arisen through social organizationTj
is
The very
speech he uses, the very mechanism of thought which is given,
are social products. His own self is attained only through his
taking the attitude of the social group to which he belongs.
must become
socialized to
of this evolution, of
human
its
become
social whole.
it
He
So when you speak
having reached a certain climax
form, you must realize that
so far as the
himself.
in
reaches that point only in
human form is recognized as an
Now, there is nothing so social
organic part of the
as science, nothing
Nothing so rigorously oversteps the points that
separate man from man and groups from groups as does science.
There cannot be any narrow provinciaHsm or patriotism in science. Scientific method makes that impossible. Science is inevitably a universal discipline which takes in all who think. It
speaks with the voice of all rational beings. It must be true
everywhere; otherwise it is not scientific. But science is evolutionary. Here, too, there is a continuous process which is
taking on successively different forms. It is this evolutionary
aspect of science which is important in the philosophy of the
contemporary French philosopher, Henri Bergson, whose work
so universal.
we
will consider later.
f
168I
CHAPTER IX
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTIONTHE
QUEST FOR MARKETS
HAVE pointed out, in a general way, the great changes that
toolc
place in France during the Revolution.
The
passed over from the feudal lord to the peasant
soil
who
worked the soil. In England this process had never taken place
on any such scale. On the contrary, the development of agriculture in England tended to bring more and more of the allotments of land into the hands of single farmers, single landowners. The lands could be worked more profitably that way.
The processes of agriculture which were being introduced in
England could be worked more profitably on large holdings than
on the little holdings that the tenant had been able to work.
The older, medieval production had been intensive rather than
extensive. It was built up by old feudal conditions and had no
relationship to farming proper. If this was to be changed, it
was necessary to bring the scattered holdings together under a
single head. The result of this was that more and more of the
tenants became farm laborers, and the direction of farming
passed from the hands of the peasant into the hands of the
larger farmers. Where in France he worked them himself, in
England the allotments that belonged to the peasant passed
under the control of the landowner or the large farmer, and the
farmer was taken out of that direct control over the process of
agriculture which was characteristic of conditions in France.
Under proper methods of farming there was no need for the
nnmber of hands that were required under the older method.
The land could be more profitably operated by a smaller number of men. Thus there grew up a surplus of population upon
[169]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
one of the conditions that favorably prepared
the ground in England for the rapid development of what is
the land. This
is
called the Industrial Revolution.]
We find a very varied background out of which this economic
change took place. First of all, there are the markets, the
growing-up of voluntary organizations for the distribution of
goods, which were able to adjust themselves to new demands.
We have the development of the credit system, which had
grown up under other conditions and for other purposes, being
carried over into business. We have a change in the religious
attitude, which brings a certain discipline of mind into the
process of business. And then we have the flowering of the socalled Industrial Revolution, in which production is taken away
from the home and is carried over into more favored situations
in the factory, in which the artisan's occupation is taken to
pieces, broken up into a whole series of different tasks, and these
tasks given over, as far as possible, to machines driven by
water power, steam power, and, later, electricity, so that the
man in occupation becomes a part of a vast machine production.
This is the process which was taking place and of which the
shifts in population connected with the Industrial Revolution
are only parts.
The
With
went on in
shift of population, of course, followed the factory.
the older textile industry, the spinning and weaving
the homes.
The
capitalist sent his
employees about, carrying
raw materials which they brought back as finished
products. With the factory, the different looms were brought
to a single place where they could be driven by power. The
population inevitably followed the loom to the factory, and
in the great industrial centers we have the building of the
certain of the
factory city. This took the individual definitely
soil.
All feudal privilege,
all
away from
feudal organization,
all
the
feudal ad-
ministration, gathered about the relation of the individual to the
soil.
The
held
it,
feudal lord
was one who was
lord over his land.
He
perhaps, under another, and he under another, until
they came to the highest; but the individual belonged to the
[
170]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
soil.
The
social organization
ship tp the
was determined by
this relation-
soil.
^he breakdown
of this feudal system and the concentration
of large units of population around the
new
factories are the
features of the Industrial Revolution which are spoken of
most
often. Back of this, however, lay the development of the larger
market, a market which required production on a larger scale.
Various social structures answered to this demand. What I
want to point out in this connection is that such a larger market
means, of course, a more highly organized society; it means
bringing people into closer relationship with each other in
terms of economic needs, supplies, and so making out of groups
which had been isolated from each other, partially unified
groups. That is the social organizing process that goes on in
economicsr 'It needs to be emphasized because in the economic
process itself we are apt to abstract from the total picture everything except that which is involved directly in the process. For
example, when we are buying and selling, we consider only the
prices, their advantage or disadvantage. We put economic men
over against us, and we regard ourselves simply as economic
men. In business, religion is supposed to be abandoned. The
dictum oi caveat emptor is one that lies back of this attitude. It
answers to what we term the "materialistic" view of life. And
yet all the advances which have taken place in the modern world
have been dependent on this bringing people together in terms
of their needs, wants, and supplies as these are met in an economic fashion. (^rKT this very abstraction of the economic from
the other social processes has been of great importance and of
great value. It is possible for people to buy and sell with each
other who refuse to have anything to do with each other otherwise. That is, it is possible to hold people together inside of an
economic whole who would be at war otherwise. Economic
organization is of importance in holding together parts of a
society which might, without it, be distinctly and mutually at
varianceTylf you will take it, you will find this view of society
fromTh^perspective of economic development very interesting.
[171]
THOUGHT
I shall refer
to
it
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
again
when we come
to the
development of
socialism.
For our immediate purpose
mind an
it is
important that we have
in
outline of the conditions under which the Industrial
which an expansion of
an economic character was taking place with the development
of larger markets and the gradual development of methods of
production which would meet this larger demand.
This involved changes in social conditions which are to be
noted, in a general way, as characteristics of the Western world.
Among these is the appearance of arbitrary organizations of all
types in the midst of fixed institutions. Out of this arose in
large degree the medieval city, with its groups of individuals
not immediately connected with the soil. Under the old feudal
conditions, of course, the population was allotted to the soil,
belonged to it. The city, growing up first as the fortress, the
center for a garrison, and as a place in which the ecclesiastical
powers centered, tended to become more and more a trading
center; and there grew up guilds which supplied the immediate
needs of the community and, besides that, carried on the trading
which connected these communities with the wider economic
world. The growth of these different voluntary organizations
played a large part in the development of the industry of
the modern world and invited those mechanisms which responded to the demand. What was essential was the larger demand
and then a sort of a social mechanism that could answer to this.
L^Je find in the middle of the eighteenth century a very considerable increase in population, which it is rather difficult to
Revolution sprang up.
It is a period in
Unquestionably, the beginning of this lay in the earlier
part oT^the century and, of course, affected conditions, bringing
explaiiij
with
it
home and abroad
the larger markets at
already spoken.
of which
have
think no one has adequately pointed out just
what the conditions were that brought this about. Probably
to a large extent it represented improved conditions of health.
In other words, the death-rate probably decreased; and, with
the dropping of the death-rate, with a larger
[
172]
number
of children,
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
as well as adults, surviving, the population as a
menced
to increase steadily. -With this increase
demand
whole comcame an in-
occupation on the part of the populations,
together with an increase in the demand for goods/ Altogether
it is a very complex problem, but in general we can bring it back
creased
for
to the development of larger markets and of institutions which
were sufficiently elastic and responsive to meet the needs of this
raarket.
rhave
already pointed out what the characteristics of this
development were. The factory was the center at which production was carried on under better economic conditions than those
found in the home. The most important of these changed conditions was the subdivision of production into a number of
tasks. These could be carried on more rapidly by separate individuals, and so the process of creation was simplified. And, as
it was simplified, the way was opened for the machine; and with
this
came the stimulus
vention came also the
the machines^
to invention.
demand
I will insist
for
that this
With
this stimulus to in-
power with which
is
the unusuaFclevelopment of inventive power.
by and
large,
to drive
not simply a question of
each generation carries with
it
We
as
assume
much
that,
inventive
it belongs to one community as
any other. The difference lies in the demand, a dethat goes back to such a situation as this which I have
just presented, one in which production itself is analyzed,
broken up into a series of separate tasks which are made sufficiently simple so that a good many of them can be carried on
by machines. The result is that the laborer tends to become
more and more a machine-tender, a person who keeps the machine going. He becomes a part of the machine activity. The
demand implies a difference between the new condition and
the old; it implies that the means of production which had been
used were not adequate. It implies a general shift in the economic situation. Of course, it also implies that there are those
genius as any other, and that
much
mand
as to
able to
make
use of such apparatus; that there
labor which can be utilized, can be put into
[173]
new
is
available
vocations. This,
THOUGHT
I
say,
is
IN
possible only
chine which
is
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
where you can get power
greater than mere
man
to drive the
ma-
power. Water power, the
development of the steam engine with the demand for fuel such
as that provided by coal, the consequent development of the
coal industry
this whole process can be traced back to its beginnings in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, and that
not only in terms of a process but also in terms of the attitude
of mind, in terms of the industrial discipline of the community.
There are, of course, other changes which, perhaps, are made
too central, such as the development of iron and coal. Machinery was essential to the development of the factory to its full
productivity. Machinery meant iron. The power to drive the
machine meant coal. And there in England, at that time, close
to the surface, was the ore and the coal. Conditions, then, were
very favorable to the flowering-out of this rapid productivity,
with all the changes that it carried with it. But this was a result,
not a cause of the wider movement.
r Of particular importance was the shift in the population, and
wTth~this the breakdown of the feudal conditions which still
persisted, on the social side, in England. Most of the population
had been governed by the squire and the curate, whose positions
were those determined by the whole feudal situation. The individual peasant or farmer worked the soil belonging to another
person. He held it as a tenant. His position in the community
was determined by his relationship to the soil. While in France
there had developed a centralized government which took over
more and more of the control of production, in England there
grew up the squirarchy, a form of legal government through
the squire, that is, through the justice of the pe'aceJThis had
an astonishingly large part in the governmenfof England. It
was carried out by men, relatively untrained in matters of
law and administration. The squire and curate were central
figures of this period, and the peasant occupied a position of
subjection. The central power of the government expressed itself through the squire. He was an aristocrat. He had, of
course, higher courts above him; and when serious issues arose,
[174]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
he might be brought into a position in which his power would
be questioned; but under ordinary conditions the squire represented the government. It was a modern feudal condition, a
feudal condition, however, in which the feudal lord was himself
definitely interested in what was still the greatest form of production, agriculture. The feudal lord was a great landowner and
one who introduced better methods of production. He was interested not only in this production but also in the stabihty of
things, in the maintenance of peace. In this he was the representative in his
own
district,
representing the local government
government. But his power was
very great, greater perhaps socially than it was in terms of administration, than it was in legal terms, so that the average individual felt himself definitely under his superiors, and what he
produced came to him under conditions which were dictated
imjixe or less by the social order of which the squire was the head.
^^Jhe changes to which we have referred shifted this relation by
moving the population, or portions of it, from the soil to the
city; and in the city the individual was under no feudal lord.
Here his task was one which he himself elected, or at least that
as over against the central
was what seemed to be the situation. He came as a day laborer.
As a day laborer he needed no skill. The skill which he had as a
weaver, for example, was of no service to him in working powerdriven machines. He came in, then, as a day laborer in return
for a wage, and the wage belonged to him not in terms of the
product of the
soil
but of his
for his services instead
own
effort
He
got
money
of for the products of the
under no feudal conditions at
soil,
in return
and he got
This freed him, in a certain
sense. The wage was all too often a starvation wage, but it was
his own. It separated him from the soil.
There is one characteristic of the city as it appears in the
modern world as distinct from the city of the earlier Graecoit
Roman
of fortified
that is the appearance of voluntary organizaWestern world. At first, the cities grew largely out
places, and these fortifications or garrisons led to
world
tions in the
all.
the appearance of groups of warriors
[
175
who
entered into volun-
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
tary agreements with each other for various purposes which
they had in common. They could shift from one place to another. Then there also appeared in the church various voluntary organizations,
among
the ecclesiastical representatives.
These were succeeded by the organizations out of which the
guilds arose, that is, those occupied in production; and they had
their own organization with something of their own control. In
all the groups
the warrior groups, church groups, industrial
groups, in the so-called university or school groups
we
find, in
community, voluntary organization.
Tsup pose we may explain these in part by the comparatively
chaotic conditions. The new communities grew up in the decay
of the old ones. The mechanism for the control of the community rotted out. New methods of control had to be built up
gradually. And they were built up, first of all, over against an
ideal situation. That is, Europe conceived of itself as belonging,
above all else, to the Holy Roman church. And, back of that,
lay the assumption of a political organization under the church,
the Holy Roman Empire. Each of these organizations carried
with it an assumption of an order of society which was not
realized. The church presupposed a community, a blessed community, in which the interest of one was the interest of all. In
it were devout worshipers of God, persons carrying out his
the Western
[
behests, utterly unselfish, having the nature of the so-called
"saint" of the period. This was the ideal which the church
was anything but satisfied with the
actual order of things^ During the so-called Dark Ages, Europe
was in a state of constant warfare between very little groups.
It was a period in the Western world in which there was such
presented, an ideal which
chaos, such continuous, unmitigated hostility between
little
groups as there has not been since. And yet, Europe had accepted the conception of the church. It was assumed that the
exist in the New Jerusalem, in the world to
come. In this present world men were under probation. There
was an ideal of society, then, not yet realized, but one which
remained in men's minds. And the same situation existed in
new world would
[176]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
the political organization. There was one political head; and
those under him, the various feudal lords, were subject to
all
the
Roman
titious,
but
community
emperor.
The
actual subjugation was largely
fic-
assumption lay in men's minds. Europe was a
which there were ideals of social organization
this
in
which were not actually
realized.
were not realized was an essential
part of the life of the time. The world was supposed to have
been created by God that men might realize their ideals; and
God knowing that they would not realize them, that they would
sin, fall from grace, appointed such institutions as the church
and state that were to carry on, so to speak, until the day of
the Last Judgment. rTKe^wor ld was not conceived of as being
the sort of place in which such a society as men conceived
could actually exist. But it was there as an ideal which ought
to exist; and because it did not exist, men were in a state of
sin. The institutions of the time were built up definitely with
reference to man's being in such a state of sin. That is, the ideal,
in one form or another, was a definite part of the life of the community, an ideal which was not realized. It is that situation,
and the comparative chaos of the period which lent itself to the
appearance of these voluntary organizations, of which we have
been speaking.
Perhaps the form of this with which we are most familiar is
the appearance of the different religious gro ups, of the so-called
"heresies" which were constantly arising.\ Men conceived of
themselves as having received inspiration from God. They undertook to interpret the monuments of the church in a different
fashion than the church itself, and gathered together those who
agreed with the new interpretation. Thus, there arose new religious bodies. These were continually springing up throughout
the whole medieval period. For example, during the Reforma-
But the
tion,
fact that they
we have
the appearance of the Protestants. This was noth-
community
same thing took place on the
ing but another expression of the breaking-up of the
into voluntary organizations. \The
political side, particularly
with the appearance of the free
[177]
cities
THOUGHT
cities
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
that worked themselves out from under the control of
overlords, bought their privileges for themselves, bought the op-
portunity to pay their
own way. And out
that were relatively free, which had their
within the Holy
Roman
Empire.
And
of this arose cities
own
peculiar place
they grew up largely
about^ industrial conditionsTj
\^hat I want to point out with reference to these various
voluntary organizations^ political, economic, mihtary, or among
the students of the different universities who gathered together
in national groups according to the different countries from
which they came or in accordance with their interests is that
they came to play a part in the actual control of society. The
most striking example of such a process in our setting is the
pohtical party^he party that has no recognized place in the
constitution of the state and yet wh_ich is an essential part in
the government of the community. yTha t is one characteristic
of the whole Western life, of the whole Western community
the appearance of voluntary organizations gathering about the
which lay back of the various institutions but which were
not definitely incorporated and expressed in them the ideals
ideals
of the state, of the church, of the universrfyT^^In
all
these there
were voluntary organizations which grew up and came to play
community, of the church, of
the school or university. One finds this in the Western coma part in the actual control of the
munity; one cannot find it in the Eastern.
The phase of this process in which we are interested at present is the economic. The guilds as such were voluntary organizations in which the artisans got together to control their
markets, their prices, and then got a more or less recognized
position, came into relationship with the feudal overlords or
with cities, won rights and privileges. With the peasants them-
was
new types
relatively easy for
selves
it
arise.
First of
we have been
all,
of organizations to
there were organizations of the sort of which
speaking, that
is,
of weavers, spinners, persons
who formed
having a common
groups in order to try to get hold of certain markets, to get
interest in
their occupation,
i7]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
their
goods bought
for better prices, to
estabHsh certain mo-
nopolies.
\.Siit5-
relatively early, there arose within these organizations
who brought in a different type of economic strucThe form which appeared in the guild was a social strucin which men got together with common interests, protect-
the capitalist,
ture.
ture
ing each other, trying to get the best prices they could, trying
to control their markets, get better distribution for their goods.
But with the
a person
for
capitalist another situation arises,
who
namely, that of
who can use it
has some accumulated wealth and
purposes of increased production and distribution. With the
amount and the expense of apparatus, with the ad-
increase in the
vantage which could be obtained by holding the product so that
could be sold at a profitable time, ready capital was found to
be of great value. And with this accumulation of wealth there
arose the capitalist, who brought about the new structur e. |
Now, this is the process which we think of as having de-
it
veloped late in the eighteenth and early in the nineteenth
centuries. We can, however, trace it out very much earher.
There was a gradual development of the capitaHstic type of
industry, owing to changes in the social situation, owing to
advantages that would come to those who could gain control
over wealth for the production of apparatus and for the holding
of goods that were to be put on the market in order to get better
prices and in order to be able to get the goods to larger markets
and to markets at more distant points. For capitalistic enterprises we need only to go back to the commercial voyages of
Drake, during the reign of Queen EHzabeth. Queen Elizabeth
had a large proportion of the stock in the undertaking. Capitalistic undertakings were going on, then, as early as this; the method of operation was developing, waiting simply for the situation
that would further its increase.
That situation was, as I have said, the development of larger
markets, especially for such goods as textiles, which could be
created in
much
The
market that one gets
sort of
greater quantities as the
in a closed
179]
demand increased.
community is fixed.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Only a certain number of shoes can be worn, only a certain
amount of clothing is needed. The guild represented a group
that could answer to that particular demand. Standards could
be fixed. But there was no opportunity in such a situation for
the development of industry on any large scale. But when it became possible to ship English cloth to Europe, to send it off
into Russia,
down
came
When
into Portugal, the markets naturally be-
the market in England and Europe itself inwas a tendency to develop this on a still larger
The market was continually growing. There was also
larger.
creased, there
scale.
New
World, with its treasure brought in
in the form of precious metal, and the beginning of a community
that demanded things also. This constant expansion of the
market and the increased number of things that could be purchased on a large scale was dependent on apparatus for their
production. But the apparatus which was there was largely that
utilized for the markets belonging to these closed communities,
so that we have just the situation in which there would be a
growing stimulus to the inventor for the production of apparatus that should lead to the production of goods on a large scale.
IThere was also growing up the capitalistic organization,
banking institutions that appeared largely in response to a demand for national dynastic loans which monarchs had to put
through to carry on wars, which the church put through to support its manifold activities. Banking came to be regarded as a
legitimate form of usur]^. This contrasted with the previous attitude. In general, tKewhole of the medieval world was under
the influence of the doctrine of the church that usury was not
legitimate, that interest was illegitimate. If you borrowed
something, it was your duty to return it in as good condition
as received; but beyond that no claim could be made. Charging
interest was an outlawed practice. It was a curious thing,
though, that just at this time church officials themselves, as
well as monarchs, were borrowing on a large scale. That was
the opening-up of the
recognized as fairly necessary. But
it
was
still
not considered
legitimate for ordinary business. Here, again, you
[i8o]
come back
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
to the idea of a closed market, a situation in
no
call for capitalistic
industry.
which there was
The growth of
this capitalistic
industry was one which corresponds to the process to which I
have been referring, one which had been taking place gradually
from the time of the Renaissance.
LIlIs- rather interesting to see that the Protestants, especially
the Calvinistic Protestants, were those
who
adjusted themselves
economic chanj^' Luther's doctrine was
most
one that spread among the peasants. It was one which he carried into the moral atmosphere which belonged to that phase of
the Reformation. It had been an attitude of the church; but it
was also retained as an attitude of the reformed dogma, which
rapidly to this
came back, of
course, to faith as over against works, to the
immediate approach to God. But Lutheranism was largely a peasant movement. It was not one that had any particular
sympathy with the making-up of the modern city. On the
soul's
other hand, the Calvinistic
movementjs
a city
movement. Of
course, Calvin belongs to Geneva, IWhat the Calvinists recog-
nized was that
men were put on
earth, as
we have seen, to
God set for
carry out their problem under the conditions that
them.
And
ditions.
Calvinists recognized business as part of these con-
Being strenuous
in business
meant serving the Lord.
it was recognized
As part of the dictum taken over by Calvin,
that one could not carry on business, especially in the city,
without capital. As a
result,
Calvin was led to recognize the
legitimacy of interests And, interestingly, he took over something of the discipline of the church itself into business. There
was no
difference between
that belonged to the artisan
it
in the
two
cases.
The
discipline
was the determination of standards
of goods and produce. But there had not been any discipline
which centered about money as such. This was
introduced into the picture by capitalism. The form of business
which we speak of as capitalistic grew up, in its earliest form,
in the business
in close
connection with the doctrine of the Calvinists.
It be-
longs to the Protestant groups, especially to the Calvinists, and
[181I
THOUGHT
in the various
IN
new
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
sects, as in
England, which opposed them-
selves to the established church.
In order that the various processes of the
new
capitalistic
setup might be carried out, capital had to be provided. That
men had
to find the
means of production, and wealth had
paid into the hands of the producer in advance of the actual
turns.
The
credit system
had
to be
worked
is,
to be
re-
The whole
and it came to
out.
banking process was carried over into industry,
be recognized as necessary that money which had been held in
the form of wealth should be utilized for production and that
such a mechanism as this had to be paid for just as much as the
machine had to be paid for. The result was that capital was accumulated and put into the hands of the producer so as to enable him to produce on a larger scale. The capitalist must pay
for the money that is put at his disposal. Calvinism, which was
the city form of the Reformation, recognized these needs of business, and thus recognized the legitimacy of interest as against
important to note that change, for it represents our
economic development from the medieval situation over into
usury. It
the
is
modern
One
situation.
of the striking illustrations which
we have
of this
is
in
Shakespeare's play. The Merchant of Venice^ a picture of the
old order against the new, Shylock representing a figure who
was objected
to
fitting into the
and yet recognized,
in
some
sense, as a person
needs of the community, but also as one in a
was a
and the new. And it
was the Calvinistic group which recognized the change as it
was taking place and who came to regard the business process
as one which was instituted by God, one in which man was
called upon to carry out with vigor
it was his duty, laid upon
him by God. Man was to be strenuous in business, serving
the Lord. This was the motto of the Calvinist, and with it was
position to take advantage of his opportunity. There
struggle going on between the old order
carried over into business the discipline of the religious
Men
life.
were to put into the former the same determination, the
same conscientiousness, as had marked their attitude toward the
I
182I
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
latter.
To
a very considerable extent this discipline of the
mod-
ern economic type, that which pursues the success of business
and which pursues it with determination and intelligence, was
by the Calvinistic regime from its religious side into
the economic process. It is of very great interest to recognize
this passage. We do not find it in the Lutheran community,
in the older Catholic, ecclesiastical. Church of England group.
At first it was limited to the Calvinistic group, where the apcarried over
plication of their religious discipline taught that the individual
even the most minute and the most materialistic, could still be serving God if he carried out his duty conscientiously. It was a combination that played its part, not
only in England, but in American life in Puritanism, a combination of conscientiousness and economic thrift, with the assumption that the two go together, that man is put here to be
economically successful. The Puritans turned back to the Old
Testament and profited greatly by the Proverbs, under this new
in all his tasks,
interpretation.
Cjo we
see clearly that the great changes taking place were
not those that appeared upon the surface.
They
pass in history
under the term of the Industrial Revolution, which is supposed
to have taken place during the end of the eighteenth century
and the beginning of the nineteenth. The study of economic history has made it evident that this process had already started
both on the Continent and in England much earlier. It goes
back to that period in which the agricultural industry of
England changed from the raising of grain to the raising of
sheep and the weaving of cloth. The development of the population there turned its attention to the development of wool
and of the woolen industry. This naturally gave rise to the
cloth industry, to the spinning and the weaving of the wool,
which were processes that could be carried on in those days in
the houses of tenants on the land. The wholesale industry
was one of men who provided the wool, took it about to these
different houses, and then gathered it up afterward. There
was considerable capital involved in this; and out of this com[183]
THOUGHT
bination
we have
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the development of capitaHsm, as
we
use
the term, together with the shift in industry itself from that of
and weaving of textiles^ Of
development of other industries came along^t the
same time. The mining industries were quickened; the beginning of the use of coal was appearing; and with the development of new machines-at both ends of the process came the
stimulus to invention. Lflv^ntion is dependent, of course, in one
sense on the endowment of the inventor; but that sort of endowment is, presumably, always present in approximately the
same degree in different periods. The question whether it gets
expression or not depends upon the demand for differences in
apparatus^>
If yotrlook back over the ancient world, you see a society
which for a thousand years or more had used practically the
same sort of tools, had used the same mechanisms of warfare,
of farming, of producing practical needs. Of course, we find a
gradual perfection in these. They vary all the way from the
crudities of a semi-barbarous period up to the highly organized
mechanisms of the factories of the period of Roman civilization.
And yet, actually, the tools used were essentially of the same
sort. We cannot find through the whole period of the ancient
world^we will say stretching through the whole Graeco-Roman
period an invention which changed the process of life, not
even in the field of warfare. There, of course, stimulus was the
greatest. They had found out different modes of warfare. But
these different methods belonged to different nations. The
the
soil
to that of the spinning
course, the
Persians, for example, used vast armies with chariots in front
and with more mobile forces in the wings. The power of the
army was in its mass; it simply rolled over its opponents, crushing them out. The strength of the Greek army, on the other
hand, lay in the phalanx, in the close organization of the men.
It was smaller, could drive with lances right through the clumsy
Persian army, and then come back at it from the rear. The
Roman legion was a still more mobile organization. It was organized in small units called "maniples." Men were armed with
[184]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
They could penetrate
into the Greek phalanx and break it up. The Roman legion,
when broken, could come together again, because it was made
javelins as missiles, and with short swords.
up of separate units. And the Roman legion was triumphant.
It was the most flexible, the most efi^ective, structure among the
armies of the ancient world. We find the same formation used
throughout the period of the Persian Empire, among the Greeks,
among
the
Romans.
We
find
it
perfected as
we read
the history
simply the perfection of an accepted order. Of
armies
used some missile; but the missile was not
course, all the
the important weapon. And there was no invention of new
of
it,
but this
is
types of missiles. It
is
a curious thing to pick
up
book which
presents the antiquities of the medieval world and compare
with the history of the
armed
forces of
it
Europe from the be-
ginning of the world up to the later periods.
We
think of the
medieval world as rather static in character; and yet the armed
forces of Europe were changing radically throughout the whole
period in their methods of fighting, in the laying out of their
campaigns. In a comparatively short time they advanced from
the soldier who was lightly armed to the heavily armed knight,
who, when he fell from his horse, had to be helped on again.
Then we have the archer coming in and unhorsing the knight.
In such a book of antiquities we find very rapid changes not
only in the fashion of fighting but also in the fashion of dress.
And we find not only changes in fighting and dress but also in
arrangements for housing people. The ancient house was most
perfectly presented in the house of the god, the temple, which
reached perfection in the Greek architecture; but it was not a
different sort of house from that used for other purposes, for
living. The house of the feudal lord was the castle; it represents
changes from a mere hovel to a structure forty feet thick which
dominated the whole area. The change in the fashion of housing
is shown not only in these but also in the churches. The Greek
temple was the home of the god, a perfected house. The home of
the god of the medieval religion was a house into which the god
entered because
it
shut out the rest of the world. It was built to
[185]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
The light of the world without was brought
through many-colored windows. The whole movement within was a movement upward. The effect on the worshiping people
was to exclude the outside world. The Greek god was simply
the first citizen in the community; he invited others to come into
his house. Medieval Gothic architecture shut the rest of the world
out and tried to invite the population within; the church was the
house of a god against whom they had sinned and from whom
shut the world out.
in
they must get mercy. In the expression of these ideas we have a
is changing from generation to generation.
structure which
If
we
turn back to the feudal world, to the castle,
expressing an idea.
was
in
immediate
district,
The
feudal lord
political
we
find
it
was not simply a man who
and military control over a certain
including the peasants or serfs, the tenants
who
be-
He was also the representative of the Holy
Roman Empire. And it is interesting to see what hold this
ideal of the Holy Roman Empire had upon the whole population
longed to the
of Europe.
Holy, nor
It
soil.
was true then,
as always, that
Roman, nor an Empire"; and
yet
it
was "neither
had a romantic
it
They beThey recognized it as a political order
that had to exist just as the community pictured in the gospels
of Jesus was a community that had to exist. It existed in man's
hold upon the imagination of the people of Europe.
lieved they belonged to
it.
mind, even though unconsciously; and the feudal overlords
were the representatives of this empire. They were housed as
they were and defended as they were because they represented
That is the point I want to bring out ^^he structure of
it.
the medieval world expressed ideasTJ Of course, any house can
express an idea, that of living in it, of protection from the climate, of providing means of getting food, of bringing about
social life; but we do not think of a house as an idea, but simply
as a house within which these activities of various sorts have to
go on. And the same thing could be said of the religious life as
took place in the Greek temple. One did not think of the
temple as expressing the ideas behind Greek religion. It was
a place where men met the gods, so to speak. A man merely
it
186I
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
met the god
in his temple.
The power
of the god was mani-
But the church, as such, expressed an idea, an
was not religion. It ought to have found expression
rehgion, but it did not; so it was expressed in stone and mor-
fested there.
idea which
in
tar, through the architecture, fjust as did the castle, so the
church expressed the idea of the Holy Roman Empire)
As an illustration of this take Goethe's Gotz von Berlichingen^
and you will see the hold which these ideas had on medieval
Europe. The dominance of ideas which have to be expressed
and the expression of the ideas varies from generation to
generation, from artisan and artist of one period to another.
the idea is actually embodied in the apparatus itself, we
do not think about the idea as distinct from the structure; but
in the medieval world the idea was expressed as an idea.
xAU this is a part of the whole series of very interesting conditions leading up to the appearance of the Industrial Revolution. What I want to warn you against is the assumption
that it suddenly appeared at the end of the eighteenth and
Where
You can trace it all
Reformation and beyond. It
grew out of the gradual change in situation which led, first of
all, to a larger market that could utilize the voluntary organization of which I spoke earlier, which could make use of the apparatus already present such as the growing presence of capital in connection with the obligations of the church and state.
W^hat is of particular interest in connection with this is the
assumption of a sort of economic community that lies behind
that whole economic process. Europe, of course, recognized itself as belonging to a single spiritual community, Christendom;
but that was largely broken up under feudal conditions, and
then there appeared national states, particularly those of Spain,
France, and England. Germany lagged behind. The larger
community was broken up, and warfare was a very large part
of the interrelation of these communities with each other. The
economic community, on the other hand, was a community
that looked for peaceful conditions. The individual might profit
the beginning of the nineteenth century.
way back
to the period of the
[187]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
by war, but economic procedure looked
for peaceful conditions.
brought together people who were separated nationally,
in language, in customs. The economic community brought
them together on a common basis. It was more universal in
one respect than the church. One could carry on economic processes with the infidel, with the man who was an outcast from
religious or political communities. One could carry on economic
processes with the savages. It was the most universal aspect of
the life of this period
more universal than the church itself,
Also,
it
so far as intercourse between peoples, between communities,
was concerned.
It was, therefore, a process that abstracted
very
community.
We must keep clearly in mind the point which I presented
in the last chapter, because it had a very definite bearing upon
the appearance of Adam Smith's An Enquiry into the Nature
and Causes of the Wealth of Nations and the development of
the economic school of which Adam Smith was the great representative. Hume belonged to the same period, and Smith
carried over some of the former's thought in his own discussion of finance. A development of this point of view also took
largely from the fixed standards of the
place in France in the appearance of the physiocrats as over
against the mercantilists. In this doctrine
ment of
we have
the develop-
a point of view which recognizes a form of
community
back of political and ecclesiastical organization. The
very title which Adam Smith gave to his work is illustrative of
this point of view
the wealth of nations, a wealth that belonged to nations, as if they constituted one community. It is a
that
lies
what is called the "old mercantiHst political
economy." This economy was directed toward getting just as
much of the precious metals as possible. It was a political economy of the man who was the direct servant of a dynast, of a
monarch who had to finance a court and an army. Such a minreaction against
ister
looked toward the gathering of precious metals into the
realm.
And any form
of industry was fostered which would
bring precious metals in and hold them in the country where
tax-gatherers could get hold of them, the latter being, presumf
188
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
The
ably, a desirable phase of the situation.
upon wealth
trol
in
mercantilist looked
terms of precious metals and undertook to con-
industry and commerce so as to bring them into the realm.
Mercantilism did not go very deeply into conditions of pro-
What
was interested in was
a by-product of wealth. Under such conditions the monarch
might set up all sorts of monopolies and charge for them exorbitantly. But in the end, this would only decrease the wealth
of the community. We have the political power endeavoring to
extract, as far as it could, what money could be got from the
economic processes of the community, endeavoring to control
production and commerce to bring in wealth. The physiocrat,
on the other hand, was one who at least carried his analysis further. He went so far as to ask what the source of the wealth was.
And, as far as he could see, it came out of the ground. It came
duction and wealth themselves.
it
form of agriculture or in the form of the results of
way or another the soil, or what lay under it,
was the source of all wealth. And it was of importance, if one
wished to gather the coin itself as a symbol of wealth, that one
should control the source from which that wealth came. That,
out
in the
mining.
In one
was an advance upon this superficial character of the
mercantiHst doctrine which dealt with wealth simply in terms of
money and which tried to control industry and commerce so as
to produce the greatest amount of money. At least the physioat least,
crats recognized that governmental procedure
which increased
the produce of the community was of more importance than
that which simply brought in gold and silver.
lies behind Adam Smith's An Enquiry
Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations is not that
of immediate sources of production of articles which become
wealth, but rather the process of exchange. It is the market
that lies behind the political economy of Adam Smith. And
not only the market in the particular community but the
The conception which
into the
world-market.
The
mercantilist thought of the
could be extracted by tax-gatherers.
of the
soil as
The
money
that
physiocrats thought
that out of which valuable articles which could
[189]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
be bought and sold arose.
Adam
Smith thought of wealth
in
connection with a market within which exchange takes place.
course, there must be something to exchange. And this exchange must be profitable. The assumption of the mercantilists,
and the physiocrats, too, for that matter, had been that every
bargain was a battle of wits, that somebody was victorious and
Of
someone
else
was defeated; that the nature of a bargain was that
between horse-traders. Someone got the best of the bargain and
got the better of his opponent. Adam Smith looked further than
that. He said a bargain, to be worth while, ought to be good for
both parties. He presented a picture of communities that produced more than they could use, and, in so far as they did produce more, they took the surplus into the world and traded it for
the surpluses of other nations.
They took
their
own
surpluses,
articles not valuable at home, into the world-market where persons wanted them and where they bought up this surplus, the
articles over and above those which were wanted in their own
homes. Persons came together under those conditions who could
both profitably carry out a bargain. One has something that he
has produced beyond his own demand; another has something
which he has produced beyond his demand. They want to make
an exchange. After this is accomphshed, both are better off.
That conception is what lay at the bottom of the political econ-
omy
Adam
It makes all sorts of assumptions, of
beyond mere production with reference to
a fixed community such as the guild. It is a step beyond the pohtical economy that simply looks to returns in the form of dollars and cents. It is also a step beyond the doctrine of the physi-
of
course, but
it is
Smith.
a step
ocrats that simply looked to the general source of wealth in a
community. It came back to the actual demand as it appears in
the market a demand which implies production beyond the demand of the community that produces, and a production that
is brought to the central market directly or indirectly, to be exchanged with the surplus of another community. Adam Smith
brought out this conception with its various implications in
Enquiry into the Nature and Causes oj the Wealth of Nations.
An
190]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
What was back
of this conception was the possibihty of pro-
duction on a large scale. In order to
make
profitable the sort of
bargaining that Smith presented, one must produce something
which one does not want in order that it may be exchanged for
something that someone else produces that one does want; and
one must produce in wholesale fashion, beyond one's own demand. This led to the establishment of the factory. And when
you have the factory, when persons can begin producing for a
market which goes beyond the needs of a single community, the
demand then comes for a division of labor. One man can do one
thing more rapidly than he can do several things. An artisan
carries his article through from the raw material to the finished
product. He cannot do all the necessary things as rapidly as a
man could carry out a single process. Divide a process up into
its various steps and then you get production at a greater rate.
Of course, as you subdivide the process, you invite the machine.
And, with the coming of the demand for the machine, there
comes the stimulus to the inventor. You may have a complicated process, such as that of making an entire shoe, which, of
course, it is not possible to do with the machine, at least not at
first; but if you can make the process simple, the sewing of simple seams and so on, the machine can perhaps do it better than
man and does not tire as easily. The stimulus to the production
of machinery, then, comes with the demand for production on
a large scale, from the breaking-up of the process into simple
parts which a machine can do rapidly and better than a
man.
one must have the means and such a market as that
which Adam Smith contemplated, where the surplus of one
community could be brought into exchange against the surpluses of other communities; one must have the factory in
which production can take place on a large scale. When you
have these, there is a constant demand for apparatus which will
accomplish what man cannot accomplish. One must have diviFirst of
all,
sion of labor.
One must
divide a single process up into a set of
processes which can be brought within the range of the machine
process.
That
is
what
lies
back of the problem of production.
[191]
THOUGHT
t
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Back of the whole thing
lies
the market, the economic situation
with the gradual building-up of a mechanism for it, with the
possible developments of the independent organizations such as
lie in the very genius of our Western institutions, and with the
building-up of all the financial apparatus lying behind the freeing of capital.
summed up
terest.
in,
That process which is traced back to, which is
what we call the Industrial Revolution, is of in-
But the
final
conception
perhaps
not
final,
but that
which has been of dominant interest until recent days is that
of the market which makes possible the exchange of surpluses
Thus we get a conception of wealth which makes possible a
world-economy process. We can see how the devout economist
of this period, such as John Bright, could be a pacifist
who
could
look toward the development of free trade and to the elimination of warfare because he
had behind him a community which
took in all warring nations and whose activity was one which
meant production and not destruction. It is possible, of course,
to turn even such political economy over to hostile purposes,
but the
first
conception of
it
was of the development of a
peaceful economic process in which there would be a continued
development of wealth throughout the whole, that is, the international economic community. As I have said, in this conception of the market in which one trades what one does not want
with someone else who brings in what he does not want, each
wants what the other does not want, and ideally each party
profits in the exchange.
That conception of the bargain and that stimulus
to produc-
and out of that the factory, the
for apparatus, machinery, to prolabor,
the
demand
division of
duce on a large scale, all arose. And back of that lies the demand for power. You cannot drive machinery with hand power,
and so we find a growing demand for steam. That is the way in
which the matter ought to lie in our minds. You cannot think
of the economic revolution as having arisen out of the production of steam. If you do that, you take the very last element of
the process and set it up as the first. To deal with this process,
tion
were on a large
scale;
192]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
you have
ment of
to go
back to the type of community, to the develop-
the market, and then to the development of apparatus.
In our discussion of the Industrial Revolution
we have
treated the two theories which were used in the interpretation of
That of the orthodox Manchester
it.
three important figures were
thus,
was
interpreted the economic doctrine of these
undertook to make a
of
it.
The
school,
whose
Smith, Ricardo, and Mal-
by the
men and
a social philosophy, especially as developed
who
Mills,
Adam
social philosophy, a utilitarian philosophy,
doctrine was one which undertook to deal with the
economic processes from the point of view of the market, the
determination of prices by the market in which the producers
exchanged their surpluses with each other and thus established
the prices of goods in more or less universal world markets,
and found in these prices the stimulus for production. The
process was one which led to the factory system, the intensive production of those goods whose prices stimulated this production. Thus we have a situation of supply and demand; and
perhaps in the end the demand is more important than the supply, because the supply springs up in response to the demand.
As
there
is
demand, the
different
means of production
Especially in the invention of machinery this
demand
arise.
brings
the production of machines by means of which to answer this
demand. This impHes a social process going on in a community
in which the need of the community stimulates production, and
the determination of the prices
The
process of production
in expense,
because what one
is
is
way
of registering this need.
one that
is
calls
for a reduction
seeking, of course,
is
profit
over and above the cost of production, and the prices you can
get in the
is
market determine
this profit. Successful
production
that which leaves a margin, which will permit the accumu-
lation of wealth.
The two phases
of the process are the cost
of production, on the one side, and the price which can be
obtained for the article, on the other. The economic process is
one determined by the relation of supply and demand in the
market so adjusted that profit results to the producer. Well
[193]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
any producer can bring down the cost of production, his
and the accumulation of wealth greater;
and then he can produce on a larger scale. So he tries to get
now,
if
profit will be greater
down
the cost of production in
all
sorts of ways. If there
is
means of production, of course, the price of these
go down. If there is plenty of ore, of coal, of raw
surplus of the
means
will
material, the price of the metal, of the coal, of the material,
go down. One of the very large elements in the cost of production is labor; and, of course, if there is a surplus of labor,
will
the price of labor will go down.
as he can
is
What
a surplus of those articles
production, for there
and hence a larger
lies
profit.
the producer seeks as far
which he
is
to use in his
the possibihty of getting a lower cost
Inevitably, the producer
reduce his cost of production.
The
must seek
to
cost of production will de-
pend, of course, on the surplus of the article. If there is a surplus over and above the demand, then the price of that com-
modity
will drop.
All this appHes just as logically to labor as
to anything else.
in. What Malwas
that
population
always inhad
discovered
thus thought he
creased at a greater rate than the means of sustenance. In any
community the increase in population will be greater than the
increase in food supply. I noted the fact that sometime about
the middle of the eighteenth century there was a notable increase in population in England and Europe, presumably because of a decrease in the death-rate. Malthus did not take into
It is
here that the Malthusian doctrine comes
account the relationship of the death-rate to the birth-rate.
However, he gathered
seemed
by and
large, would always be greater than the supply of food and that
there must be a continual holding-down of the population by the
figures which, as far as they went,
to support his contention that the population, itself,
process of starvation.
More
children are born into the world
and more survive than can continue
to survive with the food
supply available. Taken in terms of the birth-rate, the latter
will always be too large in proportion to the food supply.
Well, this offers to the manufacturer, to the producer, just
[
194]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
the situation he wants, that
main items
is,
a surplus of labor, one of the
in the cost of production. If
you can get a surplus
of coal, iron, anything that enters into the cost, then the price
of that will sink and will reduce the price of production.
course, in the
same
fashion, if there are
Of
more laborers than
there are jobs, the price of the laborer will sink proportionately.
What Malthus' doctrine impHed was a surplus of labor which
would keep the price of labor at the level of a starvation wage,
for, after all, that would be the limit to which the price of labor
could sink. Otherwise the laborer would starve to death. If
there is a surplus of labor in the market, people would continue
to work under those conditions as well as they could, getting
just enough to keep alive. A starvation wage would be the limit
below which the price of labor could not sink, and the limit
toward which a Malthusian doctrine would inevitably carry it.
Here we have, then, the essential element of this doctrine,
which, you see, is more than an economic doctrine. It is a theory
of society in so far as society is bound to a method of production
which is constantly stimulated by demand. The means of production, that
is
wealth, arise in proportion as there
is
a differ-
ence between the cost of production and the prices of the
you
arti-
produce an article than
the price at which you sell it, you have accumulated wealth;
and then you can go on with the process of production. There
cles
will
produced. If
it
costs
less to
be a constant tendency, then, to bring the price and the cost
of production closer and closer together. All the
means by which
the cost of production can be reduced will serve to bring about
profit.
Freedom of exchange
is
that which will establish the world-
market, in which the prices of things
will be definitely deterfreedom for exchange, we will have, presumably, the most helpful economic situation, for then those articles will be produced which are least expensive. Consequently,
the price of them can be brought down until it is a price in which
capital, as such, tends to pass into the hands of those who can
most intelligently utilize it. The price is being continually
mined. If there
is
[195]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
down by a free market. The cost of production must be
brought down if a profit is to be made possible. It is in a large
forced
concern, where manufacturing
on a wholesale
is
the factory system can be carried through to
clusion,
where division of labor can take place
you get the lowest cost of production. As
basis,
And, according
to the
have
said,
is
cheerful view
Malthusian doctrine,
This
whose hands the
tion.
is
successfully utilize
it in
produc-
to be carried on on a large scale, with expert
managers and engineers; and investments have to be made
expert fashion
if
not a
capital itself will naturally gravitate, for
who can most
The latter has
this will
It leads to that capitalistic class
for society.
they are the ones
one of
the price
continually gravitate toward a starvation level.
into
con-
to the limit, that
the very large elements of the cost of production
of labor.
where
its logical
capital
is
to
be successfully utilized.
in
an
The
hands of
those who can invest it most successfully, and then it remains
in the hands of those who can most successfully utilize it in production by constantly keeping the cost of production down to its
tendency
will be, then, for capital to gravitate into the
The so-called "iron laws" of nature, as exhibited
economic conditions, then, seem to lead toward a picture of
the community in which its capitalistic class would inevitably
gain more and more of the wealth while the rest of the community would get closer and closer to a starvation wage, which
is rendered inevitable by the natural law which Malthus is supposed to have discovered, namely, that reproduction in the community will always be greater than the food supply.
It is interesting that Darwin's theory of the survival of the
fittest came to him from reading the brochures of Malthus.
The latter's statement quite agreed with what the former had
seen in nature, namely, that among both plants and animals
there is always a larger number of young forms arising than
can survive. Something that inevitably follows, and about
which Darwin asked himself, was whether in the competition
of these young forms for a living there could be found any force
which would select particular forms rather than others; and
lowest level.
in
[196]
THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION
He himone of the most fruitful and important ideas that has come to man, and it occurred
to Darwin through his reading of Malthus' doctrine. Of course,
Malthus did not present him with the idea, but with a situation
out of which the idea could spring. If there is such a competition of young forms, then, presumably only those forms will
survive which are particularly adapted to the environment in
which they find themselves. If, as some biologists have computed, there is a death-rate of 99.9 per cent among cutworms,
you can see that those that survive will be particularly adapted
to the surroundings in which they live. There is an enormous
overproduction, with the consequent survival of a relatively few.
That is the situation that this economic doctrine presented;
and it is interesting to see how one passes from a highly optimistic view of human nature and society, as Adam Smith presented it, to a very sorry view which logically follows the working-out of his view by Ricardo and the addition of the Malthusian theory in regard to population. As we have seen, x'\dam
Smith recognized a community in which a bargain of intellects
was always a good bargain and demanded that the hands of
government, in the form of restrictions on trade, should be taken
off so that such good bargains might take place. It was a doctrine directed against governmental interference, against mothe idea of the survival of the fittest occurred to him.
self
has related
how
this
took place. It
nopolies, against the international
life
is
of the time, at least as
that existed in the form of actual and potential wars. Free pro-
duction on every side would bring people together under con-
which they could presumably most profitably exchange their goods, enabling those who could produce surpluses
of one sort to exchange them elsewhere for surpluses of another
sort. In order to reach this desirable result, all you had to do
was to let trade and the economic process alone. Do not interfere with it. Do not allow monopolies to arise. Let people produce under those conditions in which they can most successfully
do so, and these will be most favorable to trade and society
ditions in
itself.
[197]
THOUGHT
Now,
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Adam
carry out the doctrine of
Smith with
its
intense
production, figure in the cost of capital, and bring these two
sides of the shears together
duction, on the other
down with
on
hand the
the one
price
hand the
which
will
cost of pro-
be continu-
and then
Malthus' doctrine which provides society with a
surplus of population that has to be kept down continually by
starvation, and the capitaHstic picture so optimistic from Adam
Smith's point of view becomes very dark.
ally going
add
resultant curtailment of profit
to that
198
CHAPTER X
THE SOCIAL RENAISSANCE UTILITARIANISM
y4S
WE
have seen, the orthodox economic doctrine was
take away all restrictions, and that pro-^ duction will take place in any community which is most
economical, which is most productive. Each community will
produce that which it can produce better than others can. If it
undertakes to produce that which others can produce better, it
will destroy its own industries. The theory comes down to this:
simply remove all restrictions, and trade will follow the most
helpful channels. But in the actual processes of the various
countries themselves, it was found gradually to be a more complex problem than it had been thought to be. The economic
doctrine, as such, in its simplicity broke down. It could not be
said that any other definite, clear-cut theory took its place.
This was one of those times when people were feeling their way.
The assumedly fixed situation that grew out of the Manchester
doctrine was seen not to be in accord with the facts. As a result,
it was practically abandoned.
It is in such a situation that opportunism arises. This is true
even in the most rigid form of the socialist dgf trine, which, with
utilitarianism, we are about to consider. [Just because people
could not tell what the so-called "fixed laws" of economic and
social processes were, they wanted to go ahead and bring about
results which they could see were really advantageous. They
wished to improve the conditions of the working man, to see
that he lived under proper conditions, to get rid ot the slums.
They initiated movements toward minimum wages, toward
A-A
very simple
dealing, through insurance systems, with those conditions with
which the laborer himself could not deal. These are all movements which go with the pressure of labor itself in its organiza[
199]
THOUGHT
The
tion.
result
IN
was
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
you look over the
that, if
statistics of the
nineteenth century, you will find a gradual increase in wage, an
actually effective
doctrine at
all.
wage which does not answer
You
to the
economic
find also in various countries a falling-off in
actual increase of population, and a tendency toward a decrease
in the
proportionate increase in population which seemed to
answer to the intelligence of the community itself.
That is the situation, then, which really led to a feeling of the
way in socialistic and other economic views toward improvement at various points, with an attempt to set up a program of
what the order of society ought to be. There was, in other
words, a sense of progress without a definite conception of an
ideal order. People felt that they did not know where they
were going; but they were sure they were on their way,
and^hat changes which were advantageous could be brought
about. T^
An economic law was presented by the Manchester school
which called for free trade as that which was most satisfactory
for economic production. But England was practically the only
country that adopted it. England, of course, was in a very favorable position for the operation of free trade. She had the
raw materials for building factories, she had coal and iron. But
she was in great need of other raw materials for the manufacture
of articles that she needed. She also needed, as she found very
soon, more food than could be produced in England. There had
to be, then, large importations, and, of course, large exportations.
But England not only exported goods. With the increase
exported capital itself as well. She needed to have
in capital, she
the channels open so that there should be freedom of movement
within and without.
The other
countries in Europe and America
laws of various types, and there were very varied
and motives behind these laws. Of course, they all
do with industries which they were supposed to protect.
adopted
tariff
influences
had
to
They
all
protected the price of goods, but the reasons for
this protection varied.
very important
in
The customs
union, for example, was
bringing about the national organization of
f
200
UTILITARIANISM
It brought together the different German countries
under a customs arrangement and opened the door to the political union that took place later. An organization of its industries with reference to the various policies of the government
which could in a manner control the direction of production and
of trade was made possible through the tariff laws. That is, the
government in the manipulation of its tariff laws could open up
doors in various directions and close them in others. Particularly within the country itself, it could give remissions from certain
types of tariff taxation. The control which a government exercises over its railroads, for example, enables it to help the
development of its industries. In Germany there gradually grew
up a governmentally controlled industry which was organized
with reference to its foreign trade and which became a definite
part of the foreign policy of the government itself. And, for this
a tariff system was necessary. In other countries there were, of
course, different interests which gathered about the different
trades that were affected by the tariff. In our own country there
was a real tariff policy which undertook, in the mind of the
Germany.
greater part of the
community,
to protect the laborer against the
starvation wages of Europe. It gave the industries that were so
protected the advantage of higher prices.
Under
these condi-
tions there grew up, however, in America itself a type of organization of trade not directed by government but arising simply
out of the economic situation, the building-up of prices. I will
not go into a discussion of this except to point out that the
situation proved to be far
more complex than
it
was then
tariff
pre-
sented in the orthodox economic doctrine.
Along with socialism we
theory which had as
its
find the beginning of another social
objective the control of the social situa-
which were arising as a result of the complex changes that
followed from various economic practices, particularly as these
affected the living conditions of the great mass of workers. Bentham was the originator of this latter movement. He was a man
who approached the needs of English society from the standtions
point of administrative reform, particularly of criminal reform.
\
20I
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
What
he wanted in a philosophy was such a statement of the
motives and ends of men as could be easily used in terms of gov-
ernment and
also in other processes with which government had
found such a statement in utilitarianism, a position
which was already extant in the philosophy of Hume, and which
goes over, in one way or another, to Bishop Butler, at least in
connection with his theory of desire. 'These men found the motive of all conduct in a desire for pleasure and the avoidance of
pain. That was the statement that Bentham took up.
You can see how that fitted into a program for the reform of
criminal law. The sanction of the law is punishment; the motive
to do.
He
presumably the suffering which punishment
from the fear of punishment which comes
from avoiding crime.'' Those motives are the sort to which this
type of philosophy would naturally turn. The suffering inflicted
upon the criminal was to be in proportion to the crime. The
which operates
is
brings, or the relief
more heinous the crime, the greater the suffering. And in so far
as punishment is supposed to be a preventive, the more heavy
the punishment the less likely the individual is to commit crime.
If you can state motives in terms of pains and penalties, you
seem to have hold of the springs of human conduct. It is an
overly simple, a superficial statement of
is
one which
fits in
perfectly well with a
human
conduct; but
program of criminal
it
re-
form.
I
would not imply that
tham had
this
the only interest which Ben-
is
in his utilitarian doctrine.
of presenting the whole
of
field
He
human
regarded
it
nature. In
as a
its
means
simplest
form it was a way of getting over from those interests which
were the dominant characteristics in earlier societies back into
what became a more democratic society. That is, what was demanded in an English society was the preservation of the old
order, with the values which the old order conserved. But, however much one may recognize the importance of keeping these
old values, one realizes also that they cannot ail be kept and
that some have to change. Then the question arises as to which
of these values ought to be kept and which ones changed. How
[
202
UTILITARIANISM
much change can one
actually bring into the fixed order of
society?
To
illustrate this, let
me mention
tance which the preservation of
itself
seemingly a
trivial
tige as well as of the
matter,
the problem of the impor-
game took
it
in
carried with
men's minds. In
it
a sense of pres-
enjoyment of sport on the part of the priv-
ileged, the landed, classes.
On
the other hand, along with the
desire for satisfaction of a certain sort of sport, there
was the
desire for getting food on the part of the poacher. This does not
seem
to be
anything that strikes very deep; and yet you find
it
standing as a symbol for the old order and having, therefore, a
value
way beyond anything
that seems to be socially assessable.
In the face of such a conflict, what was the
community
to do?
wants to preserve what is valuable in the old social order.
Here is a practice that the upper classes cling to, especially those
who have rights over the preservation of game. They demand it
as fiercely as anything else. Now the problem is to determine
what these values are, so that it can be seen which of them are
important and which are of less importance. What system of
evaluation can be introduced into a community which has to
change, to shift, to reform, many of its old practices, to abandon
many of its old institutions? That was the need which the most
intelligent in the community felt. They wanted some way of
assessing these values to find out what was worth while.
:The simplest statement that could well be made, however
inaHequate it was, was the utilitarian. When it came to such an
illustration as that which I have just given of poaching, they
would say that you must consider the relative values simply in
It
terms of the pleasure that those
who
exercise the sport get out of
and penalties involved in poaching.
On this basis it can be said that one has greater value than the
other.^Furthermore, you can go ahead on this basis and set up a
system, a quantitative system, which is the easiest sort of a system to manage. When you put colors over against each other in
a color scheme, you find it very difficult to assess directly. You
can say that red and yellow have movement and life, while blue
it
as over against the pains
[203]
THOUGHT
and
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
violet are cold,
and green
is
calm. But
it is
very
difficult to
arrange these qualities so that they have a different, a definite,
meaning
in a scale.
way from
You
can get a vague
scale, if
you
like, all
the
the vividness of red and yellow around through the
calmness of green to the deadness of blue. But there
is
no. such
satisfactory basis for a schematism as can be found in a state-
ment of
colors in terms of waves.
Then you
find that colors are
represented by waves of different lengths and that there are
long waves at one end of the spectrum and short waves at the
other end and that
all
the different colors can be arranged in
terms of amplitude of waves.
Now,
in the
same way, when you come
to a
statement of cer-
some seem intensely
important, others trifling, and you try to arrange them with reference to each other some fine, some vulgar. But what is the
tain experiences as over against each other,
which these experiences should be may be assessed.^
If you take them in qualitative form, you find that it is difficult,
if not impossible, to arrange them on any satisfactory scale.
But, supposing you say we will consider simply the amount of
pain and pleasure a person gets out of each. Then you have
something that, at least on the face of it, can be quantitatively
way
in
amount of pleasure than the other.
Then you can add them up, make an algebraic sum of the pleasordered.
One
gives a greater
ures and pains
the pleasure positive, the pain negative and
determine what the action ought to be. And, more important,
you can go into the community at large and say: "Here is the
experience of a single individual, but
tance to him.
What
does
it
that purpose the thing you
man
mean
want
it is
to the
to get at
one of great imporcommunity?" For
is
the pleasure this
community.
Here is a man who holds rights for the shooting of game. It
means everything to him his prestige in the community, his
connection with an old line. It is of enormous importance to
him. What is that compared to need in the community, pergets as over against the privation of the whole
What right is
man and saying
amount of
more important than
haps starvation?
there in taking the
pleasure of this
that
[204]
it is
UTILITARIANISM
the suffering of the rest of the
community ?
pleasure and pain, you have a
way
If stated in
terms of
of assessing situations, espe-
with old privileges such as those which, in some
sense, marked the structure of English society of that time but
which needed to be reconstructed.
From that standpoint the utilitarian doctrine that stated
cially of dealing
terms of pleasure and pain was a very valuable
doctrine. The greatest good of the greatest number could be
set up over and against the good of the individual, and the greatest good could be stated in terms of satisfactions and of discomevery case
forts
in
and pams.;You see
that, from that standpoint,
we
also
have a leveling doctrine. The advantage that the landlord gets
out of his position is something that belongs to him as a privilege
from the community. Is his enjoyment of more value than that
of others? How can we find this out? He is a privileged person
and should have certain satisfactions. Well, why should he have
else, no matter how low on the
may be? Jhe hedonistic statement is a
Each man counts for one and only one. One
them rather than somebody
social scale the other
leveling statement.
man
enjoys a picture; another, a
mine which
is
gets out of
it
more valuable?
that counts.
game of
football.
The only
thing to consider
pleasure of the one and the pleasure of the other.
stated
it,
are on the
How
It is the pleasure that the
deter-
person
is
the
As Bentham
the pleasures of poetry and of pushpin, as pleasures,
same level, even though pushpin is on die same level
as tiddly winks. It
is
pleasure that
is
of importance^
a theory of great value in enabling people
Such a doctrine was
approach a situation which called for the reconstruction of
an old order. In this you can put Bentham and his followers
over against Carlyle. Carlyle wanted to keep the privileges of
the old order; he wanted to keep the values that attached to the
old order, to keep the old interests. But he recognized that in order to do this he must substitute, for the old feudal captain, the
to
new captain
were a
though
it
He
the
felt
of industry.
new
He
tried to deal with the situation as
feudalism, and he failed in this attempt.
same problem
as the utilitarians, that of the neces-
[205]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
sity of reconstructing society.
some
What
sort of thecjfy^h the basis of
both of them needed was
which such reconstructing
could take place. But the utilitarians certainly offered the more
workable theory. They set up a way of assessing the ends, the
values of life which could be satisfactorily used in a program of
reform.
have already referred to Carlyle as giving in England a reGerman Romantic movement, the philosophical
movement which we have already discussed. Carlyle's own attitude was a feudal attitude. The value of that order was staring him in the face. What he tried to bring to the attention of
England was that conditions had so changed that, if the older
order were to be preserved, it had to be in the form of a new type
of feudalism. A phrase was introduced that Carlyle made curthe
rent, a phrase which has a very different significance now
"captain of industry." He was a leader; one who led his laborers; one who was the head of the new economic community
as the squire was the head of the feudal community. Carlyle
looked for such a change to take place, for such leadership to be
set up. What he did not realize was that the economic situation
was one which had shaken loose the feudal figure, for the individual laborer, no longer connected with the soil, could not be
made to have the same dependence upon an economic overlord
that the peasant had felt under his feudal overlord on the soil.
The same sort of personal relationship between the so-called
"captain of industry" and the laborer as had existed in the earlier
order could not be set up in the new situation.
While Carlyle was reactionary in the sense of wanting a new
feudal order, he was responsive and sympathetic to the condition of the laborer. When labor was brought into the factory
centers, there sprang up great cities in which men and women
lived in almost impossible conditions. And there sprang up factories built around the machine in which men, women, and
children worked under ever so hideous conditions. This was not
because people were heartless. It was due to the fact that conditions changed so rapidly, because the factories had come into
I
flection of the
[206I
UTILITARIANISM
existence so quickly, because the machine brought
its
own
so-
and men did not anticipate all this. They
could not foresee its meaning. The community regarded industry as that which provided the morale of a laborer community.
It was assumed that no greater blessing could be given to the
child than to have this v/ork. The important thing was to get
the child started in the right habits and to maintain him in
them. To give the child a job as early as possible and to keep
him at it as long as possible was an act of kindness to the child.
He was getting habits of industry which would make him a successful laborer. So the captain of industry would go into an orphan asylum and place children from there in slavery in the
factory, drive them to work with whips, keep them at it until
the children could not keep their eyes open. Women and children were taken into industry under abominable conditions,
dragging as beasts of burden, the cars that carried the ore and
coal. The machine itself was allowed to determine the human
conditions of labor. I said this was done not because men were
heartless but because they had no idea of what this situation,
because they carthis industrial development, would mean
ried over the standards of an entirely different economic situacial
conditions with
it;
tion into the
new
one.
Well, these conditions of an inadequate
wage and wretched
living conditions were reflected in (Carlyle'^ writings.
He
re-
them; he saw something of what they meant. He
recognized that there was springing up an organization among
the laborers themselves. He wanted that organization headed
by the new feudal economic lord who took the place of the
feudal lord of the past. T have already referred to the characteristic in our Western society of voluntary organization which
played so large a role in the development of the Western community. We meet it again in this industrial situation. The labor
union was organized and composed of laborers themselves in
their effort to protect themselves economically in any way they
could under these new conditions. Help did not come to them
from the more enlightened part of the community, the com-
sponded
to
[207
THOUGHT
IN
munity that could be
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
The
manor and about
so sympathetic toward the tenant.
great people, those that gathered about the
the curate's house, and about the vicar, could care for the sick
among
felt
those on the land, and those in distressed condition; they
the responsibility for the tenantry.
But
in the city there
were no persons to take their place, and the community itself
did not respond to the conditions. It was left to the laborer to
assert himself, and he did so through voluntary organization as
in the past. The labor union sprang up. It expressed itself as an
organization of that type which appears when it is more or less
necessary to fight with violence. And it called forth the most
rigorous legislation which tried to crush it out. But the Western
world never succeeded in crushing it out. It grew in strength;
and finally England, through its Parliament, consented to consider what these conditions were which sprang up about the
factory town. Then came that group of highly intelligent men
who gathered about Jeremy Bentham. The two most forceful
figures of this group were James Mill and John Stuart Mill,
and son.
what these men were working against, it is necessary
to go back to conditions such as those indicated by the so-called
Industrial Revolution, in which children were taken into factories, driven to work, forced to remain at work twelve and
fourteen hours a day, under most unhealthful conditions and with
low wages. You have to go back to such conditions and to the
utter ignorance of the masses, and even beyond that to conditions that existed in these great industrial centers. If you want
a vivid picture of the life in these centers, take the group of
books by Arnold Bennett, in which he tells the tales of The Five
Towns, in which he gives an account of his grandfather's Hfe
as a child, the way in which he had worked. There is the
most vivid statement I know of in literature of the suffering of a
child in industry in such a period, and you can multiply that
many thousand times and get a realization of the amount of
father
To
see
misery there was.
^^'^rHe
champion of feudalism, Carlyle, could do nothing but
f
208
at-
UTILITARIANISM
scheme to take a world of
knaves and make a world of men out of them by an appeal to
their worst motjyeai.But he himself realized the conditions in
industry and assessed past and present and presented a picture
of conditions which must be changed. It is that sort of a picture
a need for reconstruction on the
that we must get in our minds
political side. We know all about the rotten boroughs, the system of parliamentary representation that could not be considered representative by any stretch of the imagination, in which
the monarch and the ministers bid for the vote of each member
of Parliament by emoluments they had to offer. You have a
seemingly utterly rotten system which had been held too long
in its place by the fears of the French Revolution, sanctified by
the rhetoric of Burke. The reformation was long overdue in this
tack utilitarianism, terming
it
situation.
But how was
this
needed reform to be carried out ?
How could
people determine what was to be kept and what scrapped?
These are problems to which utilitarianism certainly offered the
As
best answer at the time.
said,
it
set
up the individual
as its
final
element. It was, in that sense, democratic in character.
And
it
found a statement, "the greatest number," which was
very satisfactory for dealing with the evils and misery of society.
On the other hand, when it tried to state the great experiences
of life in terms of pleasure, it failed. The ends which we pursue
are not subjective ends.
We may
The
great things of
life
the things that are worth while are not pleasures
we have
are objective.
have a most vivid, most private inner experience; but
suffered.
The
and pains that
greatest things are those for which
we
That phase of human endeavor the utilitarians could not present. For them the
end was always the pleasure that one got out of what he did. It
was not food one wanted, it was the pleasure one got from eating
it; it was not music from great artists one enjoys, but the pleasure that one got out of music; it was not friends, not children,
sacrifice ourselves
and thus
realize ourselves.
whom one surrendered one's self, not the issue
which one gave himself, that was the end of effort, but the
not the person to
to
[209]
THOUGHT
satisfaction that
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
one got out of working
for others,
out of giving
home and
was the pleasure they got out of these things which
himself to a cause, out of devoting one's self to one's
children. It
was the end
for the utilitarians.
nature;
an unjust one.
it is
utilitarian presents
human
On
This
is
a poor picture of
human
the credit side of the balance the
an utterly inadequate statement of the ends
and see
the miseries there, you realize that to appreciate them you have
to add them up. One must put himself into an actual sympa-
of
endeavor. But
if
you turn
to the debit side,
thetic suffering of the pains of others. It
must get
is
pain
itself
that
we
about the
mitigation of suffering, and what the utilitarian doctrine gave
was a vivid statement of the amount of suffering going on that
ought to be got rid of. Over against that it presented the peaceful
sum
rid of. After all, all great religions gather
The doccame back
of pleasure of the few privileged individuals.
trine was,
however, individualistic
in
England.
It
and pain of the individual.
James Mill, Bentham's immediate successor, was a Scotchman with great force of character and an enormous capacity for
work. He came to England as many Scotchmen did at the end
of the eighteenth and beginning of the nineteenth centuries to
make his way. He had had training in Scottish reHgion, and he
became attached to Jeremy Bentham. Bentham was a peculiar
character; himself a squire, an owner of considerable property,
he was, nonetheless, a person who had a very vivid interest in the
change which was taking place in England, the change from the
feudal order over to the new order which we have been discussing. His immediate interest gathered about the administrative
to the pleasure
changes, especially those taking place in criminal law. Criminal
law, of course, had been administered
lord,
and
in feudal fashion.
It
first
of
all
by the feudal
had been inadequately general-
community from the Renaissance on. What Bentham saw was that it did not meet its own purpose. He saw the
ized for each
repression that went with
its
application,
sion did not succeed in keeping
was out of proportion
down
to the crime. It
[210]
and that
this repres-
crime, that the penalty
was assumed that
heavy
UTILITARIANISM
penalty stopped crime. Bentham saw rather that this frequent-
The whole situation called loudly for some
and Jeremy Bentham turned his attention to
these old feudal conditions. If you want a picture of the criminal
conditions of England at that time, take Meredith's Egoist^
which was written at the peak of his career. Here is a picture
of the squire in his autocratic situation, and of the radical under
these new economic situations. What you realize is that the
whole governmental control in any district was lodged in the
squire. He was the one who exercised all police power, who in a
certain sense represented national government at that point;
and, not only that, but he was father of his people about him.
He had both positions. For him, at that time, game laws seemed
more important than any others. They were important not at
all because he was interested in his hunting and fishing but because they represented his position from the time of the beginnings of the feudal order. The right to hunt, to preserve game,
was the sign of the man who was in power, and so it remained,
so that the poacher was a person who was undermining the order
of society. It seems to be a very trifling affair, but it was magnified because it represented an attack on the center, on the
power of the administrator, upon the police power in the community. The part which fox-hunting played in that period is
brought out here, and in TroUope's novels, as well as in Bentham's career. What we find difficult to realize is the symbolism
ly increased crime.
intelligent study,
of this simple sport. It represented a right, a sort of social right
around which the meaning of the order of society gathered.
\JThe political and social revolution was in a certain sense directed against the feudal lord, most of whose rights and powers
gathered about the social situation. It is for this reason that
^arlyle^became so interesting as an interpreter of the situation.
^sp- He wanted to preserve this feudal order. As I have already said,
in that sense he was a conservative. He wanted the social arrangement adjusted so that the old order could pass over into
the economic situation. His book Heroes and Hero Worship
gives a picture of his social philosophy. The mass of the com.
[211]
THOUGHT
munity were
there.
was
And
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
to follow their leader,
and there must be leaders
the fierce gospel that Carlyle preached to England
a gospel that
was
out these leaders who were to
were to carry over into industry
to call
realize their responsibility,
who
that sense of responsibility for laborers that the feudal lords had
felt for their tenantry. But the laborer himself was still to be in
the hands of this economic overlord.
his rights recognized, his hates
self
was
and
He must
be recognized,
fears listened to; but he
him-
to continue to be in the feudal situation of the older
For this, of course, it was necessary that strong and
sympathetic men should be brought up to undertake this sort
of work in the community. And Carlyle, in true romantic fashion, went to history to find his appeal. His Heroes and Hero
Worship was followed by The Life a77d Letters of Cromwell, by
his History of Frederick the Great and other studies, in which he
world.
was looking for strong men who should be leaders in the community and who should carry over the order of things from the
earlier situation into this later situation?)
have again gone over the different
features of the Industrial Revolution. I have done this in order
and particularly that of
to show how the utiHtarian doctrine
Jeremy Bentham played such a large part in it. The interest
in this philosophy was part of the shift from the feudal to the
industrial order. We have seen how this same interest is found
in Carlyle, who was also an important factor in England at this
time. Carlyle and John Stuart Mill, the third significant memIn this hurried fashion
may
be set over against each other
as two characteristic figures of this period, at least up to the
middle of the nineteenth century.
The best, rather the simplest, statement of the utilitarian
ber of the Utilitarian school,
doctrine
What
aroused.
of you are famihar with
It is a short
Jarianism.
way.
many
one
is
it
Mill's
UtilL
statement but very desirable in its
is the enthusiasm this doctrine
does not reveal
As Mill
states
it, it is
more or
less
convincing. But you
cannot really think of the youth of the community being
spired
by
it.
^n
order to realize the inspiration that
[212]
it
in-
gathered
UTILITARIANISM
we have
it did present a workable docwas democratic in its implications,
that it allowed one man to count for one and only one, and, particularly, that it set up a very simple statement of what the
end of all social institutions should be the good of the community. And when one asked what the good of the community
is, it could be said that it is an algebraic sum of pleasures and
pains of the community which should show how much pleasure
there is, and particularly how much misery therejs3When you
about
it,
to realize that
trine in social reform, that
it
come
to set this doctrine
over
terms of pleasures,
in
it
loses its
As someone said, it seemed to express the idea of
the Englishman waking up in the morning and smacking his
lips over a breakfast of ham and eggs. That seems to present a
pretty ignoble end for society to seek. But on the other side
effectiveness.
that of the getting rid of misery
can have behind
all
it
it
becomes
a doctrine
which
the enthusiasm of social reform.
starving of children, the suffering of
men and women
The
in fac-
under trying conditions, could be brought out and simit. They were sufferings which were not to be
glossed over because they belonged to lower orders, because the
world was such that there had to be suffering in it, because all
would be right in the world to come. You could not push things
aside for such reasons when distress could be stated in terms of
tories
ply stated by
the actual
endured
summing-up of the amount of
in the
suffering that people
midst of long periods of strikes, of penury, of
is brought out and added to all the
you have something which would appeal
business depressions. If this
suffering together,
to
what was
its stress
idealistic doctrine, if
What John
it
nature at that time. So, while
on getting rid of pain, it could be an
tried to.
Stuart Mill does
pleasures which
cially those
human
finest in
utihtarianism put
is
to present as highest those
we commonly regard
as
most admirable, espe-
connected with social ways of
ganization of family
life,
life
friendship, or-
and particularly the pleasures that
come from the enjoyment of literature, of science, of satisfaction
of all our multiform curiosities. Mill assumed that we have an
[213]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
He was, of course, of a
And he recognized in the
indefinite appetite for these.
highly in-
tellectual nature himself.
beginning
of popular education in England the possibihty of changing the
attitude
and
interests of
men.
He had
been, one might say, a
victim of a theory of education on the part of his father.
He was
He
studied
taught Greek almost before he was taught English.
ancient languages as a very
father,
who was
little child.
He was
a very effective pedagogue.
trained
by
his
His father
hit
on
was the oldest in the family, of
giving him lessons and then having him give the same lessons
to his younger brothers and sisters. He would then examine the
younger brothers and sisters to see how well Mill knew the lesson. It was a time-saving and very effective method. There was
a system of education in England at that time which made use
of very much this same principle. When England faced the possibility of popular education, people were frightened by the bill
which would be presented. It did not seem possible to hire
enough teachers and to pay for them to give a common-school
the scheme, since John Stuart
education to every child, so that the first systems of education
were such systems as this. A certain number of children were
taught, and then they were allowed to teach so many more. It
was a system which at least aroused a demand for public education, although it was thoroughly poor in its results.
[214]
CHAPTER XI
THE SOCIAL RENAISSANCE KARL MARX
AND SOCIALISM
THERE was
another reaction to the Industrial Revolu-
tion besides that of the reform
measures that grew out
They carried through a
series of reform measures which made English industry very
different from what it had been in the earlier period. The other
important social movement is that which was represented at
that time, and still is, by the name of Karl Marx, namely,
of the group of utilitarians.
socialism.
His doctrine is a fusion of the political economy of the orthodox Manchester school^ the three leading exponents of which
with the dialectic of
are Adam Smith, Ricardo, and Malthus
a strange marriage of minds. Engthe Hegelian philosophy
land especially, in the feverish industrialism of this period, and
Germany, at least as represented by the romanticists, seemed
about as far removed from e5.ch other as any two types of
human experience could bef You remember that romanticism
represented, in a certain sense, Europe's seeking for the recovery
of an old world, a return to the past from the standpoint of a
defeated self that gave itself up to subtle speculation, satisfied
itself for its
by
defeat by taking the whole universe into
identifying reality with the ego, with the self.
hand,
in the industrialism of
England,
in the
On
sudden expansion,
the development of wealth, with the enormous increase in
bers in the
new
community
itself,
itself,
the other
num-
you have the introduction of en-
which expressed themselves in the importance that came to England. With this came changes of a fundamental type in the whole community, that swept over the
country like an external affair, like a force, a conquering movetirely
interests
[215]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
ment that caught people unaware. To bring together the economic philosophy that lies behind this movement and the
philosophy that lies behind the Romantic school is what did
take place in the theory of Karl MarxTj Of course, he was a
refugee in London because its liberalism, of which he had little
theoretical appreciation, gave him refuge from the government
at
home.
He and
Lassalle are the
first
great figures in the es-
pousal of the sociahstic doctrine in Prussia, and he was driven
out.
thing we ought to realize in trying to undersomething that I have referred to already, and
that is the larger society which this statement of political
economy brings with it. Not only all those who want to trade,
merely economic men, all standing for the time being upon
the same level, but the industries themselves, lost that national character which belongs to them in the theory of the
mercantihst and the physiocrat. The point of view of these political economists, you remember, was that the real interest in
the process lies in the money, the wealth, which could be
secured, largely by governments for their own purpose, and in
the uses to which the governments were going to put the money.
But that presumed an industry which did not have inelastic
boundaries, one which had to be conducted from the point of
view of world-markets. It was a theory of industry built up on
the doctrine that, by the very nature of the process, every bargain had to be a good bargain. The markets were places where
the surpluses of one community could be exchanged with the
surpluses of other communities. Now, there is another side to
this internationaHsm which this doctrine carried with it, but
which it neither stressed nor clearly anticipated; that was the
Perhaps the
stand sociaHsm
first
is
International, the internationalism of labor.
The
conditions under which people worked in factories were
not national conditions.
lish
The
tenant, the peasant, had
conditions under which the Eng-
woven
cloth in the sixteenth cen-
tury and in the seventeenth century were conditions that were
peculiarly English.
They could not be put
[216]
against conditions
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
that were found in other countries.
They were determined by
conditions there. But the factory
largely international in its
character.
is
We discover that, of course, in the development of
We brought in people from everywhere, under a free
America.
immigration law, and successfully took them into the factory, and set them at work even before they could speak English. There are no national boundaries in the factory. And it
was the factory that was the center of the economic doctrine of
Adam
Smith. Laborers everywhere had the same essential conmight differ; but from the point of view of the
ditions. Prices
price of labor, as presented in the theory of Adam Smith, those
differences inevitably disappeared.
The
price for labor, as for
anything else, is got by haggling in the market. The price of
is determined by supply and demand, as is the price of
everything else; and, if there is a greater demand elsewhere, the
population flows there and the price of labor comes down. That
was part of the doctrine. So you see that labor the man, just
was much the same wherever you found
as an economic unit
it. The laborer was the same everywhere.
Here we have something of the situation to which I have just
labor
referred in discussing the utilitarian doctrine. If this theory
is
allowed to work without interference, the labor situation would
very soon become a wretched one. And misery is the same the
world over. If you take the privileged classes that secured the
votes in England, that is, the capitalist classes which could buy
their way into great landholdings and into peerages, you get a
different expenditure of money in one class than in another.
But if you come down to conditions under which people are
working under supervision, you find in one country or another
that that sort of industry levels things down tremendously. The
international character of the factory is what we must have in
mind
We
to understand socialism.
have to recognize these conditions
stimulus out of which the doctrine of Karl
arose.
John Stuart Mill wrote a
in order to see the
Marx and
political thesis
the doctrines of the orthodox school up to date in his
[217]
Lassalle
which brought
own
time.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
The
text is a logical presentation of the doctrine; but it had a
whole series of footnotes, and very many of these are what
would be called "socialistic literature." That is, John Stuart
Mill recognized the inevitable effects of this process to which
I have referred, and particularly recognized that there has to
be a control over distribution and wealth in some fashion if
society is to be kept from the conclusion toward which it
seemed to be moving, that is, a conclusion in which the price
of the market of the article, and the cost of production, could
be brought just as close together as possible, with the greater
masses of people living at a starvation wage as laborers, while,
on the other hand, all the capital would tend to drift into the
hands of those who could most effectively utilize it for production. John Stuart Mill felt that there had to be some sort of control over the distribution of wealth if this result was not to be
reached. It
is
the logical result of the theory
itself.
iThe theory of Karl Marx was perhaps somewhat more heroic
in the footnotes of John Stuart Mill's
Political Economy. And it is logical. It portrays a process of
production: the cost of production, on the one side, and the
price, on the other, in a process in which these two sides of the
shears are being brought closer and closer together. It is evident that it is in the method of production that the key to the
situation is to be found. If you get this productive process into
the hands of the community, so that it could be utilized in the
interest of the community and not in the interests of those who
are producing for the sake of profit, then you can avoid this inevitable result. That is, you can if you lay aside the Malthusian doctrine for the time being. Ilf you could control your
than anything suggested
production, not with reference to the getting of profits simply,
but from the point of view of the welfare of the community itself, that is, from the standpoint of the consumption of goods
to the best advantage of the community, rather than for the
production of wealth as such, then you could have a situation
which would be relieved of the blackest side of the picture which
the Manchester school presented.
[218I
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
we
two
one with
regard to the distribution of wealth in some fashion, and the
other with regard to the production of wealth; one which
In this connection
find
down
might, for example, shut
diflferent suggestions:
the limit of the size of fortunes,
take steps toward such a distribution as would be more even so
far as wealth itself is concerned, and the other, which is more
radical, which would undertake to determine in whose hands
wealth itself, wealth used for production, that is, capital, is to
lie. If you can put it into the hands of the government which
simply represents the interests of the community and not the
interests of any particular class, not the interests of production
which seeks the lowest rate in order to pile up profit which
comes back to the hands of the capitalist, but production for the
sake of the community as a whole if you can get all the capital
then you could
into the hands of the community in this fashion
have a possible solution of the difficulty, and that is the social-
must be controlled by the representatives of the community, that is, by the government; it must
not be owned by the individual, but by the representatives of
the people as a whole. There must be no private ownership of
the means of production, because production is to he in the
hands of the community itself.
In the theory of Karl Marx the world was pictured as inevitably
moving toward such a solution of the economic problem. Marx
istic
suggestion. Capital
presented a very logical
indeed,
the only logical
solution.
Conditions would continue to get worse until this scheme was set
The rich were
up; the poor would get poorer, and the rich, richer.
mere handful; and the poor, the great mass in the community.
clash between these must come sooner or later./ Of course,
the rich have all the advantages of the institutions of the community (they can maintain themselves in spite of being a minority), but conflict must inevitably come in the end if the community is increasing in numbers and if the community gives a wage
which is inevitably pushed by laws of economics down to a
a
The
starvation level.
few
in
If the
whose hands
lie
community is in such a situation, the
means of production would utilize
the
[219]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
them simply for more and more production in which the cost of
labor would be kept down just as much as possible in order that
it might be lower than the prices in the world-market. Such a
situation is one which cannot last forever in an intelligent community. It must be turned back from this process which is
grinding life out of the great mass of the community, and take
control over it; and if it takes control over it, a simple method
will be to get hold of these means of production and see that they
are not used for the sake of profits, but for the sake of consumption.
Adam
Smith recognized was that you get a
production of those things that people want to consume, and
you get it in the cheapest and readiest form if you allow the
process to run itself. In the end this would simply ruin society.
The machine was to be allowed to go by itself awhile and then
could be brought, in some fashion, under the control of the
community by simply having capital left in the hands of the
community itself, that is, in the hands of its agent, the govern-
Of
course,
what
ment.
The
world, then, was
moving toward such a revolution
as
Marx
pointed out in his Communist Manifesto in 1847, a
revolution in which the community must turn about and get
control of the means of production. Marx accepted the poHtical
Karl
economy of the Manchester
school.
He
emphasized
it;
indeed,
he overemphasized the results to which I have referred. He
assumed that what was taking place was caused by iron
laws until the social intelligence of the community should come
in to correct these evils. But he had back of his doctrine not
simply the logical analysis of what the current political economy
implied.
A Hegelian
ism of the period
is,
dialectic lay
back of it
too.
And
the social-
for this reason, called "dialectical material-
ism/'
procedure toward a revolution which, as I
have indicated, carried with it the implication of a reorganization, at once suggests the HegeHan dialectic, the conflict of
[__
r)f r nnrsPj
this
Being and Not-Being and the
[
rising out of that of the process
220
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
You have the inevitable conflict; then, undoubtedly, with the crash that comes will come revolution;
and then another order of things will appear. Marx had his
of Becoming.
training in the Hegelian school, and he found, in this process
which is going on, an instance of just this dialectic. Hegel himself had turned to society for the highest expression of the
spirit
a higher expression, you remember, than that to be
found in the individual. From his point of view, government
was an expression of the will of the community and of an intelligence that was greater than the intelligence of the separate
individuals. The government, or the state, we will say, was a
higher expression of the intelligence or spirit than was the individual himself. There was a demand, then, on the part of
the Hegelian dialectic science that the individual should sub-
ordinate himself to the state, for the state represented a higher
range of inteUigence than could be found in the individual.
That which took place through the state is something that
could not take place through the action of the individual in so
he isolated himself from the state. Bring people together
in society, let them operate through the state, and they produce
something that is higher than that which the individuals by
far as
themselves could possibly produce. Thus the Hegelian philosophy called for the domination of the individual by the state,
not by the monarch, who was, from the HegeUan standpoint,
merely "the dotting of the 'i,' " an inevitable symbol in the
community, but by a power that was centered in Prussia at
that time in an efficient bureaucracy. Here one found that to
which the individual could subject himself because of its
greater degree of intelligence, its higher expression of the Absolute Spirit\
WhafKarl Marx
puts in place of this political development,
or this expression of faith in the human spirit, is an economic
we have here the economic interpretawhich was the last word in the socialistic doctrine. The process which Adam Smith, Ricardo, and Malthus
had presented was a process which, of course, can be followed
process. In other words,
tion of history,
[221
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
out in history. It was not only taking place immediately about
them but had been taking place in the past. It was due to the
development of the times that matters went ahead as rapidly
as they did throughout the whole of the Western world, and
particularly in England. Production was advancing by leaps
and bounds; it was going on in an intense fashion and had
been going on in an intense fashion from the beginning. The
schools attempted to establish the laws by which all economic
processes must take place. From an economic standpoint, the
world had always been subject to these same laws. Men had
only relatively recently discovered them, just as men had only
at the time of the Renaissance discovered the laws of physical
And, as men could look back to the period before the
Renaissance and see how these laws had always operated, although at that time men had not known them, so they could
look back from this period at the beginning of the nineteenth
century and see how these economic laws had always been
in operation, and one could interpret history from the standpoint of these economic processes. Now, however, they could
nature.
not only look back into the past but they could look into the
toward this greater end a revolution in which the community should take possession, gain control of the means of production, and thus allow the community to express itself,
through the proper form of consumption. This was the picture
which Marx undertook to provide.
Hegel had gone back to the history of thought and had undertaken to show what the various categories were that had arisen
in human history. He started with Greek philosophy and followed his theory through to the Western world. He took the
different concepts that had arisen in men's minds, extracted
ideas, logical conceptions, and showed how they represented
future,
steps in the Hegelian dialectic.
He
interpreted history from the
point of view of the development of logic
that
is,
of
Hegehan
logic.
We have already mentioned
socialism of Karl
Marx, the
[
the Hegelian development in the
so-called
222
"economic interpreta-
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
tion" of history.
At that time
contrasted
it
with the HegeHan
Hegehan
great movements of
interpretation of history, using the term "logic" in the
sense, j^hile
Hegel stopped to find
in the
the Western world the development of the fundamental cate-
Marx undertook to find the development of
an economic process in which revolutions succeed each other.
He undertook to interpret history in terms of such economic
revolutions, to interpret thus the pohtical changes that had
taken place in the world, to bring back every fundamental pohtical change to an economic cause, and to place all in the
framework of the econorni^theory which he had taken over
from the Manchester schooLj
That economic theory, you remember, was one which assumed an economic process in which the individual laborer's
gories of thought,
wage, that which he got out of the process of production, was
inevitably forced
down
to a starvation limit, while the
element
of profit, the difference between price and cost of production, the
accumulated wealth of the community, inevitably passed into
the hands of the relatively few who controlled industry. The
movement of this process was toward an ultimate revolution in
which the com^munity would take control of the processes of production in the interests of the community as a whole. j^There
was, as in the Hegelian process, a dialectic in which there was an
inevitable conflict between the interests of the
the process by
means of which those
community and
were carried out.
This led, as in the Hegelian dialectic, to a contradiction, with
a synthesis upon a higher level. Finally, you remember, the
Hegelian process reaches the Idee^ in which the content and the
process become one. So in Marx's development one reaches the
theory in which the community's interest becomes identified
with the economic process itself. That would be the socialistic
state toward which the political program of the Socialist party
interests
worked."?
Thus, we have a picture of the development of the Hegelian
partly Hegelian and partly of the orthodox economic
doctrine as this appeared in the 1850's, in its formulation by
doctrine
[223]
THOUGHT
Marx and
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the part which
it played in the organization of
importance is due partly to the success
with which the labor group had been definitely organized by the
Manchester theory.
What Karl Marx did was to take history and interpret it
fromThe point of view of the development of the economic
rather than of the logical process. Just as Hegel had centered
Karl
labor in Europe.
Its
account of history about the various logical categories, so
the Marxian historian centered it about the appearance of economic laws. He undertook to explain all that had taken place
his
as forms of conflict, of revolutions which were expressions of the
economic situation which is moving toward a final revolution in
which the community should come, so to speak, to consciousness
of itself as an organization which controls every means of production and thus becomes a really intelligent community, not
simply existing at the mercy of these laws, but controlling the
situation through the knowledge of their operation. Of course,
it is
true of the laws of political economies, as
it is
of the laws of
them only by obeying them; but
if you can obey them intelligently, you can control them. Well,
this is a picture which Marxian socialism presented as over
against the very optimistic picture which Adam Smith gave,
and the very much more shaded and doubtful account that
John Stuart Mill gav3 It is only fair to say that the latter, an
orthodox member of the Manchester school of economists,
recognized, as definitely as Marx did, that there had to be some
nature, that you can control
sort of control over the
system as then presented. The interpre-
tation of the latter looked toward revolution.
It
favored the
bringing of matters to this conclusion. Let the poor get poorer
and the rich richer. Let the extremes emphasize themselves in
the community, and we will get nearer to revolution and so
get over the situation the sooner. Things must get worse before they can get better. This was Marx's inevitable assumption.
I have pointed out that the socialist doctrine carried with it
an internationalism which was implied in Adam Smith's posi-
[224]
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
tion,
but which got a more definite statement in the doctrine of
The
sociaHsm.
latter stressed the condition of labor as a result
of the process of production rather than the process
laborer's condition as painted
The
same wherever economic conditions were at work.
differ in language and social institutions and tra-
course, the
Men
itself.
by Marx was one which was, of
might
ditions; but, just in so far as social laws
were operative, men
found themselves facing the same difficulties. The same conflict
between price, on the one hand, and cost of production, on the
other, would inevitably tend to force down the cost of production and the price of labor. These conditions must everywhere
operate in the same fashion; and labor always, therefore, must
be in the same condition and must have a common interest.
There must be a solidarity on the part of labor just in so far as
it
came
It
was
to consciousness of this situation.
was
in
first
Germany
put into a
that this program of the Marxian socialism
political form.
The Sozialdemokratische
Arbeiterpartei was organized there, and gradually increased in
numbers partly because of the appeal of the program itself and
partly because the government undertook to suppress it. It
increased to something like four milhon voters at one time. It
was
a party
which was,
like other parties in the Reichstag, a
protest party. It did not accept the
way
of things. Its
members
stood for a situation in which the present order should give
and a new order appear with
was
the social revolution.
course, this socialistic party
many
way
And, of
to be found not only in Ger-
France at that time was
not so industrial as at present, so the socialistic party had no
but
in all industrial countries.
such part in France then as
it
did in
Germany and
Austria.
But through the organization of the labor group an international organization was made possible in Europe on the basis
of development of the Marxian program. It exercised a very
important influence.
was assumed at the time that this international organizawas so strong that it would make war impossible,
that the laborers of one country would be unwilling to pit themIt
tion of labor
[225]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
That theory was
however, when the socialistic party in Germany
organized itself with the government and, indeed, worked out
an adaptation of the governmental theory of the superiority of
selves against the laborers of another country.
dashed
in 1914,
Germany
all
to
all
other countries,
made
itself essentially a
the propaganda of the governmental dynast in
The
international organization
down
was not equal
part of
Germany.
to the task of
communiand the laborers found themselves in arms against each
other in a war which was more destructive of life than any
other war in history. And yet, since the war the re-establishdragging
the nationalistic sense in the separate
ties,
ment of the International has been going on. It is not, of course,
what it was before the war. That is, labor's sense of solidarity
is not, as yet, as strong as it was before the war. Labor is now
feeling its way in the same way as other groups in the community are feeling their way without having a clear program
before them.
!Z!Xh^ international organization of labor as such was one of
the great perhaps the greatest^ movements that took place in
Europe
in the last half
other great
of the nineteenth century. There was no
movement that swept all over Europe, taking hold
community as this movement did, passing
of the masses of the
over national boundaries, over differences of speech, getting together the representatives of those who were economically the
who
lowest in the social scale, but
represented the great bulk of
community, and organizing them in the interest of the program which was essentially ideahstic, one in which the members
did not expect to have immediate advantages for themselv^sTT
They were looking toward a revolution that was to take place
in the future. Especially in the early days, it was thought that
it would be about a hundred or a hundred and fifty years before
this would occur, and yet people were sacrificing immediate interests in support of this program. It was a great idealistic
movement which was essentially religious in its character. It is
the
difficult to
overestimate the importance of such a
this in bringing about, for the
[
time being, at
226
movement
as
least, a sense of
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
on the part of the members of the different communities of Europe, particularly in bringing to light problems which
the community had to face.
solidarity
That
size.
is
On
movement that
we have this sense of
the other side of the
the one side
to
empha-
solidarity
among
want
the great masses of the laboring population throughout industrial
Europe; and on the other
side, a definite presentation of
had to meet. The projMarxian
socialism
up
was one which governwhich
a
set
ect
ments were quite unwilling to undertake, and one practically
abandoned in socialistic communities in Europe. The project
the problem which government has
of control over industry in the interest of the
community
itself,
the recognition that business could not be regarded simply as
existing for profit, that the other functions of business
words, what
we
call
"public services"
have
in
other
to be recognized,
and that this recognition is one which must be enforced, if not
by public opinion, then by political institution, has everywhere
faced stubborn resistance. Such an institution as the Interstate
Commerce Commission of this country is an illustration of the
response of the community to the sort of problem that has been
set up by the development of industry and so emphasized by
socialistic groups.
They formulated
a sharp outline of the prob-
lem, so that the government was forced to approach
point of view that
it
The great change
had been unwilling
it
from a
to take before.
group against
those conditions in which the laborer would be unable to meet
the demands which society and life put upon him is bound up
with the same movement. Take the condition in which the
laborer is out of work, falls sick, gets beyond the period in
which he is economically productive. The older community left
him to himself or to charity. The system of insurance instituted in
a
Germany
community
labor,
as to the insurance of the labor
recognizes that
to care for those
it is
who
whatever the cause of the
the task, the duty, of
are willing, but unable, to
inability.
It also
recognizes
that the care given in the form of charity of one sort or another
was not only inadequate
so far as the individual
[227]
was concerned
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
but expensive so far as the community was concerned. It was
such insurance as in Germany
far less expensive to institute
than it was to leave the laborer under those conditions in
which he had found himself previously, where he was dependent
on either public or private charity. That situation, of course,
was recognized not only in Germany and in other countries
which introduced such insurance but finally in England. The
Asquith and Lloyd George governments carried through insurance policies, now represented inaccurately by critics in England as the "dole," as a means of dealing with unemployment.
It
was recognized, then, that the community
nitely face the problems that
its
must defiindustry places upon it, and
itself
them not simply in the interest of labor but in the interest of a community made up of laborers as such.
That this type of problem has been forced upon the community, forced into government programs, is in no small degree
due to the development of labor parties; and this was made
possible by the idealism of Karl Marx and those who followed
face
him.
call it
"ideahsm." The philosophy, of course,
is
ordi-
makes the industrial process escommunity. But the movement is fundamentally
an idealistic movement, for it is one that has looked toward the
reorganization of society, toward a reorganization lying in the
future. Such a movement is exactly what we term "ideahstic,"
and this movement certainly was of that sort. It is one of the
outgrowths of the Hegelian movement which we ought to
recognize particularly. I have run over its history up to the
present time so that you can put it in its relationship to this
narily termed "materialism." It
sential in the
theory.
now wish
emphasize again, from a different aspect, the
movement. Finance and
production, especially as these were reflected in commerce, were
inevitably international. But that internationalism did not lead
to any sense of solidarity on the part of the financiers, on the
I
to
international character of the labor
part of those involved in the financial process.
England and those controlling capital
f
228
in
Financiers in
Germany, France, and
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
America each retained a sense of
his
own
national character;
and, while involved in an international financial activity, each
identified himself with the
community
The
which he belonged.
which there grew up a
to
labor process was one, however, in
very considerable sense of solidarity of interests among the
borers themselves.
The
la-
position, of course, of the laborer as rep-
resented both by Marxian socialism and the Manchester school
was one of necessary misery; and misery, as we know, loves
company. The laborer in the face of the threat of a starvation wage felt himself supported by others in the same situation
in other countries. The movement toward a revolution which
would change this order of things was, then, an international
movement in which there was a sense of solidarity on the part of
the laborers themselves. How deep or superficial this sense of
soHdarity was can be found at the time of the World War, but
it
was
far
deeper than any sense of identity or of solidarity of
on the part of the financial groups as such. The financial
Germany and England were in very vivid competition
with each other. They were seeking world-markets and seeking
to oust each other in these world-markets, although they both
used the machinery of international finance. The laborers as
such had no sense of competition with each other. This is true
in regard to Europe pretty generally.
In the tariff program of American politics, on the other
hand, there was a very definite undertaking which had a considerable success in aligning the interests of the American laborer over against labor in the European countries. The higher
American wage was presented as protected by tariffs, and the
interest
groups
laborer
in
was taught
The whole
to regard himself as in a favorable position.
situation in
America was one which did not lead
to
the development of sociaHstic consciousness on the part of the
labor group.
It
has not done so up to the present time.
In
England also it developed comparatively late.
While they say that the Labor party in England at the present time has a definite socialistic program, it is one of the Fabian
sort, which does not undertake to map out just what steps are
[229]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
That is, it does not present revomust take place as a result of inevitable conflict. The changes can take place by gradual legislation, and the exact form of these changes its program does not
attempt to work out. It may be called a socialistic program,
but one which differs at least from that of the Marxian group.
to be taken in later periods.
lution as something that
The
difference to which I have just referred between the programs of the EngHsh Labor party and that of the Marxian
group is also reflected in socialistic thought in a later period.
Marx, of course, invented a definite program. This was worked
out in the program of the Sozialdemokratische Arbeiterpartei in
Germany, and it remained the dogma of that party for a num-
ber of years. Gradually, however, there arose an opportunistic
group in the Socialistic party, a group that sought to bring about
changes or an amelioration of conditions of laboring groups, an
amehoration not only in the fields of industry but also in the
social conditions of labor.
very
much
There grew up groups of
interested in municipal organization,
socialists
who sought
to
improve the housing conditions, the health conditions of the
labor group. In order to do that, they had to ally themselves
with governing groups in the community. As I stated before,
the logical position of the Social-Democratic party
was that of
which refuses to work with the active political
parties of the countries. They always registered their protest.
But if they were undertaking to carry out any program, they
had to work with the dominant parties. In spite of itself, as the
opportunistic group grew in power, the date of the future revolution, and the form that it should take, became less and less
definite in the minds of the socialists themselves. That is, to use
a current phrase, there was a tendency to substitute evolution
for revolution. It was assumed that a gradual process was taking place which would lead to some such result as that which
Marx had had in mind, but it did not necessarily have to
take place by means of a catastrophic overturning of things.
Especially it became more and more difficult to state just what
a protest party
the future situation should be in the control of industry, a
[230
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
change which was mirrored
in
such a type of socialism as guild
socialism.
There was an uneasy
feeling that
even a bureaucracy as
some way not adequate to
the task of working industry, that there was something in individual initiative, in the trying-out of possible methods of imefficient as that of
Germany was
in
which led to individual profit something
that provided a motive that could not be obtained under a
bureaucratic direction of industry. While the German railroad
industry under its bureaucracy proved itself an efficient and
sound institution, it was realized that this was a very different
economic undertaking from that of the production of articles
that had to find markets and had to be produced at continually
reduced prices. That is, it was realized that bureaucratic
methods were fixed methods, or tended to fix themselves. There
was no such stimulus to scrap the old and introduce new
methods for the old as was found in private industry. The
bureaucrat does not like to scrap his apparatus. There was this
provements
in trade,
general feeling that,
when
government
had not
as such
it
came
to the control of industry, the
as yet, at least,
proved
itself
com-
petent.
Interest shifted to the question of the control within dif-
which might be exercised by labor itself, a communistic movement which regarded
labor as the whole owner of industry. Could industry be
brought into relationship with labor itself? Could labor actuferent industries or groups of industries
ally exercise control?
Would
it
be possible to get hold of
differ-
ent types of industries which answered in a certain sense to the
old medieval guilds, in which there should be representation of
the labor interest?
You
get a shift of interest, you see, from
the control of the government over industry to a
more im-
mediate and direct control by labor itself, or the possibility of
it. These were changes which went on and are going on at the
present time in the program of labor groups a change which
answers to the breakdown of the old Hegelian dialectic even in
the field of political economy.
[231
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
to the Marxian development, we must conceive
having two roots: one the political economy, the industrial development which the Manchester school interpreted,
and the other the Hegelian dialectic. The statement which it
took from the Manchester school was of a process in which,
through supply and demand, through the keeping-down of
costs in the interest of the production of wealth, the price of
labor would inevitably be brought down to a starvation wage,
if,
as it generally was, the Malthusian hypothesis was accepted. It was assumed that under favorable conditions there
would always be a surplus of laborers, as well as a surplus of
other articles essential for production, so that expansion could
take place as industry demanded it. There should be the opportunity for expansion. In order that there might be this opportunity, there should be a surplus which could be taken up
as the demand developed. A surplus of labor meant, of course,
persons out of jobs, who were therefore on the verge of starvation. The ideal situation from the point of view of this political
economy, then, was one in which there was a line of men before
the factory seeking for jobs, many of whom could not obtain
any. The Malthusian doctrine, of course, fitted into this economic demand. There would always be a surplus of population
beyond the means of sustenance, so that there always would be
those who were seeking for a wage even if it was at the starva-
Coming back
of
it
as
tion level.
As we have
seen, this interpretation, plus that of the gradual
passage of capital into the hands of those
cessful in the use of
it,
who were not
suc-
led to the assumption on the part of
Marxian doctrine that the rich would continually grow
and the poor would keep on growing poorer up to the
point at which the community would cease to recognize this
form of production and industry would pass over into the hands
of the state. It was the demand of Marxian socialism that all
capital should be owned by the community in the form of the
state. All production should be directed by the state. It did not
abrogate private ownership; it was only a question of what
this
richer
[232]
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
No capital, no means of production, should
be owned by the individual except his wage. That which came
to him in his function as laborer should be his own, and the
should be owned.
amount which
that would be would presumably be determined
by the state in its function as producer. And production, then,
would take place not in the interest of laying aside more capital,
not in the interest of profit as such, but definitely in the interest
of the
community
itself.
The assumption of this doctrine is that the whole of history
had been moving toward a revolution and that back of the
great political movements of the past always lay an economic
motive. The development which was taking place was traced
by the socialists back to the gradual development of capital
out of more primitive conditions, and then out of this capitalism
There was alit was assumed revolution itself would spring.
ways the contest between those who were producing and the
masses of the community; and this had expressed itself in continued opposition, contradictions. And what the dialectical materialism, as it was termed, attempted to say was that this
process was one in which there had been conflicts of opposites
with the appearance of a synthesis in which, for the time being,
and such that the final conwould take
which capitalism as such would be
these opposites were harmonized,
flict,
so to speak, from the economic standpoint
place in a shift of emphasis in
abrogated and state control come
One
in.
can, of course, point to the seeming failures of the
Marxian
There has been
keeping economic processes going.
The Russians seem to have made enormous concessions to pristate in Russia at the present time.
great difficulty
there in
vate capital in order to keep their industries going. As
stated,
Marxian doctrine, which is very definitely economic dogma
pushed into the Hegelian dialectic, gradually lost its hold
throughout Europe and in our two great industrial communities, Germany and England.
In Germany there was the Sozialdemokratische Arbeiterpartei that was inspired by the
Marxian doctrine; and under the leadership of Bebel and those
the
THOUGHT
who
followed
him
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
it still
maintained the Marxian doctrine and
looked forward to revolution; it still played the part of the protest party, one that refused to accept the operation of the government under then present conditions, one that was waiting for
a socialistic government.
votion to the Marxian
socialism in
As
have already pointed out,
dogma waned
this de-
in the later history of
Germany. There grew up an opportunistic move-
ment, gathering pretty largely about the force of the socialist
party, to bring about various changes, reforms in the immediate
conditions. As you know, Bismarck tried to undermine socialism by introducing state insurance for those who fell sick, for
those who reached the old-age limit insurance which would
protect the laborer under conditions in which he was not able
to protect himself. Then, as I said, the socialistic part, especially in the municipalities, wished to bring about better conditions
for labor. They could only do that, of course, in so far as they
worked with other parties. This gradually became the domi-
nant element in the socialistic party. When, after the war, the
opportunity came to the Socialists, who were the majority party
in the Reichstag, of carrying out a program which they had
produced in the past, namely, that of bringing about revolution,
to
they became a relatively conservative party, unwilling
put control of industry into the hands of the bureaucratic
state.
In English history socialism had been of a different character.
The Marxian
doctrine, although formulated in
England
never took hold of the English laborer in the early days.
In fact, in one sense it has not in the present day. Labor in
England never looked forward to revolution as such. In England the laborer fought for better conditions and better wages,
itself,
but his weapon has been the trade-union and not a socialistic party looking toward the reconstruction of the state itThe conditions preceding the war, and those following
self.
it, increased the representatives of the Labor party in ParHa-
ment, so that it became the second largest party. The Liberal
party lost largely to the Labor party and to the Conservative
[234]
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
party, so that the two parties that stood over against each other
were the Conservative and the Labor parties. This development of the Labor party centered about a program which was
worked out really by the Fabian socialists, the Webbs. Sidney
and Beatrice Webb were the ones who very largely drew it up,
but there were others involved in it. It was a program that
looked toward the various socialistic types of industries, those
in which competition is eliminated by the nature of the indus-
A public utility is successful only in
try itself.
competitors.
You cannot have
peting with each other and
the
same
petition
is
still
so far as
it
com-
have successful operation.
And
Com-
true, of course, of other so-called "utilities."
the breath of
has no place
life
dox system
has no
several telephone systems
from the point of view of the orthothere. It
is
necessary, in the case of
such social industries, that there should be public control; and
is
perfectly possible to have public
It is possible,
manager.
It
management
it
in these cases.
conceivably at least, for a state to pick out a good
may
be a question whether
it
can select a success-
entrepreneur, a person who can take capital and build up
an industry; but it ought to be possible for an intelligent government to select a good manager, and we have various illustrations
of this in government-directed business notably the postful
office,
and
in
Germany
in the
operation of the railroads as suc-
on by the government. Where you eliminate
competition, where the process of operation is one which has
already been well standardized, there it must be possible to
introduce public operation and a gradual control, through the
development of the income tax, through the distribution of
wealth in the community.
Speaking of the change which took place in the socialistic
doctrine and the orthodox economic conceptions, I have indicated that it was a change from a program to opportunism.
The term "opportunistic" does not do entire justice to the shift
in attitude. It was not simply an attitude on the part of the
thinkers of various types to reach out for any chance advantage
that might be gained. There was always behind it the assumpcessfully carried
[235]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
was some sort of method or social process that
could be found out, and therefore some sort of method that
might be adopted so that these human institutions could be
adjusted to this process; that is, that there might be laws
tion that there
which,
if
discovered, could be used to control social events.
The
assumption of the economic doctrine had been that certain
had been discovered which are
involved in the economic process, and that the only thing
one could do was to accept them and act in accordance with
them; that if one undertook to contravene them he got himself
into difficulties. It was like refusing to obey the law of gravitation. One must obey in order to control.
What generally came out of the struggle, however, was a
gradual recognition that these laws did not have the form which
an earlier economic doctrine had given to them. That doctrine
led logically to the conclusions which Karl Marx drew from
them. That is, if one were to accept not only the laws of supply
and demand, those which control the price of things in the markets of the world, but accept also the process of competition, and
the Malthusian law, the results which Marx drew from them
were logical. However, out of the labor-union movement in
England and in this country, out of the processes which were
responsible for these movements, it was found that the price
of labor could be influenced by other considerations than those
of supply and demand, that it was possible to increase the price
of labor above a subsistence level. What had been overlooked
in the Marxian assumption was the greater productivity of
labor. It had also overlooked the various social conditions that
determine the fixing of the wage. Taking the laws of these first,
it was found that in the struggle between the labor unions and
the employers, in the discussion of the conditions under which
labor operated, there could grow up a public sentiment that was
effective in determining the price of labor, or at least that had
an influential part in determining the price of labor. Also, it
was slowly discovered that a wage which made possible mere
subsistence and which kept the laborers on the verge of starvafirst
so-called "iron laws" of nature
^36
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
was not a wage which produced the highest
not an economic wage.
tion
The
abstract doctrine
man was Hke
we have been speaking
a machine:
results;
it
was
of assumed that
he could be bought and then he
would operate; but he could operate only on the basis of a subsistence which he obtained in exchange for his labor, and which,
if inadequate, would render his performance inadequate also.
There were evidences of a social sort, of a physiological sort,
which entered into the determination of the wage which were
not presented in the first formulation of the economic doctrine
in question.
grew up a recognition that Malhad not the necessary operation which was supposed to belong to it. In the first place, there was evidence
which was to be found in France that population could be held
down, that, actually, increase did not take place in accordance
with the Malthusian law; and gradually in England itself there
grew up evidence that there was what has later come to be
called "birth control," which determines to considerable degree
Then,
too, there gradually
thus' law itself
the increase of population.
That
is,
the
human
race does not
necessarily oversupply the world as forms lower than
method
for the control of
it
do. Its
population was of a different sort than
that which exists in lower forms.
Man
himself could determine
was found that the sohave uniformity which belongs to a
so-called "law of nature," and men went back to the study
of human conditions, to study the process of production and
distribution, the economic process; and, as this investigation was
undertaken, it was found that the situations were very complex.
One result of this was the discovery of something of the same
assumption that belonged to the Hegelian doctrine, namely,
that the state had a higher intelligence than the individual.
Indeed, something of this sort was more or less implied. Why
should one assume that a bureaucratic state would be more
successful in the process of production than individual entrethe actual increase.
In other words,
it
called "iron laws" did not
preneurs?
One found, of course,
in industry that a large
[237I
number
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
of capitalistic undertakings failed where very few succeeded.
It was computed that something like ninety-odd per cent of
It was this, of
which led to the assumption that capital would flow
into the hands of those who were successful. Why should it be
assumed that the state in a bureaucratic fashion would be able
to draft ability which would enable it to carry on these industries successfully? Great industries have to work on a very
narrow margin if they work in accordance with economic laws,
and the Marxian doctrine was orthodox in its acceptance of
these laws. Something like a 5 per cent margin is what separates
a great industry from success or failure. It is always, so to
speak, near the edge always has to maintain itself by a careful consideration of its conditions and the situation within which
it operates, and on the basis of which it can succeed. As I said,
the assumption that the state could take over such a difficult
undertaking as the management of great industries and make
them successful, is an assumption that implies that the state
is going to control powers and capacities which it is very difficult
to secure under private management. The person who succeeds
is one who is selected out by a sort of process of competition, and
it is very difficult to determine from consideration of the individual whether he will succeed or not. There is something of an
capitahstic undertakings were not successful.
course,
implication that the state as such has a higher intelligence than
the individual, if we assume that this industrial state is going
to be economically successful in its processes.
This type of program was, as
have suggested,
socialistic in
was
became
character, but evolutionary rather than revolutionary. It
the sort
of program which the Labor party put up.
socialistic in the sense that it
It
looked to the state to take over
production, but has never been socialistic in the sense of
ing socialism a religion.
a religion, had been in
The Marxian
Germany and
mak-
doctrine was essentially
elsewhere in Europe, as
That is,
is at present among the communists in Russia.
was conceived of essentially as an expression of the inteUigence of the community. What this sociahstic doctrine has
it
it
[238]
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
implied
is
that the economic process
is the dominant process of
dominant process of the comcontrolled by the intelligence of the community, that
the community, and that this
munity
if this
is
process
is
developed to the proper level the community
over it. The religious life is essential-
will naturally take control
whole group to which he
which the individual is subordinated to
ly a life of the individual in that of the
belongs, that
is,
in
the group, in which the individual realizes himself in the
of the community.
The
socialist doctrine, then,
sense a religious doctrine. It conceived of the
life
was
in
life
this
of the com-
economic process. The individual was
Revolution. The control of the process was to pass into the hands
of the community, in which the individual was the essential
part. That is, the individual through the part which he played
munity
as essentially an
realized in this great social process through the Industrial
in the various labor organizations, industrial organizations,
the fundamental element in the state.
ing himself in the
life
And
was
the individual, realiz-
of the community, had definitely a religious
attitude toward the process
In other words, you can find
itself.
a parallelism between the statement of religion and the Hegelian state, the state being nearer to
in the
God than
the individual
community, the individual subordinating himself
to the
state as a higher expression of spirit. This attitude, being of a
on the socialist side, expressed as an
economic process which is the essential life of the community,
and it is in so far as the individual, in his relationship to this
economic organization, subordinates himself to its highest expression in the state that he gets a realization of himself in the
group to which he belongs. That is, he gets essentially a rereligious character, was,
ligious attitude.
Now
one which you do not find in the English
has in some sense become. Fabian
socialism is not a religious movement. It is one which looks
toward the meeting of all sorts of evils found in the industrial
communities by governmental action of different sorts. It feels
this attitude
Labor party,
is
socialistic as it
free to use the
government
in industrial situations as
[
239
much
as
THOUGHT
it is
used
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
in political situations,
and
in policing situations that
arise. The government can be utilized by the community to
meet economic conditions and to better these conditions. But
it does not assume that the economic process is the process in
which the intelligence of the community as such expressed itself necessarily. The development of socialism in England is,
in a certain sense, parallel with the development which took
place in Germany in the passage of dogmatic socialism into opportunistic socialism one wiUing and desirous of utilizing the
powers of the state to bring about better conditions for labor
without endeavoring to state just what the organization of
society was going to be. The earlier sociaHsts proceeded as if
they had had a vision on the Mount which showed them what
the order of society should be. They felt they could work out
deductively what the order should be. It was that which they
held before themselves, waiting to bring about this great change
which, when the evolution of conditions had reached the proper
point, could be carried through. In place of this we have in England a type of socialism which felt itself free to utilize the state
in a fashion it assumed to be legitimate.
The old doctrine called off the hand of the state from industry. Adam Smith called for the abandonment of monopolies
which the state had allowed to grow up, the giving-way of
tariff,
the opening of doors, the taking-off of political control of
industry, allowing industry to proceed with
is still
the doctrine in the orthodox school.
its
own
As over
laws.
That
against this
development which has been taking place
not only in industrial Europe but also in America. Our Interstate Commerce Commission, for example, as I have already
mentioned in passing, is an expression of government in which
you have the
sort of
the control of industrial conditions, specifically the determina-
under which transportation is
hands of the state. We have established
other bureaus along the same lines, although they have not developed to the same extent or had the importance which the
Interstate Commerce Commission has. We have been behind
tion of rates, of the conditions
to take place,
is
in the
[240]
KARL MARX AND SOCIALISM
England
development of governmental control over public utilities.
We proceed very slowly in this country as compared with England and Germany, the reason presumably
being found in the fact that our local governments are more
corrupt than local governments in England have been, so that
the community has been wary of introducing an opportunity for
the government control of great public utilities. For example,
in Chicago there was a time during which public sentiment
in the community as a whole was, by and large, for public
ownership of the transit system. At the present time sentiment
is active on quite the other side. The lack of confidence in our
municipal institutions as they are organized and conducted by
in the
our present politicians
is
such as to
make
the
community
hesi-
tate to turn over operations of great public utilities to them,
and so
this
type of development of public control has advanced
much more slowly in this country that it has in Europe.
The movement, however, is one whose general lines I have
very
sketched.
We
have
somewhat sensational uncarry out the Marxian program,
at this time the
dertaking in Russia to actually
the setting-up of a Marxian system as
final,
or an attempt to
I have said,
very unsatisfactory results from the industrial standpoint, at
least up to the present time. Of course, there is a certain absurd-
through in
carry
it
ity in
undertaking to carry out Marx's doctrine
its detail,
with, of course, as
a doctrine gathers about the proletariat
in Russia. Such
composed mainly of
factory laborers. Socialism has never been able to get hold of
and 90 per cent of the laborers in Russia are
peasants, those living upon the soil. The Communist-Socialist
government has had to give way before the peasantry and turn
over control of the soil to the person who is, to all intents and
purposes, the owner of the soil which he cultivates. The place
in which to undertake an experiment such as is being carried out
in Russia would be in Germany or in England, great industrial
communities in which you have a large and relatively highly
intelligent proletariat in a socialistic sense, men who have had
training of a poHtical sort such as the socialists have had in the
agricultural labor,
[241]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Social-Democratic party in Germany, and such as the EngHsh
But what was clearly evident after the
had things in its own hands in Germany,
was an entire unwillingness to undertake any such experiment;
and, of course, the same thing is true in England. Laborers as
such were quite unwilling to undertake any revolutionary
process, any turning-over of the industry of the community to
control by the state, with the consequence that there has been
laborers are getting.
war,
when
socialism
a serious slowing-up,
if
not actual discounting, of the effective-
ness of such a program.
242]
CHAPTER
XII
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE MECHANISM
THE HANDMAID OF FINALITY
THE
economic organization of society which we have
in the so-called Industrial Revolution
has been the source out of which some of the most important of our scientific conceptions and hypotheses have
arisen. The conception of energy is illustrative of this. This
been discussing
conception was definitely revolutionary in modern science beit brought together fields which could not be stated in
terms of a mechanical science. Newton's statement was taken
from the heavens and, of course, was a generalization of Gali-
cause
law of the falling body fused with the observations of
Kepler and others, Newton gave a statement of the solar system in terms of attraction, that is, of the movement of masses
with reference to each other; and he gave the laws for this solar
system. Then this system was carried to earth again and was
made the basis for the study of the phenomena that take place
about us. It was very fruitful in a field in which you could
locate actual masses, but people tried to carry over the conception into fields in which they could not actually locate the
different masses on account of the minuteness of the bodies.
What they wanted to do was to apply the simple law of Newton's statement to other physical processes.
For example, take such a process as heat, that is, of molecular
bodies moving at great velocities with reference to one another.
They are beyond the range of our observation. You cannot take
that problem and carry it over into the phenomena, because you
cannot get a statement of the positions of the bodies that will
enable you to work the law out. There were various uniformities which science could locate. Again, take the phenomenon of
leo's
[243]
THOUGHT
Here
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
which could be determined. How were these different phenomena to be brought into
relationship with each other? They could not be stated simply
in terms of the movement of masses with reference to each other
as Newton could state the movement of planetary bodies, and
yet they must be made into a necessary idea. That is, you can
electricity.
also are uniformities
say how much work will be done, how much work is involved in
doing this or that thing, and yet not know how the atoms or particular masses are moving with reference to others. All we can
determine is just how much work is done in one situation and
how much
is done in another. Then we have a basis for determining proportionate amounts of energy. We can look at the
whole process from the standpoint of energies, from the standpoint of the amount of work done, and not try to determine just
what the positions of all the physical particles are in their movements in relation to one another. Such an undertaking goes
beyond our vision. But you can still say that energy is expended; you can still say how much work is involved in bringing
about a certain situation, and how much can be developed.
The economist turns to the scientist and wants a theory for
his new servant, the steam engine. He says, "I want to know
how much work it can do." So the scientist takes the unit of
work and discovers the amount of energy. That is, he finds that
the machine can be depended upon for a certain number of units
of work done. Thus, in the physical world you can say that
energy is a bookkeeping conception. It takes electricity and
light, coal, expansive steam, and the revolving dynamo, and sets
up a certain unit by means of which it is able to put them all into
the same class, just as the economist takes all sorts of different
and
objects ^the machinery, the soil, the plant, the workers
sets them all together, states them in terms of the amount of
labor necessary to get a given commodity. Work or energy,
then,
is
a bookkeeping conception taken over from the economic
doctrine, just as
have said the conception of the survival of
the fittest in the competition for existence
Darwin from the economic
is
situation presented
[244]
taken over by
by Ricardo and
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
in the form of the hypothesis of evoluvery interesting to see the sources from which im-
Malthus and generalized
tion.
It is
portantly constructive ideas have arisen, to see what an organic
thing society is; how ideas that you find in one phase of it appear in some different form in another phase, but come back to
common
sources.
The conception
of energy, then, comes from the
The
theory of the steam engine.
demand
for a
thing about the steam engine
that interested people was exactly the amount of work that it
would do. The steam engine took the place of human arms. It
was more effective and more reliable. It did the work that laborers had done, and enabled the entrepreneur to make the work
of the laborer still more productive. Work in the form of labor,
of course, was an essential part of the economic doctrine. The
cost of production, which was essential to the conclusions of the
Manchester school, always came back to labor. The price of
anything could be given
in
amount of work necessary
to
terms of labor, in terms of the
produce it. Labor became a uni-
Labor was generalized in the
terms of which the cost of any
versal element in this equation.
economic equation as that
in
particular article could be assessed.
Of
course, the success of
economic production was dependent on making this cost less
than the price. But in order to make your business a paying
one, you have to make a statement of the actual cost of your
production. And the ultimate element you come back to is
stated in terms of labor. That played a very large part in the
doctrine of political economy at that time. What was wanted
was a statement in terms of labor of everything that was being
done. The unit of labor really comes out of the economic doctrine. It is a bookkeeping term. You have to set up an equation
in regard to the process as a whole; you have to make your cost
of production no greater than the price you can get for your
article; and you have to state the cost of production in terms of
labor. Well now, if you are introducing machinery, you must
be able to state what the machine does in terms of the amount
of work accomplished. The unit was presented to science by
[245]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
economy, and the conception of labor had the same
work had. Take any object that is to be estimated in terms of manufacture and you
can state the whole cost of it in terms of labor. For example, if
you want to know the value of food, it comes back to the labor
that has to be expended on the ground. You can put the value
into terms of the amount of work done, the unit of which arises
out of the economic situation.
This conception led to the setting-up of a certain metaphysics, to a theory of energy which Ostwald, a German chemist, proposed, in which energy was regarded as being the ultipolitical
transferability that the conception of
mate element. He tried to get rid of the conception of atomic
particles. With this in mind he wrote an elementary chemistry
in which he did do away with atoms entirely. Instead of talking
about the union of two portions of hydrogen with one of oxygen,
instead of talking about a certain number of atoms to be
brought into relation with each other in chemical combinations,
he simply stated the amounts in such terms as, "Take twice as
much of one as of the other," and up to a certain point he was
able to work out an adequate statement on these terms which
got rid of atoms. He simply stated the amounts in terms of
quantities. But he could not get beyond that point. In fact,
the so-called "carbon chemistry," which sets up the idea of
molecules in which the different relative positions of identical
atoms within the molecules give rise to different organic substances, made this undertaking impossible. What this German
chemist was trying to do was to set up a certain metaphysical
entity of energy and say this is the ultimate substance in the
universe. That in itself broke down; but the history of it, which
I have briefly given, shows a very interesting development of
such a scientific concept and the interrelationship of such a conception with the social structure and social theory of the period.
Let us now bring up the other side of the life of Europe,
which we have in some sense neglected, and get a point of view
from which to interpret a good deal of what we have said by
turning back to its science. Throughout the whole of the nine[246]
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
teenth century Europe was essentially scientific in its knowledge achievements. The philosophies of the period which we
have studied, and which we will study in what follows, no longer
had the dogmatic attitude which belonged to earlier philosophies. These earlier philosophies had been, in some sense, inter-
dogma
preted along intellectual lines of the
philosophy of
element
life;
in the life
responding position.
of the church, of
its
and where the church was the dominant
of the community, philosophy had a cor-
The importance
of the church as the inter-
preter of the world, the interpreter of the lives of individuals
in
accordance with the church as giving means of life to the indi-
vidual, as a philosophy of
life
to the
man
in the street, shifted;
and another form of interpretation, the scientific, appeared and
became more and more dominant. It is true that in some sense
in the back of the mind of these generations Hes a plan of salvation presented in such form as that of Milton's Samson
Agonistes. That remains as a sort of pattern for the interpretation of the world, that
is,
the idea that there
is
some
sort of
moral purpose which underlies the whole order of the universe,
and that this great moral purpose finds particular expression
in the life of man and in the history of man, and that, while it
may be impossible, as it was earlier assumed, to take the history
of that process as given in the chapters of Genesis and throughout the Bible as the single strand upon which everything is to
be strung, it is still true that the moral purpose presented in the
doctrine of the church itself is still, in some sense, regarded as
identical with the purpose of the universe and that, if one is
right with God, he is in line with the natural development of
things about him. Some such feeling of the moral identity of
human history with that of the universe is a conception which
has come over from the ecclesiastical and doctrinal statements
of the church, and it still plays an important part in our view
of the world. In the form in which
it
was given by the church,
the literal statement of that was relatively simple:
man
sinned;
he came under the condemnation of God; he was saved by the
sacrifice of Christ.
[247]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
In the past there has been the otherworldliness of the great
rehgions. It has been in relationship to the world to come, that
is,
in relationship to social ideals that could
this world, that
men have been
not be achieved in
able to get together.
The
gospel
of Jesus presents a picture of a society in which the interests of
one are the interests of
members of
all,
in
which
all
regard themselves as
an ideal which has never, of
and which never
can be, things remaining what they have been in the past.
Single groups living on that basis during the medieval period
a single family. It
is
course, been realized on the face of the earth,
Men gave up property, famiwhich there should be that sort of
identity of interest in this world. Such a society belongs in a
New Jerusalem. But men still kept this ideal, although they
might differ in all sorts of other things even though they might
constantly be at war with one another. The salvation of the
individual soul was wrapped up in the good of the whole community, and this idea was inevitably that of another world.
Such a statement as this is, however, quite inconsistent with
the one which science gives. Nevertheless, for years the two
statements went along without coming into necessary conflict.
I have already indicated the independent position of science in
the modern world. In a certain sense the Renaissance scientist
took up the study of matter and motion as a field which led outside the immediate social interests and ecclesiastic interests of
the community. From the point of view of the church God had
created the world out of nothing to serve as the field in which
would be enacted the drama of man's fall and salvation. Science could make its investigation without coming into conflict
with the doctrine of the church. It was to be assumed that an
infinitely wise God would work by means of uniform laws; that
he would have the ability and the interest of a supreme
mathematician. Thus science might find the way in which God
operates in the world without finding out his purposes. When,
however, the science which dealt with matter, the science of
Galileo, and especially his dynamics, which said that matter is
had
ly
to be organized into cloisters.
life,
to reach a situation in
[248I
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
nothing but inertia mass as revealed in inertia when this science went on into the fields of biology, for example, the going
became more
ence which
is
difficult.
infinitely
was difficult because biology is
more complex than mechanics.
It
a sciIf bi-
ology is to be reduced to mechanics, it is necessary to carry one's
view into very complex situations. Still it is possible to conceive of plants, of animals, and of a physiological mind as
mechanical, and thus they could be understood, in terms of
what x^ristotle would have called an "efficient cause," as over
against a final cause, a form of understanding which had
proved itself of immense importance. Aristotle never realized
that by obeying nature one might control it by discovering uniform laws. From the time of the Renaissance on, the Western
world was controlling nature and using its forces by very competent investigation of its laws and a complete willingness to
obey those laws in carrying out its own purposes, so that a
nature that seemed to be outside the ends and the purposes
of the creator of the world became more and more important
to society. A science which seemed to have abandoned and to
have carefully kept itself from theological inquiry in regard to
the meaning of the world was coming in by the back door, and,
by studying the mechanical order of things, was getting more
control of nature and bringing about tremendous changes and
becoming more and more important in man's mind. It continually rendered this type of explanation more and more attractive
an explanation from the statement of the efficient
cause, from cause and effect and the uniform laws of nature,
as over against an explanation from the point of view of final
cause, of end, of purpose. Which form of explanation shall we
take? Why is the world here? Why are we here? Why should
we suffer, be restricted here and there? What is the end that
explains all? That earlier, teleological form of explanation was
set over against another form which undertakes to show how
things have happened, and why, because certain things have
happened in a given way, other things must necessarily follow.
That is a science of physical necessity, but one which did not
[249]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
it necessity in so far as the conduct of man was conhave said that one gets control over nature by obeying
it. You find out how things must happen, and then you can use
things that happen in a necessary way to bring about your results. This very separation of mass, of the mechanical process
from other processes, psychological and social among others, left
people, in some sense, free to utilize these very social purposes.
What I want to bring out is that, while there had been a sort
of theological inquiry that is still perhaps present in man's
mind as to whether men are free or not, and questions of freedom of the will may still be discussed under sophomoric conditions, the necessity which science presents had not, as yet,
carry with
cerned.
carried with
it
control over
human
initiative.
The more
neces-
sary the statement of natural sciences can be made, the greater
freedom man has in reconstructing, in bringing about changes
in, his environment.
This paradox is of very great importance in our understanding of the position of science in the Western world. Of course,
if, with Laplace, you say that everything that takes place is
simply a shift of physical particles moving in accordance with
absolute law, then you can conceivably have an equation in
which you have only to introduce the variables, including time,
and you can determine the position of the moon with reference
to the earth and sun, and so determine eclipses. You can conceivably get equations which can determine the whole solar and
stellar system. Increase its generality, and all you have to do
is to introduce the variable time and you can tell just where
every physical particle will be at any possible moment in the
future as well as in the past. Seemingly, the whole world would
be absolutely fixed and determined. That is a conceivable statement of this mechanical science. But what I am pointing out is
that the science which gave this sort of a view of the world is
the science which was enabling human initiative to reconstruct
its world entirely and, through the reconstruction of his environment, enabling man to make an entirely different society. You
get this paradox: a statement of the mechanical nature of
[250]
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
everything, one which seems to include
man
also,
which, at the
same time, gives man greater control over his environment,
greater freedom of action, and allows him to set up social objectives.
Man
sum
of
is
all
a physical
and
cording to the statement
What he
make him
biological organism.
the physical particles that go to
we
are
now
considering,
if
is is
the
up. Ac-
you can de-
termine where those particles are, you can determine just what
he will say and think. Such a doctrine gives you absolute neces-
working out as complete a meyou get one which gives man
a more complete freedom than he ever had in the past. The
best statement that you can get of the development of science
throughout this period, but especially during the early part, is
to be found in Merz's History of European Thought in the Nine-
sity in everything;
and
chanical statement as
is
yet, in
possible,
teenth Century.
The Newtonian
doctrine presented a picture of an orderly,
mechanical universe, one governed by mechanical laws, a universe of masses in motion. The laws of these motions in their
simplest forms could be given. The changes that took place,
if in
a sufficiently simple situation, could also be traced out.
The method of analysis which grew out of the work of Leibnitz
and Newton that of an infinitesimal calculus sought always
to take as simple a situation as possible; and, if a sufficiently
was discovered that the laws
of change could be determined. The picture, then, which was
presented of the physical universe was of one which was in motion, and in motion in accordance with simple laws, and that
which moved was mass. There were, of course, many features of
the physical universe which could not be brought under terms of
mass; but it was assumed, or at least hoped, that something
of this kind could be worked out, that such a mechanical statement of things could be made universal. The picture which Laplace presented was of an equation which could determine where
all the physical particles of the universe would be at any one
moment if you simply introduced the variable of time. Such a
simple situation could be found,
it
[251]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
was what men had before them. So far as they could get
into the intricate movements of things, the molecular movements of things, the laws seemed to hold. It was, then, to be
assumed that such physical laws as these operated throughout
nature, and that the whole of nature could be regarded in terms
simply of masses in motion and could be brought under as
rigorous laws as those which science had already discovered.
There was, however, the biological field which seemed to
picture
The importance
to open the
that
seemed
hypothesis
was
it
Darwinian
of the
door to a natural law in the development of physical forms. If
such a hypothesis could be accepted, the changes that took
place in animate nature would be due to causes operating from
behind, causes which were a posteriori. That is, you would not
have to assume a certain nature in plant or animal which determined its growth, but that causes were operating, or rather
had been operating, which brought about results here as in inorganic nature. Of course, men had discovered many parts of
the process of life which could be stated in physical and mechanical terms. Certain of the so-called "organic products" had
been produced artificially in the laboratory. It was perfectly
conceivable that changes which took place in living forms were
simply physical and mechanical changes, that men and animals
and plants were, as Descartes had guessed, nothing but machines so far as the life-processes were concerned.
Now Darwin's hypothesis came in to indicate how particular
forms might arise. All it asked for was indefinite variation on
the part of young forms, that every young form should vary in
some respect from the parent form. Then it asked that there
should be competition for life which should be sufficiently
strenuous that only the form best adapted to survive would survive. What Darwin pointed out was what had been suggested
in Malthus' doctrine, namely, that there were always more
young forms arising in nature than could possibly survive.
There must then be competition between these forms, and those
among them which were less fitted to survive under the condioffer resistance to the entrance of physical law.
[252]
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
which they found themselves would inevitably disapGiven this indefinite variation, one could fairly assume
that when the difference in the form answered to changes in the
environment a new form would arise which, under this competition, would maintain itself while all other forms would disappear. In this way Darwin undertook to explain the appearance
of species. Back of it, as I have pointed out, was the recognitions in
pear.
tion of a
more or
less identical life-process in all
forms.
The
form of the plant or animal was the adjustment of
this life-process to a particular environment. Suppose, now,
that this environment changes; there must be a corresponding
change on the part of the animal form if it is to survive. If we
grant these indefinite variations, we may assume that through
them some forms will be better able to adjust themselves to new
conditions, and so new forms may arise.
Here, you see, you have simply variations from behind, indefinite variations due to the very processes of reproduction.
Given the changes which are taking place in the environment as
biological
a result of geologic and climatic influences,
it is
possible to ac-
development of plant and animal forms in mechanical terms. One could, in this way, get a picture of a
mechanical universe which was governed by absolute laws
which determined where all physical particles would be and
therefore what all the physical things would be and everything
that they would be doing, and, finally, every change that took
place. It was a picture of such a complete universe as this, with
count
its
for the
fixed laws, that
is,
in a certain sense, a
counterpart of the
picture of a fixed order of society which grew out of the
Man-
was formulated by Karl Marx as the basis
for his socialist doctrine. Both of them belonged to their period.
The physical doctrine went somewhat the way of the economic doctrine. In the first place, there were, as I have already
indicated, fields of experience, of nature, which could not be
chester doctrine and
brought under the terms of masses in motion. Light, for
example, presented serious difiiculties. It was recognized as answering to some sort of wave process. The corpuscular theory,
[253]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
which Newton accepted, had been abandoned for the time being
(though it now seems to be coming back in one form in the
quantum theory); and some sort of a wave theory was found
phenomena of Hght. Well,
if light is a wave, it must presumably be a wave of something.
Sound could be resolved if we noted waves of air. One could
to be best to account for the various
follow the
waves on the ocean,
theories of light
made
in the water; and, in fact, the
wave motion as they
and gases. The assumption
use of the laws of
could be investigated in liquids
naturally was, then, that there was something in motion, some-
thing answering to these so-called "waves" of Hght. It was
called "ether." The term is one which goes back to old Greek
meaning there. This
phenomenon so far
as known at that time. It was a substance that science set up
ad hoc for a particular purpose. The waves were not discovered
in the moving ether, but the mathematics of wave motion was
one which best answered to the phenomenon of light. So ether
was set up as something within which the waves might occur.
When it was set up, however, it had to be fitted into the
physical doctrine of the time. If it was a substance, it itself
presumably moved. If all the planetary bodies were moving
through it and the stars as well, it ought to respond to their
motion. If you set up a body moving through water, you not
only cause waves but affect the motion of the body itself. This
is true of all known liquids and gases. But no measurements
made have ever indicated any retardation of the motion of the
heavenly bodies on account of the friction of the ether. There
was no evidence which could be found of this ether being
speculation, though
it
had a
different
ether did not exhibit itself in any other
dragged along except, perhaps, in one instance. In studying the
velocity of light passing through a moving liquid, it was found
that its velocity was somewhat reduced; and at that time the
assumption that could be made for the reduction was that
was being swept along with the moving water to some
But
apart from that, no evidence was found that ether
degree.
was carried along with the earth which was supposed to be
first
the ether
[254I
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
passing through
it.
Of
course,
if it
were,
it
would
affect the
hne
of light coming from the stars and should lead to a displacement
of their visual position. But no such displacement could be
found, so
it
was very
difficult to place
ether in the mechanical
theory of the universe. It was thought of as a something that
moved; but if it was a something, it ought to have inertia and
ought to exhibit itself in responses which it offered to bodies
moving through it, responses in the form of resistance. And
It could not very well be defined. When
it did not do that.
men came to define the waves which arose in, or traveled
through, this suppositious ether, they found that they had to
define the ether itself; and they got some very strange definitions. It was perfectly elastic, and yet how could you have such
a body as that and fit it into any of the physical theories of the
time.^ Thus it is seen that ether presented a very serious difficulty in the field of the physical sciences.
phenomenon of electromagnetism. Of course
electricity, in one form or another, had been known for an indefinite period. But it was only to some degree in the seven-
Then came
the
teenth, mainly in the eighteenth century, and in the nineteenth
that any scientific study of
was made. This study revealed
a phenomenon that approached light in its form. Maxwell
proceeded to deal with ether itself in terms which brought light
and electricity into the same field. Hertz carried these speculations through and put them to experimental tests and showed
that the electrical wave was of a type similar to the light wave.
Then, of course, the field of electricity became one of the most
exciting fields of scientific investigation. There were, however,
various anomalies in it too: first, one in regard to ether, and a
it
further one, in that the element to which one could reduce
under certain conditions was atomic in character.
men came back to ultimate elements,
those out of which the electron has arisen. That is, you have a
statement of electricity in terms of waves and also in terms of
ultimate particles, bits of electrical jelly of some sort which act
like physical particles under some conditions. IMen found them-
electricity
In further investigations
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
selves driven to these different statements of electricity to account for various aspects of the total behavior of electrical
phenomena. I have said later investigation has carried this
same opposition within light itself. Certain phases of light,
brought out by the quantum theory, are dealt with from the
standpoint of ultimate elements; others, from the point of view
of the wave theory.
In other words, within physical theory
itself,
apart from ani-
was breaking down. The laws of
Newton within the world of mass and motion were invariable.
mate
life,
the rigid doctrine
They could be applied under all conditions, so far
be stated. The laws which Maxwell worked out
as they could
for light
and
electromagnetism were found not to be invariable. Problems
and difficulties of a serious character arose, then, in pushing
the scientific theory into this
new
field.
There was a
field in
which there seemed to be an operation of fixed laws, those of
masses in motion. But a part of this field was that which had
to do with the phenomena of light, electromagnetism, and electrons; and these were not amenable to those laws. What a few
scientists undertook to do was to work out what changes would
have to be made in the formulas of science if this variability of
Maxwell's laws was to be maintained, and they reached rather
astonishing results. One result was that the elements of time
and space, the unit of measurement, would have to be changed
as the velocity of the moving body changed. It was not advanced as a physical theory. It was simply the bringing-out of
a mathematical theory which did apply to the measurement and
investigation of electromagnetic and light phenomena. If these
mathematical statements were worked out, a point was finally
reached where the units of space and time had to be changed.
From the point of view of a certain moving object, the units of
length and of time would have difl-'erent values from what they
would have with respect to some other object at rest, or moving
with a different velocity.
I
want
to call
your attention especially to
this.
It
was some-
thing that grew up, in a certain sense, earlier than the doctrine
[256]
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
itself. It grew out of the necessity of giving a
mathematical statement to phenomena discovered in the fields
of light and electromagnetism. In order to give a satisfactory
mathematical statement to this, the scientists found themselves
giving a different value to the units of space and time in accordance with the velocity with which the body was moving. The
Michelson and Morley experiment had been before the world
for some time. What Michelson and his colleague had undertaken to do was to show evidence of an ether through which the
earth was moving. They undertook this by means of a relative-
of relativity
simple experiment. Of course, if light is moving along
through an ether, you can also conceive of the ether as moving
in the other direction from that of the light swimming through
it. Now, set one beam of light moving through it in the direcly
tion of flow
and another beam of
light
moving
to that direction, as in the situation of
one
at right angles
man
rowing up-
stream against the current and another man rowing across the
stream. Take the distance each would cover in a given time.
The man rowing upstream could not row as far as the man
rowing across. Thus, in the Michelson-Morley experiment it
was expected that this same difference would be found; but it
was
not,
made
and
this negative result disturbed people. Fitzgerald
the suggestion that this result would be
met
if
we could
conceive of the earth as shortened in the diameter which was in
same direction as that of the motion. That is, if the earth is
moving in a certain direction, we can conceive of the diameter
of the earth which hes in the direction of this motion as being
shortened. If we found the diameter was eight inches shorter
in that direction, then this Michelson-Morley experiment would
be exactly accounted for. As you can see, the required changes
the
are very minute.
able
if
And
the thing
you think of matter
character.
What
is,
perhaps, not so inconceiv-
itself as
being electromagnetic in
Fitzgerald did was simply to figure out
what
the shortening of the earth would be in the direction of the
motion of the body itself, and he found that this shortening
would be very minute. Then came the discovery that the mathe[257]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
matical statement which had been given to these so-called
"measurements" of space and time fitted exactly into this
shortening of the body in the direction of
exactly agreed.
And
its
motion.
The two
that was the statement which gave the
basis for Einstein's statement of relativity.
What
lines
have
tried to
do has been to point out that we have
of development here which had been going on inside of
the physical theory
itself.
Relativity
is
a statement that has
grown up in the midst of it, not something that has been put
down upon a physical doctrine from the outside. It is a natural
development within the theory itself. It has been changing.
Here, again, we have a parallelism between the physical theory
and the economic theory. You start off with the assumption of
certain fixed laws which operate in nature, or in production and
distribution. Then you undertake to build up a theory of the
universe or of society on the basis of these, and you find that
there are various things that happen that do not fit in, and you
have to reconstruct your theory to deal with these situations.
The same thing, in a sense, happened in physical theory that
happened in economic theory.
Back of this development of science lies the vast difference
between a research science and any dogmatic statement of the
world. If you say within any science, "This is the way the
world is to be explained, and inside these limits you can carry
on your investigations, but you must not carry your problemseeking beyond them," the scientist is up in arms at once. He
problems anywhere. He insists
that he can set up any postulate which will enable him to solve
his problems, and that that is the only test that can be brought
in, the only criticism that can be made. Science is tested by the
success of its postulates. It brings its hypotheses to the test of
experience itself; and if this test is met, then the doctrine is one
to be accepted until some flaw can be found in it, until some
new problem arises within it. There is, then, an inevitable conflict between a view of the world which is dogmatic and the
method used by science. Any dogmatic theory of the world is
insists that science
can find
its
[158]
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
found to be
in
conflict
with the
scientific
method.
On
the
we must not assume that because science makes
postulates it is itself dogmatic. Of course, that is the charge
very frequently and very unjustly made against science. Beother hand,
cause science sets up such a postulate as that of the possible
mechanical statement of what goes on in the world, it is accused of setting up a dogma. But it simply says that, if we start
off with the mechanical process in explaining digestion, for example,
we
not do
this,
we
fail,
will try to carry it
we
through
in this fashion.
If
we can-
another explanation. But until
we are justified in setting up such a postulate. The
will try to find
postulates of science are not dogmas; and as long as science
problems in this fashion, it is
entirely justified in setting up such postulates. It is very important that we should realize the difference between a dogmatic
science and a research science, between dogma and postulate.
We should realize what is meant by the demand for scientific
freedom: that every problem that arises may be freely attacked
by the scientist; that he is justified in setting up any postulate
which will enable him to solve that problem; and that the only
can pursue the solution of
its
which shall be made is the success of his solution as determined by actual experience itself.
Now, science, with its demand for freedom, is the outstanding fact not simply of the nineteenth century but of all thought
since the Renaissance, for modern science brought in the
Renaissance itself. A definite method was introduced at that
time. Galileo in his study of falling bodies gives a classic
illustration of what is meant by "research science," and that
has been the method which has been applied in a wider and
wider field; and, just so far as it is brought in in any field, it has
found itself in conflict with fixed dogma. And, so far, science has
always been successful in its conflict with dogma. But we must
not assume that in this conflict science is putting up its own
dogma for the purpose of ruling out that with which it is in
conflict. Science is simply setting up postulates, and it is justified in setting them up until someone can show they are not
test
[259]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
it is perfectly ready to abandon them and to
adopt any other which will lead to the solution of the problem
in connection with which the difficulty is presented.
The mechanical doctrine which was dominant in the scientific
world of the nineteenth century was that of Newton, with its
conception of a mechanical process which could be determined
by laws of nature which presumably were inevitable and invariable. It took account only of the position of physical particles
in their relationship to each other as a whole. It did not deal
with the values which objects directly have in our experience
those of sensation, for example, color, sound, taste, and odor.
But even as important, and perhaps more important, it did
not deal with the characters which belong to living organisms.
tenable; and then
It
simply stated the relative position of
all
physical particles in
was no
and deal-
their relationship to each other. In this doctrine there
reason for cutting out certain groups of these particles
and finding in them a content,
them themselves such as is found
in all living forms. What this science did do, however, and it is
well always to keep this in mind, was to state certain fixed conditions under which these phenomena could appear. Take the
phenomenon of Hfe, for example. The physical and chemical sciences could state what the conditions are under which life as we
ing with
them
as separate objects
a meaning which belonged to
feel it, see it,
know
it
about
us,
can
arise.
gives us control over the process of
life.
In so
It
is
far,
of course,
it
a statement of a
mechanical, as over against a teleological, view of the world.
world simply to a congeries of physical particles,
atoms, and electrons; it takes all the meaning out of it. That
would be an unjust account of reality, for the development of
science has always gone hand in hand with the determination
It reduces the
of the conditions under which other characters could appear.
We
never could have had the advances which we have had in
hygiene and medicine but for the mechanical statements which
and chemistry.
are given in physics
as close as
been
we have
We
never could have got
to the life-process as a
for this physical
whole
if it
had not
and mechanical statement. From the time
[2601
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
of Bacon on, the slogan of science has been, "Knowledge is
power." That is, what we learn about nature enables us to control nature.
Or, to use another of those expressions that belong
"We can control nature only by obeying nature."
Thus, while the mechanical science seems to have presented a
world the meaning of which was all emptied out, with nothing
but physical particles and their movements remaining, it has
actually enabled us to get far greater control than we ever had
before over the conditions under which men live as biological,
psychological, and social creatures. Thus, it helped to make the
ends of social activity much clearer. It is that point to which
I wish to draw your attention especially, a point which we
must continually keep in mind. Really the mechanical science
of this period has not mechanized human conduct. Rather, it
to that period,
has given freedom.
Humanity was never
before so free in deal-
own environment as it has been since the triumphs
The ability to look at the world in terms
congeries of physical particles actually has enabled men to
ing with
its
of mechanical science.
of
determine their environment.
simple review of the conditions with reference to health, to
shows what has been accomplished in these directions
by means of scientific method. As I have already said, the food
environment is one of the greatest factors in changes which have
disease,
taken place
in the evolution of living forms.
Man
has reached
the point where he can conceivably control his food environ-
ment.
He
is,
of course, the only living form that has reached
that stage. Curiously enough,
the society of the ants
we
find small beginnings of
it
in
the beginnings of cultivation, the plant-
ing of mushrooms and other plants in their galleries, the import-
ing and conserving of certain insects which supply them with
glucose. This seems like the beginnings of
human
agriculture.
But human society has actually, or may actually, determine
what vegetation may grow about it. We cannot change the climate, but we can move about. We can get the products that
come from the various climates. We are in a position such as no
animal form has been, namely, that of controlling specifically
[261I
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the environment in which
we
live.
From
the point of view of a
Darwinian evolution the various forms have arisen very largely
through the changes that have taken place in the environment,
climatic and biologic changes, the conflicts that have arisen
among vegetable forms; and all these changes have given rise to
new species. There we have the species more or less under the
form,
But when we reach the human
we have one which determines what the environment
shall
be. It
control of the environment.
cannot, of course, plant wheat in the Sahara
Desert; but it can determine what quantity of wheat shall be
produced and where it can be grown most successfully. It can
measurably control the flow of its streams. It can, to an amazing degree, determine what are the conditions under which life
shall take place. There we reach a certain culmination in the
evolutionary process. Other forms are more or less under the
control of their environments.
and gets control over
What
it
has given
it
its
But the human form turns about
environment.
that control in the great degree in which
has been accomplished in these last three centuries has been
the scientific method, which has found
its
greatest expression in
methby
od
which the human form has turned around upon its environment and got control over it, and thus, as I have said, presented a new set of ends which control human conduct, ends
which are more universal than those which have previously
guided the conduct of the individual and of mankind as a whole
the ends, for example, and the policy of the government, of a
the so-called "mechanical science."
It is the scientific
group of governments, conceivably of the whole human race.
The human
and
It
race can determine where
trees shall
grow
there. It can
it will live,
what plants
its own population.
human stock shall be
determine
can set up a definite ideal as to what
what the production shall be. It can definitely set about
making its own habitat and living in that habitat in accordance
with ends which it can itself work out. That has been the result
of the application of scientific method. It does, in a very marked
bred,
[262I
INDUSTRY A BOON TO SCIENCE
degree, you see, alter the outlook of society. It has tended to
make
a universal science.
This carrying-over of the conceptions of the physical and
mathematical sciences into biology, the working-out of some of
the
most important phases of the
mechanical
life-process in
terms, the statement of that process from
its
beginning in the
transformation of carbonic acid gas into starch
all
the
way
through the plant and animal forms up to its final appearance
in dioxideSj is a most important part of the scientific period we
have been discussing. This statement implied, as we have seen,
that the whole process could be stated in mechanical terms or
in terms of mechanical science. The process is very intricate;
and it is not actually possible, at least it has not been up to the
present time, to follow
its
phases out
in detail.
But, beginning
with a process which could be stated mechanically, and terminating in the same, it was fair to assume that the whole process
could be so stated. Furthermore,
hypothesis
made
it
we have
seen that Darwin's
possible to deal with
the formation of
was needed for
was the hypothesis which Darwin assumed, namely, the
indefinite variation of young forms, the presence of far more
forms than could actually subsist, a condition which brought
about competition for existence. This seemed to be all that was
species in terms of natural causation. All that
this
necessary in order to account for the formation of the species
themselves.
Agriculture and the breeding of farm animals and
of sport animals had indicated the very great phability of the
forms under the influence of selection. Nature seemed to provide such a selection in the competition for existence.
portance of these points of view, as
wanted
The im-
to bring out,
is
that of the carrying-over of the mechanical sciences into the
field
of biology.
Of
course,
not be worked out; but
it
it left
vast stretches which could
made such an assumption
legitimate hypothesis for the purposes of research.
263
a perfectly
CHAPTER
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
XIII
RESEARCH SCIENCE
IS, of course, the research attitude
TTour modern
science. It has flourished
which distinguishes
more
intensively in
the last century and a half than ever before. There
one
is
phase of it that I wish particularly to point out in this connection. Research science approaches certain problems. It does not
undertake to give a systematic account of the world as a whole
any specific field. In the earlier period the function of science seemed to be that of presenting a systematic account of
the universe, including all living forms; and great interest was
centered in the mere statement of classes, families, genera, and
in
species. Interest centered in the picking-out of the
proper types,
the selection of those characteristics which were best adapted
for classification.
But the
interest in science shifted from that
over to research work. Here
we
are thinking of biological sci-
however, true of all modern science.
The research scientist starts from a specific problem that he
finds as an exception to what has been regarded as a law. Given
such an exception, he undertakes to present a hypothesis which
will lead to the solution of the problem. His work, then, starts
with the problem and ends with its solution. Now, what is inence in particular. This
is,
volved in the solution is that the exception itself shall be accounted for, that a new statement shall be given which will over-
come the opposition which the problem suggests.
The illustration of this process that I have often used
is
that
of the sporadic appearance of a contagious disease. Before
knew about
the microorganisms that carried the disease,
it
we
was
assumed that the disease was carried by actual contact. A
is an exception to the rule. Where no person has
sporadic case
the disease there can be no contact.
[264]
The
sporadic case, then,
MODERN SCIENCE
is
an exception.
Now,
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
the scientist starts off with a given point
of view, a given theory, a given technique; he finds an exception to this; then he sets about forming a hypothesis which,
on the basis of facts which he gathers together, will enable
him to connect this exception with the other facts which are
recognized and which can be established. Such a hypothesis
was that of a microorganism which can bring disease, which
itself is carried by a stream of water or in milk, or in some
such fashion. This is a satisfactory illustration of the research
method. It starts from an exception and undertakes to fashion
a hypothesis which will bring these conflicting causes into relationship with each other.
The research scientist does not guarantee the conceptions
with which he starts. He has worked on the theory that an infectious disease of some sort goes from one person to another.
The common theory had been that there must be actual contact between the man who has the disease and the person who
catches it. The scientist accepts this theory for the time being,
but only as a postulate. He does not accept it as something to
be taken in a dogmatic fashion. He accepts the clinical account
of the disease, the history of it, the way in which it presents itself
accepts it from the point of view of the science of the time
but not in a dogmatic fashion. He is perfectly ready to find
problems in all phases of his theory. In fact, the research scientist is looking for problems, and he feels happiest when he
finds new ones. He does not cherish laws and the form in which
they are given as something which must be maintained, something that must not be touched. On the contrary, he is anxious
to find some exception to the statement of laws which has been
given.
Science starts with certain postulates, but does not assume
that they are not to be touched. There
as
we know
it
in
which a problem
no phase of the world
not arise, and the sci-
is
may
is anxious to find such a problem. He is interested not
merely in giving a systematic view of the world from a science
already estabhshed but in working out problems that arise. This
entist
[265]
THOUGHT
is
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
What
the attitude of research science.
point out
is
that the assumptions which
particularly
lie
behind
want
to
this. science
We assume, indeed, that the world is oraccordance with law, that processes in it are uniform.
Otherwise, of course, the world would not be knowable, at least
are only postulates.
dered
in
not in the sense in which science knows it. We know the world
in terms of laws, but we do not assume any certain laws to be
the final formulation. We expect these laws to be continually
We
would think any science barren which did not in
one generation give a different view than that held by the generation before. And, if that difference is a fundamental one, we
think science just that much more productive.
The distinction between the scientific postulate and the
dogma is the distinction between research science and the science of Aristotle. Aristotle stated that it was the nature of
a heavy body to tend toward the center of the earth. He set
that up as a dogma, as his particular definition of a heavy body.
From that he could deduce any logical conclusion^ for example,
that the heavier the body the greater the tendency toward the
changed.
center of the earth. If that
is
the case, then the velocity of the
falling body must be proportionate to
have a solution of a problem
from a dogma.
The
scientific
method
is
in a
its
weight. There you
dogmatic fashion, deduced
aptly illustrated by the procedure
mind, from instances he had seen,
whether or not this conclusion of Aristotle was true he took
bodies of different weights to the top of the leaning tower of
Pisa, dropped them, and found that their rate of fall was not in
proportion to their weight. Then he set up apparatus to discover whether or not he could find a law in accordance with
which they did fall. He did not start off from a given theory
which stated what the nature of the falling body was and then
of Galileo. Questioning
in his
undertake to deduce from that what its velocity must be.
Rather, he undertook to find out just what the velocity was, to
see if it agreed with this law or not; and, when it did not, he set
up a hypothesis that the velocities of faUing bodies vary with
[
266
MODERN SCIENCE
the time of their
fall.
With
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
as accurate an apparatus as he could
produce, he found that his results accorded with that hypothesis. It became, then, a theory,
if
you
like,
to take the
place of the older Aristotelian dogma.
From
the point of view of the scientist, Galileo's theory
postulate.
He
does not set
it
up
it
agreed with the
facts.
as a statement of the nature of
the body, as Aristotle did. Galileo set
cause
is
If,
it
up
as his postulate be-
however, later observations
it did not agree, then any scientist would be
change
only too glad to
the doctrine. All universals used by scientists are postulates of this sort which are accepted as long as
they are in agreement with the facts. When they differ from the
facts of observation, they have to be reconstructed. We can say,
then, that science deals with hypothetical universals. Its conclusions are hypothetical propositions. If such and such a law
holds, such and such a result must follow. But scientific research does not attempt to establish the law as something abso-
should show that
lutely given.
Of course, the old medieval attitude had been that of a giveis
form or statement of causation, a science inherited from Arntotle.
ties
And when
Galileo suggested that bodies
fall
with veloci-
not in proportion to their weight, he was regarded as a
heretic.
From
this
you can
see that the
change
in attitude
research science involved was very profound. While
it
which
starts off
with certain assumptions, these are regarded only as postulates,
and nothing more. They have no inherent
virtue,
no inherent
authority.
One of the basic postulates of the scientific view which I
have been presenting was the mechanical character of the universe, the assumption that we can, for example, state the whole
life-process in mechanical terms. Such an assumption is a postulate which the scientist makes, but it is only that in his eyes.
He is entirely justified in using it in that capacity until he can
hold to it no longer. The conflict, so far as there is one, is between a mechanical and a teleological view of the world. This
conflict has
become peculiarly acute
[267I
in biology.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
you are dealing with the force of a stream of water, you
look at it from a mechanical point of view so much energy at
this point, the water falls so far, and so much energy is developed below. That is an account which is a posteriori, from
behind. However, if you undertake to deal with such phenomena as the digestion and the assimilation of food, you start
If
with the assumption of a certain function to be carried out.
is what would be called, in terms of an Aristotelian science, a "final cause." All this apparatus is there to
off
This function
accomplish a certain purpose. If food
digested before
it
is
taken
in, it
must be
can be assimilated. The apparatus is there,
We set up the end as something which
then, for this function.
is
may
be
causes, but
we
we
there to be carried out in order that a certain result
reached. In biology
have
to
have
final
we proceed with mechanical
causes in our interpretation of these. If
we have to have
assume that the sort
try to go into the actual digestive process,
recourse to the chemical laboratory.
We
of organism in question has to perform a certain function; but
when we come
state
it
in
we do not
mechanical terms. We
to state the operation of this function,
terms of
final causes,
but
in
that, if we have certain chemical substances prescombinations
ent
and we add other substances, a certain change must occur which will lead to such and such a result.
want
to
show
in certain
is, you explain the process from behind. You do not say,
"This must be digested, therefore it must be changed in such
and such a way." You say that this food is brought into contact
with certain substances and that therefore it must change.
You get an explanation that lies behind instead of in front.
That is, you have a mechanical, instead of a teleological, ex-
That
planation.
Another illustration of the difference between a teleological
and a mechanical explanation is found when you set about to account for a certain murder and you say that the man who had an
interest in the death of the murdered man was the cause of it.
It is the end which the man had in view. That is the explanation of what takes place. If, however, the physician who is
f
268
MODERN SCIENCE
called to account for the
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
murder does
way and
entered the body in a certain
so,
he says a bullet
led to a given result.
There you get the mechanical statement, a statement in terms
of cause and effect. This effect is caused by another effect, and
so on. You have a set of causes and effects which follow one
another. If, on the other hand, you are interested in the case as
district attorney, you look to ends, rather than to causes and
effects
ends which the murderer had in view. The latter
wanted the person's life insurance or his property. That end,
the attorney says, explains the murder. That is, he gives a
teleological explanation, while
the doctor
who performs
the
autopsy gives a mechanical explanation.
In biological science you bring in both these points of view.
We
say that, in order for the plant or animal to live, it must
it takes in. This is an end that it must ac-
digest food that
Then you try to show how this takes
you make use of a mechanical explanation.
complish.
do
so,
points that
and to
Well, the two
place;
brought out, that of the possible statement of
life-
processes in mechanical terms and an account of the origins of
away the necessity of a teleological exIf you could make a complete statement in mechani-
seem
species,
planation.
to take
you would not need to bring in the teleological exall. If you can show just what the position of all
the physical particles is, what changes they must go through,
what motions will take place, what reconstructions will occur,
you finally get a statement which you can understand, and one
which does not involve ends. The teleological statement, on the
other hand, in a certain sense, sets up your problem for you.
The animal has to digest his food. How does he do it? The
manner is stated in mechanical terms, but the problem is teleological. Now, supposing you could carry out the whole process
of living in mechanical terms, you would not have to bring in a
cal terms,
planation at
teleological
That
is
statement at
to the so-called
out of
life,
all.
the basis of the objections which have been offered
"mechanical sciences"; they take the meaning
its end or purpose. And this objection, of
take out
[269]
THOUGHT
course,
was made
IN
all
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the
more vivid
in the
contention over the
idea of evolution. Here, seemingly, you have a mechanical ex-
planation for the appearance of species and of their different
organs. All you ask for
is
a set of indefinite variations, a
com-
petition for existences, a changing environment. All these can
be explained mechanically. Presumably, you can show, or at
Darwin assumed that you can show, that every form must
least
some way from its present form, and also that variations could be handed on to the next generation. Of course, this
assumption has been questioned. But it is the assumption which
Darwin's doctrine carried with it. It was necessary to recognize
the fact which every biologist did recognize, namely, that more
young forms are born than can possibly live. Consequently,
there must be a resultant competition for existence. You have
vary
in
to recognize this competition that biology, together with ge-
ology, points out, namely, that the environment
is
constantly
changing, so that the adaptation of a form to one environment
does not adjust
it
There you can explain the origin
lie behind. You do not
a creator having an idea of a form and
to another.
new forms by means of causes which
of
have to say that there
then fashioning
it
is
after that idea of his in order to carry out
some purpose which he has
in
causes operating in a certain
new
mind.
way
You can
simply show that
will lead to the
appearance of
forms, and so you can explain the latter mechanically.
It
was that which
a fight which
what
am
still
led to the very vivid fight over evolution,
continues in some parts of the world.
emphasizing
is
a postulate that science makes. Its
explanation
is
postulate
that the world
is
Now,
that such an appeal to a mechanical
is
knowable, and,
fundamental
if so,
there
must
be a reason for everything, and this reason will have a universal
form. Of course, science has to make that assumption, for it is
its
business to know. Therefore,
it
must postulate that things
And knowing is finding uniformities, finding
But we do not assume that the laws we have disthe statements which persons are going to accept
are knowable.
rules, laws.
covered are
later. We expect to have these laws changed.
[270]
Now, one
of the
MODERN SCIENCE
RESEARCH SCIENCE
IS
assumptions that the biological sciences make
give a mechanical explanation to
process. Perhaps they
may
is
that they can
what goes on
be mistaken about
in
this.
If
the
life-
they are,
be just as ready to recognize that as they are to recognize any other exception. But it is a natural and a perfectly
legitimate postulate. We must go on assuming that we can give
they
will
physical and mechanical statements for everything that takes
place inside of us until
We
longer.
we cannot accept
must make
postulate and not set
it
any
we must make it a
dogma. As long as we accept
we are entirely justified in it.
it
up
as a
such a statement as a postulate,
For
these statements
that postulate, but
has been supported by the successes, the achievements,
of science. It opens a door to the understanding of the world.
There
is,
then, no real conflict between a mechanical and
life.
The
who approaches the problem of digestion inevitably
undertakes to make a chemical statement of what goes on.
a teleological account of the world or of the facts of
scientist
He
still
takes the attitude that starches are digested so that the
Hfe of the form
may
be maintained. That
process in teleological terms.
ary theory
still
Of
course,
if
is,
he states the
he carries evolution-
further, he can say that this so-called purpose
is
nothing but a mechanical process of the survival of one form
over another. But the particular form in which his problem
arises
is
teleological.
does enable
life
How does
to continue?
the digestive process go on that
Take
the question of the secretion
of the various glands of the body. W^hat
we assume
is
that the
various processes that are taking place there have to result in
a nice adaptation to the conditions of the life-process,
and that
the stimulation that comes particularly from the ductless glands
is
essential to carry this out.
We
see that certain of the secre-
such as that coming from the pancreas, enable the blood
to carry more sugar and to carry it in a form in which it can be
most readily turned into energy. The animal must expend entions,
ergy rapidly.
The sugar
most
But
readily.
able, the
in
in the
order for
it
blood enables him to do that
to be there, for it to be avail-
system has to be tolerant of sugar. Therefore you have
[271
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
You
you set the process
by finding actual
chemical processes that take place. You get a statement which
starts off in teleological form, and then you give a mechanical
to
up
have the pancreatic
in teleological
account of it.
Science does not
scientist
is
secretion.
see,
terms and then explain
feel
any
conflict in
it
such a statement.
The
perfectly willing to accept the problem, and he looks
forward to as complete a mechanical statement of it as is possible. And he is perfectly justified in setting up this point of
view until it breaks down. He can say that, theoretically at
least, a mechanical statement can be made of the whole world.
But he does not necessarily assume that that will be an adequate statement. The complete mechanical statement would not
take account of the end, of the purpose, to which we have referred. And that seems to be necessary to our comprehension
of the world. Yet there is no conflict between that teleological
statement of it, on the one hand, and the mechanical, on the
other. Science does not feel any conflict there. Therefore it has
welcomed every advance in mechanical science because it enables it to give a statement, an explanation, of that which is
taking place. The more complete you can make your mechanical statement, the more satisfactory you can make your explanation. You must postulate that such a mechanical state-
ment of the universe can be made. And
you find that it
is not satisfactory, you can throw it over. But you must make
an assumption that such a mechanical statement can be made.
That is the attitude of our modern science. If science were
dogmatic, that
is,
then,
if
of the Aristotehan type, then to postulate a
mechanical account of things would mean to abandon definitely
all final causes, all ends. We would have to set up a theory, a
philosophy, a theology, which would be of a mechanical sort.
That
is
the difference between the mechanical statement that
is
suggested in the ancient world of Democritus and that of research science of the present time.
The
scientist's use of the
mechanical explanation does not carry any dogma with it. He
is entirely justified in making a postulate that he can give such
[272]
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
a statement without being involved in assuming that there
jio
it.
meaning
is
world beyond this mechanical statement of
His attitude does not carry that assumption. It leaves the
in the
whole question open. All the scientist assumes is that he can
make such a mechanical statement, and he gives evidence to
show that he can carry
it
out.
The
result
is
that research
sci-
ence has been able to take over a mechanical theory of the
world and postulate such a theory without committing
any philosophy based upon
You
can find scientists
itself to
it.
who do admit such
a mechanical phi-
losophy. In the middle of the seventeenth century a perfectly
undertook to abandon everything except
the mechanical view of the world, not in terms of a postulate,
but in terms of a dogma. It assumed that consciousness, socalled, was nothing but a secretion, in some sense, of the brain,
just as bile is a secretion of the liver, and that you could treat
it as any other physiological process. It assumed that there
was no end or purpose in the world, nothing but mechanical
procedure. What I am distinguishing between is the postulate
on the part of the scientist that he can find some statement,
some explanation, some solution, of his problem and such a
dogma as this that there is nothing but a mechanics of physical
particles in the universe. One does not imply the other. And
our science is free because it is able to make use of such a postulate without being committed to it as a dogma. What people
found was that such a statement of materialistic science,
definite materialism
when taken
course,
it
to be the end, did not
mean
anything.
But, of
exercised a very considerable influence as late as the
middle of the nineteenth century. Darwin seemed to make such
a dogma all the more practicable and plausible, and you find
certain so-called "evolutionists" taking such a view of the universe. For a time the question of evolution seemed to be the
question as to whether, as Disraeli said, you were on the side
of the monkeys or that of the angels. As for him, he was on the
side of the angels!
tion.
If
you get
That
is
a silly
way
of presenting the situa-
a mechanical statement
[
273
which
will
account
for
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the origin of species, so
much
the better.
The mechanical
state-
you set up, and you must carry it out just
as far as you can, up to the point where it breaks down. And
nobody is happier than the scientist if it breaks down, for then
he will have another problem. He can make a postulate without setting up a dogma. And a postulate of the mechanical account of the world is that which science sets up, but not a dogma
that answers to that. In science itself, there is no attempt to
set up a materialistic philosophy.
The development of science, then, during the last century, the
carrying-over of the statements of physics and chemistry to
everything that is going on, gave tremendous push to our understanding of the world. It also had this definite effect, to show
that science could tolerate no dogmatic statement. Science does
not attempt to set up a dogma, as I have already insisted; and,
of course, science cannot tolerate any other person's setting up a
dogma. If your theological account becomes a dogmatic account, then science cannot accept it. If you say that the world
was created in six days, and that creation started at some period
between four and five thousand years before Christ, as stated
in Bishop Ussher's calculations, you set up dogmatic statements
with which science is in inevitable conflict. Science will at once
turn about and ask for a justification of Bishop Ussher's calculations, will look up documents, ask what they are, where they
came from, who wrote them, and pull the dogma all to pieces.
If you set up a dogma of that sort, science inevitably undertakes to find a problem in it.
The field of biblical dates is, of course, one in which we find
one of the most striking applications of scientific method during
the nineteenth century. It passes under the name of "higher
criticism." In the form in which it appeared, it started not with
the Bible but with Homer. There had been more or less discussion of the Homeric texts way back in Alexandrian days. The
German schools set themselves to work on these texts and found
all sorts of problems. The solution which one clever Oxford
fellow gave was that the Iliad and the Odyssey were written
ment
is
a postulate
[274]
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
not by Homer but by another man of the same name! But
what they were at work upon was to disprove the theory that
these texts were written by any one man. They showed how
the works had arisen and how they became woven into the form
in which we have them at the present time. And that same sort
of interest was turned loose on the books of the Bible; and these
fell to pieces in exactly the same way, and the authors ascribed
to them were shown, many of them, to have been mythical. So
the dogmatic structure of the church,
inevitably
came
its
theological structure,
into conflict with science.
Thus we see that science has gotten away from metaphysical
dogma as to what the nature of things is, and goes back to the
ordering of events which
of uniformities, but
it
it is
it
observes. It states
its
laws in terms /
always ready to change any statement
has made.
The acceptance of the scientific method is the most important
phase of the intellectual and spiritual life of the Renaissance.
I have been indicating what follows from that acceptance of
the scientific method, the
method of research
science. It
is
not
up any fixed statements of the laws of nature
which must hold under all conditions. All that can be said is
that up to the present time we have observed such and such
possible to set
uniformities.
We
tinue. If they
still
postulate that those uniformities will con-
do not, then we
will restate the laws.
Of
course,
wider generalization, namely, that there are uniformities
back of this. In the form in which science uses
seems to have come into the Western mind by
way of religious doctrine. The fundamental belief had been that
the world was created by an infinitely wise and omnipotent
being who must have worked in an intelligent and intelligible J
fashion so that everything could be explained if one were only
able to get back to the fundamental situation. There was a \
reason for everything. That is not, for example, the assumption \
of an Aristotelian science, which admitted certain accidents in f
nature that could never be explained. There were uniformities,
but there were also exceptions which were just there as brute \
in nature, lies
this postulate
it
[275]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
The fundamental assumption
that the world is explicable
an assumption that the world is intelligible, that is, that
we can know it. Knowledge is never a mere contact of our
organisms with other objects. It always takes on a universal
character. If we know a thing, explain it, we always put it
into a texture of uniformities. There must be some reason for it,
some law expressed in it. That is the fundamental assumption
facts.
is
also
of science.
The
scientific
statement of causation
tion of this uniformity. Science, in its
set
up
is
an excellent
illustra-
more dogmatic phase,
Every effect must
a universal law of cause and effect.
have a cause; every cause, a like effect. The scientist found,
however, that an attempt to define causes was most difficult
finally impossible, in the sense in which these terms had been
used. What could one consider to be the cause of any particular
event? Let us take again the illustration which I used before,
that of the assassin killing his victim.
What
is
the cause of the
From the point of view of the prosecuting atwould be the action of the assassin himself. From the
point of view of the social psychologist, it would be the influences which had led to the murderer's taking such a step as that.
From the point of view of the physician, it would be the actual
latter's
death?
torney,
it
entrance of the bullet into the victim's body, or the breaking
of a blood vessel. There are different causes; and
when you
tempt to define causation as such, you are in great
at-
difficulties.
What
science has done has been to substitute for the idea of
cause as a force simply a uniformity which has been discovered
in nature and which we may expect to continue. What we come
back to, then, is a theory of probabilities. The different causes
to which I have referred in this particular illustration are causes
that are determined by different interests. The prosecuting attorney has one interest, that of convicting the guilty person.
The
an interest in determining the conditions out of which such a crime arises. The physician has still
another interest in determining just what the situation within
the
social psychologist has
body of the victim
is,
what
particular vital spot has been
[276]
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
You have sets of different interests, and
each interested person selects one phase or another of the situareached by the bullet.
tion
and
What
labels that the cause.
ferent views
is
ample, to the
a set of uniformities:
lies
back of
all
these dif-
those which led, for ex-
detecting and arresting the criminal;
officer's
those which led the social psychologist to form his
judgment
as
on persons; those which led the
physician to identify certain conditions of the tissues with certain results. What the cause is in each case depends upon the
selection of some particular one of those conditions which is
to the effect of social conditions
of interest to the particular individual.
Generally,
"causes of the event."
can be changed
you can see
in order to bring
it
is
And we
the
out a different result; but
that, as the interests vary, the causation, in our
ordinary use of the term, will vary. Well, science
statements
call these
some condition which
is
in its general
not interested in these changes which are to be
brought about, but it is interested in giving the uniformities
which lie back of what we term the cause, so that the so-called
laws of nature are the uniformities of nature.
cause
is
some one element, some one
such a uniform
series.
We
fact,
expect that,
if
Any
particular
some one event,
in
that or a like event
upon it; and we fall
back upon our judgment of probabilities for justifying us in
that judgment.
But even that assumption of uniformity is a postulate. Science has no absolute evidence that the world is explicable. It
has only discovered a minute number of the so-called laws of
nature. And yet, we go on the assumption that the whole of
nature is intelligible. It is a postulate upon which we act and
upon which science will undoubtedly continue to act, but no
absolute proof can ever be presented for it. Not even an inducoccurs, the corresponding event will follow
tive proof
cause
can be given of
we have found
so
it.
many
It is impossible to
say that, be-
instances in which the operation
probable that the whole of
nature is uniform. You cannot set that up, for you are assuming the uniformity to start with. That is your major premise.
of nature
is
uniform, therefore
it is
[277I
THOUGHT
You
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
can never prove that nature
is
uniform by means of an
inductive syllogism. But nonetheless, science sets up this postulate
and
will
continue to set
it
up.
Not
to accept
it
would be
to
surrender the results and undertakings of science, at least in
certain fields.
The
fact that science
may
not be successful in
certain fields does not disprove those postulates.
No
one can
ever really disprove this postulate of the uniformities of nature,
it may be that we have not gone far enough. We could
always still recognize the possibility that there might be a reason
which we had not found yet. Science in its attempt to know
will always carry with it the assumption that the world is knowable. However
and I must insist on this point it remains
only a postulate, inevitable, if you like, but one for which no
because
absolute proof can be offered.
One
of the results of the freedom which this gives science
the introduction of
mended because
new
is
concepts, concepts which are recom-
I have already pointed out
you the important part the steam engine played not simply
in the development of industrial production but also in the development of physical theory. The theory of the steam engine
was first successfully attacked by Carnot, who, you remember,
conceived of the steam engine as doing work in a manner
analogous to that of the water wheel. It does work because the
of their usefulness.
to
may
down from higher to lower
performs work just as water
does as it runs to lower levels. After heat has reached the lowest level, it can do no more work. Having got down below the
level at which it can expand, its ability to perform work ceases.
You see here that the development of this theory was introducing a new scientific conception, new at least in the form in which
a concept of work done. Carnot, bringing toit was presented
gether the process of the water wheel and the steam engine, set
up this conception of the amount of work done as that which
heat
levels.
be conceived as running
As heat "runs down
hill," it
could be used for computing these two methods of operation.
Of course,
a unit
had
proposed. This idea
worked out, and the foot-pound was
of the amount of work done in raising a
to be
is
[278]
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
pound weight through a distance of one foot. You could do
that by means of the water wheel or by means of the steam
engine. Then, answering to that unit, Carnot set up the idea of
energy. Here is a certain amount of work done- done, of
course, in very different ways in the two mechanisms^ but a
common result is achieved. As a means of computing the results
of these two operations, Carnot, and those who carried out his
theory, set up this conception of a unit of the amount of work
done, and then they set up a supposititious energy that answers
to this. There must be a certain amount of energy responsible
for doing this amount of work, no matter what the type of
mechanism used. It is a very interesting illustration of the introduction of a new concept answering to a new scientific situa-
tion.
Of course, back
of this
new concept
lay the ideas of force. If
you go back to Newton's mechanics and ask what a force is,
you are told that it is a cause of motion. If you try to state that
cause, you have to state it in terms of other motions; and a
force remains outside the field of your actual observations. Of
course, you can observe all the various motions. But energy,
you see, is something that is set up answering not simply to a
motion but to this conception of work done. This conception
was really introduced in an effort to work out a theory of the
steam engine. And one of the most important phases of the doctrine lies in this very conception out of which the situation
arose, that of bringing together the water wheel and the steam
engine as accomplishing the same thing, as having, therefore,
the same energy, that is, as responsible for the same amount of
work done. You think, then, of a steam engine as developing
amount of energy, of the water wheel as developing
amount of energy, the amount of energy being the
same in both cases. Energy is simply something stated in terms
of what it brings out, a certain amount of work. It is, then,
a certain
a certain
something that can be located in one situation and in another;
and it cannot only be located but it can be transferred from
one to another and another and another situation. Suppose you
[279]
THOUGHT
want
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
to produce electric light.
You
take the energy that
is
found in coal and transfer it to the revolution of your dynamo,
thus changing it into the energy of an electric current, and so
finally into the glowing filament. Thus, you have carried your
energy from one form to another. Having set up this unit of
work, having defined it in terms of energy, you can now go
back and discover the energy that is responsible for a given
amount of work now
It
is
a very
good
cepts arise. It
is
it is
now in that, now in another.
way in which scientific con-
not simply the idea of a cause of motion which
really has to be
theory;
in this form,
illustration of the
pushed outside of the doctrine of physical
a conception of something that can be regarded as
responsible for a particular sort of result, that
work that
sort of
is
done.
And
is,
of a particular
when you have set up this
that amount of work done,
then,
you can get
you can say you have just so much energy.
/" From this conception of energy which could be transformed
and found now in this form and now in that arose that great
relationship, wherever
generalization of the nineteenth century, the conservation of
energy
that there
is
always just so
you can
much energy
now
only
it
takes
one form,
now in another, then all that has happened is that it has been
transformed. In a sense this law of the conservation of energy
was proved. If you make this postulate, you can show in any
particular system which you set up that the same amount of
energy is present throughout the whole process. That is, a number of instances are given of a certain system in operation, and
it can be shown that the amount of energy in that system is
constant no matter what different forms it may take. I want
to point out this instance and put it in your minds along with
the hypothesis
the other great generalization of the century
different forms. If
find this energy
in
of evolution.
What
have been saying about the scientific method appHes
also to the social situation, and makes it possible for the whole
community to grasp the ends of the community as a whole and
to make those ends the interest of the individual. That is conI
[2801
MODERN SCIENCE
ceivable and, as
we
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
shall see later,
is
the basis not only of social
community of
relations but of the appearance of selves. This
ends
is
often achieved. For example, in the matter of hygiene,
community be
turned toward the care of the health of the individual and you
reach the health of the community. And you can only reach
the health of the individual adequately by reaching the health
the whole attention of the trained staff of the
let
of the whole community. Save the individual, and you cherish
the good of the community.
And you can
only by saving the individual. This
only
in this case
it
is
accomplish the latter
the ideal of Christianity,
must be the salvation not of the
soul but of
the_bady.
movement as that which we are consideraway from the abstractions which are involved in
separation of soul and body, of mind and body, of the
The
ing
is
this
result of such a
to get
phase of the influence of the
want to emphasize as over against the
spiritual
and the physical.
scientific
method that
It is a
seeming mechanical character of science. On the face of it, as
I say, it presents absolute necessity, a law which determines
where every physical particle should be at any moment throughout the whole history of the universe. While this seems to be a
prison house for any intelligent effort, what it actually serves
to do is to present the apparatus for the control over the environment and for bringing larger and larger ends and ideals
within the vision of humanity. It is that side of it I wish to
bring out before I leave this seemingly mechanical science.
I
now want
to turn briefly to a discussion of the general
philosophical effect of this development of science.
emphasizing was
first
the scientific
place, that brought
member
method and
men back
that the scientific problem
exceptional event, something that
is
is
have been accepted, so that attention
its
What
to observation.
one that
was
import. In the
arises
You
re-
out of the
contrary to laws as they
is
directed toward obser-
vation and toward a statement of the so-called "fact" in terms
of the problem that arises. It is well to recognize that observation
is
not simply an opening of one's eyes and seeing what
f28i
THOUGHT
there
may
always directed by some sort of a problem
mind; it always expresses an interest
We are looking for something that is relatively
we are trying to find are facts which are of the
It is
back
lies
of some sort.
novel.
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
about, or opening one's ears and listening to what
is
occur.
which
IN
What
in one's
same sort as those which have been noted. Now these facts always represent possible or implicit problems with which science deals. We speak of them as "hard facts," because they
have been hard enough to break down some law, some accepted
idea.
For example, take the situation underlying the problem ot
You recognize an acquaintance on the street, start
to speak to him, and then find he is not the right man, after
which you know there are differences that you did not note at
first. Now those differences represent the problem to you, the
problem of why you should have mistaken this man for your
friend. They are hard facts, they defeat the anticipated conversation which you are going to have. They defeat the meeting
with the friend. You have run up against an obstacle. When
you recognize an acquaintance, you pay no more attention to
the actual features than is necessary for the recognition of the
person, that is, for allowing your conversation to go on. There
is no purpose in giving attention to more than that. You just
want enough to assure yourself that he is the person you think
he is. But, when you have started to speak to him and find he
is somebody else, then the differences stand out and you remember how your friend really looks, and you wonder why you
should have made such a mistake. Or you recognize certain
perception.
likenesses.
That
is
scientist
is
the character of the so-called "hard fact."
And
the
continually noting that which departs from the ac-
cepted view, the given laws. With him it is not a disappointment but an achievement, a new problem to work on. He apit with interest and excitement. It is a discovery of
something that is an exception to the view that has been held;
it is the getting of something novel. These facts, then, arouse
proaches
[282]
MODERN SCIENCE
interest
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
and observation. And they not only do
that, but they
lead to the formation of a technique of observation.
is
and seeing things
images happen to
What
it isj is
as the
have said
not simply the opening of one's eyes
that scientific observation
fall
on the
retina.
the recognition of the relationship of those things
which you see to the customary view. And you have to examine
facts from that standpoint. That is, you have to state them in
the form of a definite problem. In the case I have just given
from perception, you note that which makes you certain the
person you meet is not your friend. You have to make that
definite and clear. It might be an acquaintance who had had a
long illness, so that you hardly recognize him. You have to assure yourself whether it is or is not the friend. You bring the
images, the facts, into relationship with your customary intercourse. And then you may go to see what the likenesses were
that led you to make the mistake. Now, when you come to the
scientific situation, you have the so-called facts before you in
terms of their exceptional characters. And you have very carefully to define in
The
what that exceptional character
consists.
illustration of the sporadic case of the infectious disease,
which I have referred, shows this. You have believed, up to
the appearance of this problem, that disease was conveyed by
contact with someone who had it. Now you have a case in
which there is no contact. Your observation forces you, under
these circumstances, to make absolutely certain that there was
no such contact. You have to comb the neighborhood. You
have to make sure that the person who has now come down with
the disease was not a stranger who brought it from elsewhere.
You have to determine very accurately that this is an exception
to the law. You have to state the case in terms of the law and
show that it is an exception to it. And then, when you have that
stated, the first thing you do is to look around for other instances. Now you have a way of defining your facts in terms
of this law, and you look for other sporadic cases and put these
down. This means that as a part of scientific method you must
observe that which runs counter to the currently accepted laws.
to
[283]
THOUGHT
To do
this
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
you give a very careful
definition of the exceptional
instances in terms of the law, so that your observation
tain particular characters.
gather
And
is
of cer-
given these, you are able to
other similar instances. This enables you not only to
all
state your
problem exactly but
also to insert, so to speak, the
negative form of your hypothesis. It states your problem for
you:
How does this sporadic case, or rather
these cases,
mapped
before me, arise in a district in which there were no other in-
The reason for it, presumably, will have
something to do with the distribution of the cases, for these persons have contracted the disease in some unknown manner.
There must be a common cause. You have no hypothesis, as
yet, as to what the cause is; but it must be a cause which can
operate in this series of instances. Therefore, you must have a
hypothesis which fits in with the facts.
This is what the scientific method of observation consists in:
it is the observing of that which runs counter to accepted
opinion, current laws; it is the statement of the so-called facts
in terms of their exceptional character; and then a gathering of
all other facts that you can get hold of which are of the same
sort and which will show you something of the nature of the
hypothesis that may possibly meet that situation. You find
stances of the disease?
that the cases of a disease are
all
located along a river.
Then
you can say that the infection is very likely one which has
traveled along a water course. There you get the form of your
hypothesis. If you can find some infective microorganism that
can travel in water, you can test out your hypothesis. There is
just as
much
accurate technique in observation as there
experimentation.
sis
What experiment
that you have formed and see
does
is
to take the
if it will fit in
is
in
hypothe-
with the facts
which you have before you and other facts which you can
gather. Your experiment is especially constructed so as to
determine whether the hypothesis will agree with the facts.
You assume that something is to be found in water. You actually isolate a microorganism; you try it on a dog to see if that
particular microorganism will give rise to that particular disease
[284]
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
Then, having got that into the dog, you recover the
microorganism from the dog itself and try it on another dog.
You examine those animals which have not the disease, and
prove to your self-satisfaction that they have not the organisms
in their systems. So you prove positively and negatively that,
where the organism is present, the disease is present, and,
where not, the disease is not. But your original observation has
to be as accurate as possible. You must define your facts in
terms of the accepted law in order to see in what way they are
exceptional. That is what we term the "scientific method."
What I was pointing out with reference to what is of particular importance from the general philosophical standpoint is that
these laws which are overthrown by the facts are laws which
had been accepted and have now disappeared as laws. You are
undertaking to set up another law in place of the one which has
been overthrown. The new law is tentatively set up as a hypothesis. You test it. When you have tested it, it becomes a
working hypothesis. And if others test it and it works, it becomes an accepted theory. But, although it is an accepted
theory, it is still subject to some other chance exception. That
in the dog.
is, it still
remains hypothetical.
What
want
to point out
is
that
the necessary conclusions that science draws are always in the
form of a hypothetical syllogism.
But
You
say this must be true
to a statement by a
you will find that he is careful to say that, if
these laws which have been tested by experience continue to
hold, if no new exceptions appear, then such and such a result
must follow. The necessity in this case is hypothetical. There
are no laws of nature which are given in such a fashion that
they can be made dogmas. That is, you cannot say that any
law is absolute and fixed. The laws of nature, as used by science,
are always hypothetical. If some exception appears, then they
will have to be remade. That is the form in which all our socalled laws of nature exist in the minds of the most careful sci-
science has proved
good
if
you get back
scientist,
entists.
I
it.
They
are there as hypotheses; or, to use the expression
have used before, they are postulates.
[285]
We
postulate these
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
certain results; we act on these results; we get
we expected to; and we accompHsh what we set
accomphsh. But new facts may arise which may make it
we reach
laws;
the satisfaction
out to
necessary to reconstruct the postulates.
private faith that any law
deed, the law
take
its place.
ways some
No
may
may have
We
have always the
to be reconstructed. In-
disappear; but another law will be found to
The law
is
dead; long live the law! There
is al-
possible reconstruction that can take the place of
statement that science makes
it.
is final.
We
have had a striking illustration of this in the last few
years in the appearance of the idea of evolution and in the modification of the fundamental laws of the Newtonian world. In
both cases laws were found to be incorrectly or inadequately
stated. They have had to be restated from the point of view of
new experiences. We advance, then, by the use of postulates
which have worked. And we continue to use them as long as
they work. We can recognize that these postulates may have
to be abandoned; but we also recognize that, if they are abandoned, we shall put up others in the place of them. That is the
scientific method which came in and ousted the older technique,
the dogmatic attitude toward the world.
There is one phase of this development to which I wish to return for a moment, that of the idea of energy. By means of it
I wish to illustrate the different sources from which science gets
its
exceptions, or perhaps
which problems
arise.
should say the different points at
seen, in this case the problem
As we have
arose out of the steam engine, which
factor in the life of the
portant
had become a very im-
time and which
made
it
neces-
it could be conwhich people did not
sary to work out a mechanical theory of it so that
The steam engine worked by
trolled.
forces
understand. But what they were sure of was that there was a
certain amount of accomplishment, of work done. They set up
the idea of a something which was there, which could be found
wheels of the machine, in the electric
in coal, in the revolving
something there that answered to this work done.
they called it "energy." As I have said, they assumed on
current^
And
[2861
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
the analogy of the water wheel that the steam, as
it
flowed from
higher to lower levels of temperature, did this work.
Work was
The work which could be done was in
proportionate to the amount of heat. So the laws
proportionate to the
fall.
some fashion
of thermodynamics were worked
out.
This led to the conception of entropy, the assumption that
there exists throughout the whole of the universe a certain
amount of energy which is in different degrees of excitement.
Temperature was recognized as answering to the movement of
things, of molecules, the sort of movement which we cannot see,
which we cannot feel with our fingers, but which reveals itself
to us in terms of temperature. Wherever there is energy, it is
assumed that it is an instance of that sort of motion. Now, according to the laws of energy, this motion
a uniform
minimum
in
which
it
will
is all
tending toward
be evenly distributed
all
through the physical universe. Where you have a great rate of
motion, that motion will impart itself to the other molecules
about it, and that to still other molecules, and gradually there
will be an evening up. If there is more motion in one place than
in another, there will tend to be a situation in which the amount
of motion will be the same everywhere. Thus, temperature can
be conceived of as streams of water which are all running down
toward an entropic ocean, where the motion will be at the lowbut the same everywhere. The whole world seems
to be running down toward that result.
While that conception still remains, it has lost a good deal
of its interest. We are now approaching the scientific problem
from another standpoint; and the conception of entropy, while
still retained, has not the import that it had before. W' e are now
stating our problems in terms of waves, not of heat. The question of entropy was one that arose out of the appearance of the
machine. And, as we have seen, in a certain sense the machine
dictated the conceptions which science itself should utilize.
That is, industry wanted a unit that would answer to work
done. Industry was interested in work. It divided its work up
est degree
into single units, steps, such as the foot-pound.
[287]
That became
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the accepted unit of work.
Now
look to nature, where
seeking for forces to drive our machines, and see
if
we
you can
are
find
something to answer to this unit of work done. Society, as I
said, came forward with a problem, that of controlling the
forces of nature as they appeared in machines. These machines
worked. If we can get a simple unit, this work can be expressed
in any instance in which we find it. We will look in nature for
forces which will do work, and we will state them in terms
of units of force. It is very interesting to see how society set
up this problem for the scientist. The former had its job on
hand that of introducing machines and it wanted a scientific
statement of nature that it could utilize for that purpose. With
task of getting a certain amount of work done, it looked into
nature for something that answered to that work; and this was
supposed to be energy. There might be gradation of energy.
its
This particular telephone here at
my
amount of gradational energy.
tain amount of work.
I let it
From
all
this
you
If
see that science
side represents a certain
drop,
becomes
it
will
do a
cer-
really quite fluid
instead of being a fixed dogmatic structure of the world. It be-
comes a method, a way of understanding the world, so that we
can act with reference to it. And the problems that arise are
those involved in our conduct with reference to the world.
That conduct has a great many phases. It is not simply the
conduct involved in driving machines. It is also our conduct
with reference to other members of society. Religion, for
ample, undertakes to interpret the meaning of the world.
calls for a certain type of conduct on the part of those who
cept reHgion. Science may come in to determine whether
concepts which religion embodies are in accord with what
call
exIt
ac-
the
we
the "facts." It then faces another problem.
Such a situation
The accepted
arose, as
we have
seen, in the case of evolu-
reHgious doctrine stated that
the differ-
tion.
ent forms of plants and animals and physical things were given
all
by fiat of the Creator. They were made just as they were by
God, and they remained in the form that he gave them from
[288
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
day of creation. Science examines the origin of species. It
shows that there is no strong evidence that the forms of things
arose in the creation of a day. God, of course, may have been
the
responsible for their
evolution
but he did not,
life;
if this
statement of
correct, create the forms as such at a particular
is
moment. Well,
science presented evidence to us that the forms
themselves arose in the life-process, and then it came into conflict with the dogma of the church. And it was necessary that
the
dogma
of the latter should be restated
to continue to
if
man were
going
govern his conduct by science. Inevitably, in
will have to be restated, because people are
dogma
the end the
controlling their lives
by
science.
and with the various technical
problems presented to us those of transportation, of communication with distant people you must deal with them in a
scientific manner. You cannot have two methods of conduct
which are separated from one another. In the end your scientific conduct will be dominant, so far as dogma is concerned.
It is not, you see, so much a question as to whether or not science can demonstrate a theory of the world. It is a question as
to whether people are going to act in accordance with scientific
If you
want
to deal with disease
technique.
I must insist again that scientific interpretation does not set
up one dogma in place of another. What it sets up are postulates. It sets up hypotheses on the basis of which we act, and
we will continue to act on them as long as these hypotheses
work.
They
be reconstructed when exceptions are found.
will
Back of these
postulates, however, Hes the constant assumption
that the world
is
intelligible.
That
is,
if
we abandon one hy-
pothesis, we at once set about to build up another. From the
point of view of dogma, this procedure would be a confession of
failure. It is like people continually building cities under vol-
they are repeatedly overthrown, only to be built up
canoes:
again.
But
science
od of conduct.
question
is
is
not stating dogma. It
The only
is
giving us a meth-
thing that science accepts without
that the world itself
[289]
is
intelligible.
When
a sci-
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
law has been proved to be incorrect, it is reconstructed.
The process of inteUigence, then, is one of conduct which is
entific
continually adjusting itself to
new
situations. Therefore,
it is
what we mean by
"inteUigence": the control over conduct by past experience;
the abihty to adjust one's self to a new situation; adjusting
one's past experience to meet this new situation. If there were
no new situations, our conduct would be entirely habitual.
What we term "consciousness" would disappear. We would
simply become machines. Conscious beings are those that are
continually changing
its
technique.
That
is
continually adjusting themselves, using their past experience,
That is what we are
That is what inteUigence consists in, not in
out once and for all what the order of nature is and then
reconstructing their methods of conduct.
doing
all
finding
the time.
acting in certain prescribed forms, but rather in continual re-
adjustment.
The theory
of evolution, you see, was a statement
of this from the point of view of
life.
Science, then, is not simply an advance from one theory to
another, is not the erecting of a structure of laws simply to pull
them down the next moment. Science is an expression of the
highest type of inteUigence, a
method of continually adjusting
You
can immediately see that this
attitude involves a different view of the universe from that
which is presented by dogmatic disciplines. As far as our ex-
itself to
perience
that which
is
is
concerned,
new.
if
everything novel were abandoned, ex-
our conduct would become
habitual. Just as we pay Httle attention to our food, just as we
walk along the street without being aware of the process, or as
we carry out so many of our customary tasks without giving
perience itself would cease.
That
is,
attention to them, so in a world without novelty that in the
experience of the individual which
we
call
would sink toward zero value. Experience
"consciousness"
itself
would
cease.
Our experience involves the continual appearance of that which
We
which is different from the past. In fact, if it were not, the very meaning of
the passage would disappear. The conception of the mechanical
is
new.
are always advancing into a future
[290]
MODERN SCIENCE
IS
RESEARCH SCIENCE
statement of the universe which Newton gave was of a universe made up of physical particles governed by very few and
very simple laws. There were movements of these particles;
but they were tending, as we have seen from the conception of
entropy, toward a condition of stagnation, of very slight movements. Changes were tending to balance each other; they were
moving toward a situation in which there would be no change
at all. That mechanical statement, as everybody felt, took the
meaning out of life. If you state the world in purely mechanical
terms, then you have a single law for the whole of it, and it is
practically the same. The same kind of energy can be somewhat differently distributed, but it is uniform. It gives a static
sort of picture of the universe. The point of view which comes
in with scientific method implies that, so far as our experience
is concerned, the world is always different. Each morning we
open our eyes upon a different universe. Our intelligence is
occupied with continued adjustment to these differences. That
is what makes the interest in life. We are advancing constantly
into a new universe; and, not only is the universe that we look
forward into new, but, as we look back, we reinterpret the old
universe. We have continually a different past. Every generation re-writes its history.
Novelty reaches out
from each present experience.
291
in
both directions
CHAPTER XIV
SCIENCE RAISES PROBLEMS FOR
PHILOSOPHYVITALISM
HENRI BERGSON
THE
evolutionary phase of the scientific conception of
the world got one of
its
philosophic expressions in the
philosophy of evolution of Henri Bergson.
turn to an examination of that philosophy. Life
I
is
wish
now
to
a process of
continued reconstruction involved in the world as experienced.
The new is always appearing, with the consequent appearance
new forms answering to that reconstruction. Bergson recogwhat the office of intelligence is in this immediate adjustment, and he saw that it cannot look ahead and see what the
order of the world is going to be. But Vv^e have assumed that we
of
nizes
can prophesy the future, at least in certain
the astronomer can figure out
all
number of centuries ahead; and we
for
details.
For example,
the eclipses of the sun for a
utilize the
determining certain events in the past.
same
We
sort of data
can date past
events from certain eclipses which occurred at certain recorded
And we can go ahead and predict them for the future.
But these eclipses are stated in terms of the laws of Newton,
and these laws are being continually re-written. While the
times.
differences
may
be minute, the statements of the laws are not
There are changes taking place which those laws do
not take into account. Even such fundamental facts as that of
the relative motion of heavenly bodies with reference to each
other cannot be stated once and for all. If the function of intelli-
exact.
gence
is
to previse the future of the world,
it is
a failure.
Bergson took that view. He said, like all
are en route to something which we cannot foresee.
not know where we are going, but we are on our way.
And
the rest of the world,
we
[292]
We
do
Intelli-
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
we
us where
are going, and
gence undertakes to
tell
do
in that sense a failure.
it.
Intelligence
our immediate steps; but
to direct
it
cannot
which Bergson called the elan
us on; and yet we do not know where
going to do.^i^fi^adjust ourselves to
it
tell
us the meaning
vital^
it
cannot
does enable us
not one directed by our intelligence. There
in nature,
it
It
The onward movement which we
of the world.
it is
is
is
at the
discover in
is
which
going,
some
is
what
moment
force
pushing
it
is
as best
we can. This means that we trust ourselves to that force without trying to see into the future. So Bergson decried intelligence.
He was an anti-intellectualist. He undertook to show that our
reflective
view of the world always distorts the world.
in the interest of conduct, it
complish our daily tasks; but
it
It
does
does enable us to ac-
is
true;
it
does not give us the picture
it
you ask Bergson how we are to get a
is, he says by means of immediate
intuition. "]And there his philosophy becomes quite unsatisfac'^
of the world as
it is.
If
picture of the world as
it
tory.
It
is
the evolutionary phase of science, as interpreted in
Bergson's philosophy, that
we
will consider first, that part of
philosophy which emphasizes the forward push, the elan
vital. It emphasizes a progress which takes place without any
his
one sense having
always the relationship of form to environment. The control may be on the one
side or on the other. In human societies forms are reached which
do, in a very large degree, control the conditions under which
they live. But, while you can say that that is a goal which in
some sense has been reached; while there is always an effort on
given goal.
have spoken of evolution as
reached the goal of human society. There
in
is
the part of every living form to control
its
environment, as
far as it can; the ways in which that goal can be reached, by the
development of sense organs, of means of locomotion and of
communication, never stands outside of the process. It is
reached in the struggle, in the effort to control. The form it
takes is something that can never be prevised. And that is true
not only of separate forms but of social development as well.
[293]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
We can never tell what inventions are going to put us into closer
communication with each other, what industrial methods will
be worked out for closer economic connection with other people
in the world, what means of communication will set us in actual
intercourse with people thousands of miles
away
so as to
make
of society a universal interrelationship of people. All these are
ways
in
which we get ahead, and not ways of approach to a
given, fixed ideal. Bergson interpreted the
opment
as anti-intellectual.
He assumed
movement
of devel-
that reason, in the
control of conduct, simply served immediate purposes.
it
served them by distorting the world. Forward
And
movement
does not come from a rational, reflective element but from an
impulse that
concerned.
lies
behind, a blind impulse as far as reason was
What Bergson
failed
to
realize
is
that there
is
nothing so rational, so self-consciously reflective, as the applica-
method to immediate conditions, and that the
use of this method is just the means, under these conditions,
that the human race is using for advancing. The anti-intellection of scientific
tualist attitude of
import of the
Bergson represents a
scientific
failure to grasp the
method, especially that
it
puts the en-
vironment under the control of the individual. It is always
true that we get ahead and keep going without knowing what
toward which we are moving. But we are free to
work out the hypotheses that present themselves and test them
and so solve the immediate problems that we meet.
the goal
is
is one which was an
outcome of the theory of evolution, as I have already said. The
philosophy of the Renaissance had as its background a view of
nature which got its expression in Newtonian mechanics, that
is, a physical world which was determined in all its movements
by certain simple laws and which gave an account only of the
positions of these physical particles. The result of this was the
In a certain sense, Bergson's position
bifurcation of the world, the putting of other characters of
the world of our experience into consciousness while
it left
the
world of matter and motion to the statement of a mechanical
[294]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
The
philosophy.
there
is
doctrine of Bergson
is
one which impHes that
a process of evolution going on in nature, a process in
which there
a constant creation of that which
is new. There is
statement of nature, at least of the mechanical
theory, practically nothing that is new. While there is a shifting
of energies from one field to another, there is the same amount
is
in the traditional
of energy, the same kind of motion and of matter. These always
remain the same.
everything
tical
is
And
the doctrine of entropy assumes that
moving toward
a state in which there will be prac-
stagnation, at least only slight
among molecular
movements taking
place
This was the picture which the mechanical view of the world gave. It abstracted from everything
except matter stated in terms of inertia and the motions of these
bodies.
particles. In consciousness arose the various experiences of the
world that we know, different objects with the sensuous characters which belong to them in experience. What the me-
was able to do was to state the conditions
under which these conscious experiences arose. But the characters which belong to objects and their nature as objects bechanical doctrine
long only to the conscious experience,
if
the doctrine
is
carried
out consistently.
The world
one the physical
particle, the other the universe as a whole.
from the point of view of
the mechanical philosophy, is simply a congeries of particles
all being related to all others. There was no justification for
unifying certain groups and saying that these existed by themselves. There were really only two objects in the universe:
itself,
lines drawn between separate groups of physical particles
were arbitrary, determined by the process of consciousness.
The very interest which, for example, an animal would have in
The
certain
groupings of them as over against other groupings
would, in Bergson's statement, be determined by his perceptions. That is, he would see those characters of the object, as
which were of importance for
dangerous and
run
toward it.
would then run
He would regard only those parts and characters of the physical
this
his
appeared
own
in his experience,
conduct.
He would see that which was
away. He would see food and
[295]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
universe which are of interest to him, so that perception would
be responsible for the actual structure of the thing itself. Perception would be, in that sense, the determiner of the object.
But Bergson assumed that the nature of things themselves
was
to be found not only in perception but also in the world.
Our thought
or perception
so-called
belongs to the nature of things.
"consciousness"
The conceptions
that
really
we form
of things are, as he indicated, determined by the usage to which
we are going to put them. We think things out in terms of plans
of action. These are the characters that belong to the things
We
world as it is and as it will be
when we are going to act in a certain way. We recognize, as
fixed, the ground upon which we walk. The object toward which
themselves.
we
are acting
is
want
to see the
fixed or
moving
in a certain direction.
things as conditions of our conduct.
as
it.
we
We
fix
We
the world as
see
much
can, because that will enable us to act with reference to
In reality the world
is
not fixed.
We
are simply selecting
out the characters which are of interest to us for our conduct
and holding them in a static condition before our eyes because
the changes taking place are unimportant as far as our conduct
is
concerned. Actually, everything
is
in
motion. Things that
motion may be so
unimportant. Or the motion may belong to a
whole group of objects, so that relatively they are at rest with
reference to each other. The earth is moving about the sun in
this manner, but for our conduct it can be dealt with as at rest.
Such a statement of things in certain fixed relations, Bergson
seem
to be fixed are really in motion, but the
slight that
said,
was
it is
a special statement.
the world, so to speak
And
catches
this special
it
statement freezes
at an instant
and holds
it
not a statement of things as they really are. They
changing
always. And their change is not simply moare really
tion from one special point to another. There is change gothere. It
is
ing on within the objects themselves, just as there
is
change
an inner change, and, as a
That fundamental procchanges.
result of this, there are outer
ess going on in all things Bergson said appears in what we call
going on within ourselves; there
is
[296I
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
"time," or duration as distinct from space. And one of tlie
fundamental tenets of his philosophy is that this duration, this
process which is going on, can never be presented adequately in
spatial terms.
Any
statement of
it
in
purely spatial terms
is
always bound to be a distortion of reality.
When he looks for an instance of what he calls pure "duration," as distinct from mere motion in a fixed space, he goes to
the inner experience of the individual. If
we look
inside our-
is interpenetrawe
what takes place at one moment and what takes place
at another moment. You cannot cut oflf your ideas, feelings,
sensations, and fix them at a certain point and say that one
belongs to this point and another to another point. Your feel-
find a process going on in which there
selves,
tion of
something that pervades a whole experience. Such a phefor example, as a melody is illustrative of what Bergson refers to. You can deal with the melody simply as a set of
notes, if you like; and you can hang those notes up on the
bars and think of each note as answering to a certain vibration.
But there would not be a melody if there was a sound at this moment, another at the next, and so on, each taken by itself. And
if your experience was only of that sort, it would not be one of
ing
is
nomenon,
a melody.
What
is
characteristic of the
melody
the fact that
is
the note which you are hearing and singing extends on, endures
into later notes. It
that
is
a relationship between the different notes
makes up the melody. There must be an interpenetration
of the different notes in order that there
and that
is
what
is
characteristic of
all
may
be a melody,
our thought. Duration,
as such, always involves this interpenetration, not only in the
sense that
what
is
taking place extends over into what
is
coming on, but
coming into existence and anticipates what is
also that it gives the meaning and value to things. It is the
use of the table that makes a table of it. If there is no use
for it, it is nothing but a lump of wood. It is our attitudes of
conduct that give to even such a thing as a work of art its
beauty. It
is
is aroused in us that calls
our attitude toward more ab-
a sort of response that
out the aesthetic feeling.
And
in
[297]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
stract things, such as a concept of a table as a unit that
is al-
ready there, we find that that constitutes the import of
as an
object.
When you
cubicles,
cut things off and place
an injustice
is
really
them
it
in special
being done to reality.
The
"knife-edge" point of view assumes that all our experience takes
place at instants instants that are not spread at all. These in-
stants have the
As
same
relation to time that a point has to space.
a point has no magnitude, so an instant has no duration. It
succeeded by another instant, and so on. The mathematician breaks up not only space, but motion, into an infinite
number of points; he breaks up the temporal phase of it into an
is
infinite
number
of instants.
Now
our experience of anything taking
to an instant, then pushed aside and
another experience put into its place; if our experience was
simply that which takes place at one instant and then at the
next instant, and none of these instants had any spread; then
you can see that,
place was really confined
if
there would not be any experience of change at
all.
Then
the
world at one instant would be completely wiped out by the
world as it is at the next instant. There would be no connection between the two, no real duration; there would be only
substitution of one instant for another. This statement of
time in terms of separate instants Bergson calls a "spatial
And what he insists upon is that this
time
does not anticipate each duration
of
Statement
spaHaT
as we actually experience it. What the mathematician does,
you see, is to give an account of time which is spatial. If he
draws a line which represents the path of a motion, one of the
co-ordinates representing time, another space, he can draw
a curve which determines the velocity of the moving body;
he can mark off a certain point on one co-ordinate and call
it a certain moment, the next point the next moment, and
so on. That is a spatial statement. What is of importance
from Bergson's point of view is that each moment in time
includes any other, just as any point in space includes any
statement of time."
other point in space.
The
exclusion of the parts of duration
[298]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
is
what Bergson
They do not mutually exclude each
denies.
would be nothing but a set of separate experiences which could have no temporal relationship to
other. If they did, duration
each other at
all.
but with practically the same meanstatement that our experience is always a passing
experience, and that this passing experience always involves an
extension into other experiences. It is what has just happened, what is going on, what is just appearing in the future,
Put
in different terms,
ing, is the
It is never
no such thing as the
experience of a bare instant as such. The psychologists have
termed this the so-called "specious presen t." a term which implies that it is not a real present. It is experience dealt with as
that gives to our experience
peculiar character.
its
an experience just at an instant.
if
There
the present were instantaneous.
that which
is
going on;
Of
course, the present
a spatial image.
it is
psychologists have hitched
is
memory on
as a
is
To this present
memory image,
and the future as another image, something anticipated;
and they have dealt with these images as if they existed in
an instantaneous present. You can see that your memory of
something is something that exists now. You remember now
what you did an hour ago. So the psychologist makes up the
present out of an instantaneous experience, plus an equally
instantaneous
memory and an
equally instantaneous anticipa-
tion, all fused into a present instant.
And
they say that these
images, fused into an instant, give us the impression of a specious present which extends.
Well, of course, experience does extend. If you could get it
and then simply replace that by another
into a single instant
instant, there
would
would need
to be
no such thing as duration.
be living only in the present.
And
You
the difference of the
presents would be a difference not of duration but of substitution. Actually, our experience is one which includes both past
and future. What is going on is something that is slipping
away, plus something that is just coming up over the horizon.
Part of it has just happened, part is just coming to be; and in
[
299
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
it may have happened and that it may be an experimust be past and future. Our present is the fusion with
order that
ence,
it
both past and present in the experience itself. The specious
is not the present. The present is something that is
present
happening, going on; and in this going-on what does happen
related really, actually, to what is taking place, and what
taking place
is
really related to
what does happen. Of
is
is
course,
our present is chopped off into very small portions. We can
represent only a few seconds perhaps. At times it is so chopped
off that we cannot effectively connect the different portions of
An
it.
illustration of this has
been given of a person
who
is
rid-
ing in a train with telegraph poles flashing by. Suppose he tries
to relate these.
He
He
is
counting them.
They go by very
rapidly.
finds himself dealing with sets of such short intervals that
he cannot connect them, think of them consecutively.
experience
is
think them separately.
But
if
grass in the sun, with things
bird, the
wind
One
replaced by another so rapidly that he cannot
in the trees
he can stretch himself out on the
moving slowly
where there
is
the swoop of a
an extension, he can
get a longer present than in the railroad train.
One
part of
experience merges into another, and you have really the inter-
penetration of Bergson.
This
is
something you do not get
in a spatial
statement. It
is
the very essence of space that any position excludes any other.
A thing cannot be in
two places
at once. If
you are going
to rep-
resent time in this spatial fashion, then your experience cannot
be at two separate instants. [But our experience, our feelings,
our sensations, are extended over our present; and one present
is a flow in which the past is
and the future back into the
extends over another so that there
really reflected into the future,
past. That, Bergson says, is the nature of reality. It is not that
which can be expressed in points and instants; it must be expressed in duration. And what he insists upon is that we should
take time seriously. The impression we have of this continuity
and of this interpenetration is not something simply to be found
in consciousness while the real world is made up of happenings,
[300]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
separate instants at separate points, in which the past and the
future are not actually present. If the future is in the experience
it
influences
it.
That
is,
of course, the nature of our so-called
"intelligent conduct."
What we
are going to do
by what we
Our ends
are there, interpenetrating
are doing.
the world in terms of means. If time
our
all
is
it must be, then what is
what has just happened. You can get
The
nature.
determined
taken seriously, as Berggoing to happen can actually
son says
affect
is
own
final
causes into
future can influence the present just as
condu,ptJ If that
is
it
does in
the nature of what takes place, of
duration, the future can enter into
it.
The world
is
not simply a
process of the readjustment of physical particles with reference
remains always the same;
to each other, a situation that
process that
lies
ahead of
fluencing
is
it,
what
it is
going on, always moving on into a future which
which
is
is
just appearing, and, as
it
appears, in-
taking place.
For example, a person
finds, in crossing a street, that the
automobiles are going by at great speed; and he suddenly stops
or turns. It is only after he has actually stopped or turned, or
means
to stop or to turn, that he
responsible for his action.
That
is,
aware of what it is that is
his adjustment to what is takis
ing place comes earlier than the impression of the situation
self.
You
find that frequently
it is
the beginning of your
it-
own
motion that first apprises you of the object itself in regard to
which you are moving. It is particularly true of the impressions
which have reached the periphery of the retina as over against
the most sensitive point of vision. We turn with reference to a
moving object, and then see what it is. The motion comes first,
with reference to something which is already there. Rut.it is our
adjustment to it that is first given in experience. (Tliat is the
sort of picture of the world that Bergson presents. It is always
moving on toward a future which is just arising. W'hat it is
you cannot tell until it does arise. But it is always coming into
experience, and we are always adjusting ourselves to it, finding
out what it is by the very process of change. That is the sort of
evolution which is taking place, a process ceaselessly going on
^oi
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
with continued adjustment, with a future actually affecting that
which is taking pla(;^'Well, as I said, what Bergson has in-
on is that we should take time seriously, that is, that we
should take into account pure duration, and that that involves
not simply the past but the future as well.
sisted
The
past which physical science gives us
has happened.
We
is
of something that
are always looking back at something that
has happened, in so far as we are observing things
scientifically.
The event must have taken place, must have left some definite
record, must have fixed itself in some definite way; and then,
after it has fixed itself, we estimate it. Scientific data are the
records
left.
All that has happened,
all
that
is
taking place,
is
framework in which every element excludes
every other element. But that is not the nature of reality acfixed in a spatial
From
cording to Bergson's statement.
his standpoint, reality is
something that is always going on, and that which is taking
place is always reacting on what has taken place and acting
ahead upon that which will take place. The novel Is always
there affecting us, always affecting what is taking place.
In a sense, of course. Darwinian evolution expressed this.
Something happens and affects the form, selects out that which
is adapted to the new situation. It eliminates those forms which
are not adapted. This process, going on all the time, is one in
which what is taking place has something of the future in it.
If you take a geological picture of the world, you get a picture of
it looking back over what has taken place, and the continued influence of that which is going on over the future is lost. The
view of evolution which Bergson recognized is a view in which
there is this interpenetration in which the future can affect the
present, in which there is continued adjustment, but an adjustment which is due to what is taking place.
But this view is one which can never be given in spatial
terms.
we
What
is
are thinking.
just taking place
Our thinking
is
is
continually belying
what
just such a process of putting
things into a framework as the mathematician's process of
dealing with motion.
In thinking,
[302]
we
are putting things into
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
and separating them from each other. It is
the very nature of thought to tear things apart, to cut out the
things that are important, to pick out only one particular character of the thing and relate it to something else that has the
same character and then put these into the same cubbyhole.
It is a process of classifying things in which we are continually
different cubicles
breaking them up. That, says Bergson, is of service to us in
our conduct; but it does not give us the reality of things.
His philosophy then, while it looks toward the future, looks
toward a future that is always novel, toward a future which
cannot be conceived, which cannot be presented in terms of perception. Any picture which we make of the future, as we know,
is always belied by that which really happens. You go to meet
somebody and anticipate the meeting. It may be a disappointment or it may be beyond your anticipation, but it is always
different.
You
never can present
it
to yourself exactly as
it is
You
can only say that such things have happened in the past; they have had such and such a fixed character; so I am justified in assuming that the same sort of thing
happening in the future v/ill also have this character. But there
All this fixed conception can
is always something different.
going to happen.
when we use conceptions to
give us the nature of things as such, we are always discarding them, according to Bergson. And we know that the future will always be different from anything we can actually
do
is
to direct our conduct; but
present to ourselves, so that an intellectual view of the world,
a conceptual, reflective view, is, apart from its use in conduct, a
Thus, Bergson is an anti-intellectualist. The true
view of reality, says Bergson, has to be got by intuition, in
which you are able in some way or other to catch the something
that is going on and hold on to it as a reality. He is very vague,
unsatisfactory, in the picture of reality which is grasped in a
distortion.
sort of metaphysical intuition.
have done no more than
suggest certain phases of the Bergsonian philosophy. What
is of importance to us is this taking of time seriously, for in a
Of
course, so far in this discussion
[303]
THOUGHT
certain sense this
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
is
an anticipation on the philosophical side of
up a space-time in place
the relativistic doctrines which have set
And what
of an absolute space and an absolute time.
portant
view of the world which
And
chanical.
is
also im-
that Bergson's philosophy arises out of a point of
is
is
evolutionary as over against me-
evolution as such
is
a process that
is
continually
an elan vital. Anything that is continually going on cannot be stated simply
in terms of that which can be put into an instant. What evolution has done is to present to us the conditions out of which
new forms can arise. It has given us those conditions; and our
thought, our interpretation, of them impHes constant appearance of new forms. If we turn back to a mechanical stategoing on. Bergson's term for this process
ment of
the world,
what we get
now
is
is
simply a distribution of
and now at another. In
what we have is practically the same. We
have the same amount of energy, the same kind of motion.
physical particles
these situations
all
Everything
that arises
It is
the
is
at one instant
is
interrelated with everything else.
means simply the
only our interpretation of
new
The new form
redistribution of physical particles.
it
that
makes the new animal,
What
plant, out of this shift of positions.
to insist that this process of
change that
Bergson does
going on, with the
is
appearance of that which is novel, is the reality of things, and
that our philosophy of nature should be an evolutionary philosophy which takes into account a theory of change. This
change involves duration. His is an approach to the interpretation of the world from the evolutionary point of view which
takes into account the whole of our nature.
From another
proach
latter
is
the
From
that Bergson's ap-
You will remember
that the
his
failed to find in
'
we may say
as that of Kant.^
problem arising out of the statement of Hume.
came back to the reality of states of consciousness but
found
Hume
point of view
same
them the world which
this point to the
class notes of
science
had been describ-
end of the chapter the material has been taken from
in "The Philosophy of
Mr. George A. Pappas. They are from a course
Bergson," as offered during the
summer
of 1927.
[304]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
ing.
The
uniformities of the scientific description dissolved into
a succession of conscious states held together
tion which, being subjective,
tell
objective world. Against this
by laws of associaan
us nothing of the nature of
Kant proposed to find
itself. Whereas
sity for science within consciousness
the necesfor
Hume
knowledge had no other basis than that of habit, for Kant concepts were themselves essential, they were the precondition of
knowledge. Prior to dealing with the spatial attributes of reality you must have a concept of space. The necessity of the
was the basis of the science
came from the nature of the
great mathematic structure which
of the time was something that
mind
Itself.
Since the
fectly possible to
basis of
plies
it.
Of
mind had
this formal capacity,
it
was per-
develop a rational and universal science on the
course,
you
will
remember that
this science ap-
only to the world of experience, the world of phenomena.
no bridge from it to the other world, that of noumenal
But within the former there was necessity, uniformity,
and universality, because the mind required that. The mind being what it is, these characteristics of our science could not be
There
is
reality.
avoided.
Now
Bergson is Kantian in the sense that he too takes his
departure from the results of science and builds up his position
in terms of what he sees to be the implications of these data.
He, like Kant, was convinced that, while science was exact
within the field of experience, there was another phase of reality
that science itself could not come into contact with; and, in
somewhat the same way as his predecessor, he felt that this
latter was more important than the former. The fundamental
distinction between the two is that the science in which Kant
was interested was mathematical while Bergson turns to the
implications of biology and psychology.
Mathematical mechanics, the mechanics of Newton, had
broken the world up into ultimate elements. In this statement
we have the universe as a whole, on the one hand, and the
infinite number of particles that compose it, on the other. This
view pays no attention to the particular groupings of these par[305]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
tides into smaller units, objects or organisms. These can be of
no special interest
not necessary.
to the physicist, because the groupings are
They
are the result of the operation of certain
physical tendencies, and any group that
broken up until
finally the ultimate
these are obtained,
it is
may
be formed can be
elements are reached.
When
seen that the temporary groupings of
them are wholly incidental from the point of view of their nature
and have nothing to do with the character of the physical forces.
This
still
is
not the picture as the biologist presents
less the
most important factor
to us. It
is
the structure of the particles, not in
is
their isolation, but as they appear as structures.
realized this;
it
presentation of the psychologist. In biology the
Kant himself
and while he was primarily interested
ing a philosophical defense of the
Newtonian
in present-
science, he recog-
nized, in the Critique of Judgment, that things had to be dealt
with in biology which were of no importance from the physicist's
point of view.
The
first
of these was that the biologist has to
conceive of particles as related in wholes; and second, that to
understand these wholes, ends and purposes had to be admitted
Hke art, is teleological.
into the picture. Biology,
in philosophy what Newton had in
complete intelligibility. That is the
suggestion that came to Bergson. He found the mechanical ex-
Kant had accomplished
science:
he had given
it
When you turn to the world that had
been unfolding under the influence of the growing interest in
biological phenomena, particularly after Darwin, you find that
the early statement of science is not adequate. You cannot take
planation inadequate.
biological structures and describe them in Newtonian terms.
Thus, Kant's intelligible world is faced with a serious difficulty.
His problem must be worked out again. It is this that Bergson,
in a certain sense,
undertakes to do.
He
proposes to start with
the nature not of physical but of biological and psychological
phenomena.
His interest
in Bergson's
in the data of psychology indicates another roQt
thought, one that goes back to Descartes. Psy-
chology became important in the nineteenth century. It^oes
[306]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
not start with the physical particles of the mechanical stateIt starts with the organism which is there as the condition of experience. The organism in some sense is there before
ment.
consciousness appears.
Of
course,
this
is
not the Cartesian
statement. For Descartes, mind and body were distinct substances neither of which depended upon the other for its being.
His fantastic treatment of the pineal body must not be thought
of as implying any functional relationship between mind and
body. It was simply a device for dealing with an acknowledged
situation, the reciprocal influence of mind on body, and vice
versa. Not even the English empiricists saw the problem in
terms of a functional relationship. Their psychology was a philosophy. It undertook to give a statement of the structure of
things whic h at t he same time left the things "out there."
Hume left the world in the form of impressions and ideas, of
states of consciousness. It is to this situation that the words
"subjective" and "objective" ordinarily refer. But gradually a
new meaning appeared. With the psychology of the nineteenth
century these terms apply to a functional relationship within
experience. The mind is no longer something here, something
inside, which gets impressions from something there, something
outside. The inner and the outer, the subjective and the objective, are phases of a single process and point to differences
of perspective, not to absolute differences of locus. This new
approach is that of what may be called the scientific, the "new,"
psychology, as over against the philosophical psychology of the
earlier period.
ological
It
organism
develops out of the recognition that the physiis
the condition of the appearance of states
of consciousness. Just as there
a functional relationship be-
is
tween the organism and its environment, so there is one between what is "in the mind" and what is "outside." It is a
reconstruction of psychology which starts off with the assumption that there is a world "out there" and a world which is the
precondition for the states of consciousness.
According to
creates
new
this functional point of view, the
mind
itself
worlds, not in the Kantian sense of determining the
[307
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
must be interpreted,
each new perspective gives rise to a new
forms, the categories in which experience
but
in the sense that
The mind
creation.
is
sponsible for the world
mind
a part of a creative process which
itself.
Appearing within
functionally related to
is
other aspects of
all
is re-
this process, the
it.
It is
no
longer possible to stand by the bifurcation of the world into
outer and inner.
With
new position Bergson
we find one of the clues
is
it
for the interpretation of his
whole position.
is
within,
what
which
hearty agreement. In-
in
this
deed, in
it
If the
without.
is
lies
is
the condition of
what
Thus Bergson
turns his attention to that
within experience; and he, like Kant, finds in this
certain factors which
reality can
world out there
brings the possibility of the within being created of
become
must be
dealt with before the nature of
problems of the philosopher
clear, before the
can be satisfactorily dealt with. The thing in subjective experience to which he gives his attention particularly is its flow, that
is, its
temporal aspect.
He
finds the
same thing
in consciousness
that the biologist finds in dealing with organisms, namely, that
it is
impossible to reduce either to ultimate elements.
By means
of this process of reduction physical science had destroyed the
significance of particular objects.
so far as
it
The world
of experience, in
contained wholes, was broken up into an indefinite
number of elements. The world in inner experience had been
broken up into a series of atomic impressions by the English
empirical thinkers. In each case something
former,
it
ticles; in
is
the latter,
it is
ences into one another. It
Bergson.
He
is left
out. In the
the essential unity of certain groupings of para certain penetration of the experiis
this
which
is
of especial interest to
goes back to his experience and finds that
what
an interpenetration of experiences. Take
the notes of a musical scale, for example. A melody is something
more than a mere accumulation of separate tones. The E, G, C
of the scale have no musical significance in themselves. It is
takes place there
is
only as they interpenetrate that they form a musical unit;
only as the tones interpenetrate that the melody
[308]
is
it is
presented.
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
The
experience of the present
of what took place just before
place.
That which
will
moment
is what it is because
and of what is about to take
it,
be in consciousness
nected with that which
is
in a
moment
is
con-
present there now. All our experi-
ences share this character of interpenetration. But
it is
especial-
our indefinite states of consciousness. The subjectivity to which Bergson returns, then, is one which shows us a
ly true of
content rather than a form. In this there
is
a distinct cleavage
be_tween_him and Kant.
It
is
in
terms of the interpenetration of particles
in objects,
on the one hand, and of elements of conscious experience, on
the other, that Bergson proposes to build up his philosophy.
That is, whereas Kant took his problem from mathematical
physics, Bergson attacks the philosophical question from the
point of view of biology and psychology. The procedure of the
scientist of modern times differs from that of the ancient scientist in that the former starts from specific problems whereas
the latter developed his procedure from the point of view of certain given characters.
modern
science
is
The
practical significance of this
hypothetical. It
give science a categorical form.
is
true that
Kant
But he did not succeed
is
that
tried to
in this.
Although he did not realize it, the categories, the universality,
the necessity, which he set up are themselves only hypothetical.
Even though the form of the laws might be universal, they were
still only^ hypothetical in character. Gahleo's statement that
velocity varies with time and Darwin's statement that species
have arisen under the influence of the process of natural selection and the survival of the fittest are both hypothetical.
One of the hypotheses of the mathematical point of view was
that organic structures could be broken up into their ultimate
particles in exactly the same way as could inanimate objects.
But the biologist found this could not be done. He had to deal
with his objects as individual things. The parts must be conceived in their relationship to the whole, for apart from that
relationship they have no significance. In dealing with the problems of this science and with tliose of psychology, we cannot
[
309
THOUGHT
come
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
mechanical statement. If we atwe destroy the object with which we are deaHng.
to the simplicity of the
tempt to do
so,
The organism must be thought
whole and not
sciousness
in
terms of
must be
of in terms of
its particles,
its
processes as a
just as states of con-
dealt with in terms of their actual inter-
penetration and not simply as a flow of atomic sensations each
of which
is
of, others.
distinct from,
One
nor psychology
and can be dealt with independently
result of this
is
is,
of course, that neither biology
as accurate as physical science.
The me-
up
no reason why one whole should be built up rather than another. Biology, on the other hand, deals with wholes, and the
parts have meaning only in so far as they belong to the whole.
If you look at them from the point of view of physical science,
they cease to be parts; they become atoms and electrons. Thus
you have to pay a price for the exactness that you get in the
chanical science builds
the whole from the parts, and there
is
mechanical statement.
The inadequacy of this statement of reality greatly impressed
Bergson, and to offset it he turned to the nature of the process
of consciousness for his clue. The terms "extensive" and "intensive" have no significance for mechanical physics. All particles are alike.
Consciousness does have a definite intensity and
a definite extensity.
What
is its
inner
reality.'*
What
is it
that
and what is the
relation of the judgments that refer to it and those which science
uses in referring to the outer world Bergson finds a number of
characters which pertain to this inner world which have no significance for the outer. The most important of these are two
that have already been mentioned: the experience of the interpenetration of our states of consciousness, and the reality of
intensity and extensity in inner experience.
The statement that one experiences a certain brilliance has
no meaning for the physicist. He cannot deal with brilliance
any more than he can deal with color. Experiences of brilliance
are qualitative experiences. You cannot say that your experience of the brightness of a Hght is equal to your experience of
one does
realize in this field of inner experience,
.^
[310]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
the combined brilliance of three lights. In regard to certain ex-
made to carry on such analyses.
has been found that the addition of a certain fraction of a weight
I think it is one-fourth, according to the law
periences attempts have been
In weights
Weber
it
you a qualitatively distinct experience. But even here it is impossible to get any constancy of
statement from the point of view of inner experience. It is im-
of
is
sufficient to give
possible to completely control
then ask what
is
all
the conditions outside and
going on in consciousness.
consciousness directly.
And when you do
ments of your experience related
in
that,
ways
used in dealing with the outer world.
You have
you
different
to go to
find the ele-
from those
The fundamental
ence found between these two types of experience
That
is
differ-
that the
they have a span,
they have duration. This sort of consciousness has a peculiar
inner experiences interpenetrate.
is,
disregard for certain important philosophical problems. It
ig-
nores the epistemological difficulty. It refuses to take account
Bergson approaches the problem of
knowledge from the point of view of biology, and what he finds
is that knowledge answers to a stream of interpenetrating states
of consciousness each of which draws into itself the nature of the
past and projects its own nature into the future. Thus they
of a bifurcated world.
achieve a span, a duree.
But of what importance
is
termines the nature of time.
this duration? First of
Tim^
is
not simply the
all, it
sum
de-
total
number of temporal units. It is a process, and
must be conceived as a process or its essential character is lost.
of an indefinite
In the second place, this being the distinguishing character of
our inner experience, the relation of penetration which characterizes it passes over into the character of the object. This
means, of course, that time has a new significance in the outer
world. The basic philosophical question, as Bergson sees it, is
this: Shall we take time seriously, shall we recognize the import
of duration in experience itself? The answer which he gives to
this question is affirmative. The fact of an event in the time
series
means the recognition of duration
as a reality in itself, as
THOUGHT
something that
is
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
A
going on.
passage which
is
always taking
the necessary precondition for the appearance ofparts.
place
is
You
could not single out individual temporal events unless
there were a continuous passage, a duration, in which they appear. Here, again, we meet the necessity of recognizing the
whole as the condition of the parts. This reality which is going
on, says Bergson, has to be taken seriously. It cannot be presented in terms of mathematical analysis. In the latter, all we
can do is to break up the series into minute elements and look at
these as points. But this is not the process. Thus Bergson tries
to seize upon an inner process in reality which will correspond to
the process in our inner experience.
But the mathematician will ask if Bergson has been fair with
it not possible for him to take time seriously in the
Bergsonian sense? Is not his description of reality one in which
processes are recognized and dealt with as important aspects of
him. Is
the whole? Let us substitute for the older concept of space such
a one as Whitehead's.
extension
is
that
it
The only
thing that you can say about
extends over. Such a statement obviously
about a continuum. Now, a continuum can be broken up.
Take this table, for example. It is a continuum; you can break
is
it
up
into parts.
Now
add
to this idea of extension, of a con-
tinuum, the idea of time as a fourth dimension. What you get
then is not merely a spatial spread but a temporal spread. That
is, you get duration. In this latter case we now have an actual
process in nature. Thus, Bergson's insistence that duration is
an attribute of inner experience only, and that since the world
by science, is a static world it cannot be the source from which this inner duration is obtained, is
not wholly adequate. The mathematician has presented us with
a picture of a world which has just the type of spread, of duration, that Bergson says is requisite if we are to get at its real
nature. The thing that Bergson dislikes in the scientific procedure is essential to it only for purposes of description and
outside, at least as presented
analysis. In this aspect,
it is
true that science,
and particularly
mathematics, gives us static independent particles.
[312]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
For example, one of the most useful of
cepts
that of the limit.
is
all
mathematical conto which the
The ultimate element
mathematician retreats, as Whitehead points out, is the limit.
As an object we deal with the table as having extension. It has
not only extension in space but extension in time; its extension
lasts through this hour. We conceive of the table as a part of a
world of passage. It is passing; in its temporal dimension it has
an extension that cannot be defined in an instant any more
than
spatial extension can be defined in terms of points.
its
But when we undertake
scientific problems,
sively smaller
we
to analyze this table in terms of certain
find that
and smaller
it
can be broken up into succes-
bits of extension.
We
reduce this ex-
tension by getting something that extends over, something
is apart from the table. To take the analogy of boxes, we
which are contained within other boxes until we
boxes
get
finally approach a limit. We never get the limit because we
which
can always think of another box being within the smallest that
of up to that time. Thus, if you take a certain
we have thought
portion of extension and consider
its
quantitative characters,
be of a table, an electrical charge, a
momentum, or what not, you can successively take smaller and
smaller portions of it. These can be constructed into a quanti-
whether
tative
this extension
series
reached;
Now
it is
which approaches a
limit.
This limit
is
never
ever more closely approached.
series in
the mathematician does his best to state his law of the
terms of such
limits.
They can never be
gotten in our
Here you are dealing with
an ideal situation. The mathematician realizes that it is ideal.
But he can get a better statement of what is going on in the
process through this method of postulating an ideal situation
which can never be found in actuality than he can by turning to
the immediate process as it is going on. These ultimate, static
particles against which Bergson utters so severe an indictment
are ideal particles in terms of which we get the laws which we
find in nature. There is no such thing as a point or an instant
in the static sense. They_a.re_constructs which we use in so far
experience, but they can be thought.
[3^3]
THOUGHT
as
we
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
are seeking a certain sort of simplicity, a simplicity that
makes
The law
possible to get a statement of a law.
it
then tested
is
dis-
covered in the ideal situation, but it is
to see if it works. It is taken out and put up against the
object, against the process it is designed to describe. Thus,
when we come back
as an
object in
we
to the table,
see
it
in reality
described as at rest,
which the particles have no
added
velocities
But after the scientist has gotten hold of his law in
way, he comes back to the table and deals with it as an object whose particles are in motion, as an object which itself revolves around the sun, for example. It is an object which has a
passage. Thus we get the Bergsonian duration in the external
world. It is not duration in the Bergsonian sense, because it is
not duration from the standpoint of an inner experience. The
duration with which the scientist deals is an objective duration.
to them.
this
The
It belongs to the object.
it;
to see
it
we may have
object
may
we
look at
But that
reflects
be fixed as
to stop the process.
a limitation in our method. It does not imply that process,
passage, duration, are excluded from the nature of things and
made
subjective.
Whitehead comes back
Bergson
faces.
to
somewhat the same problem that
tries to seize upon an
But, whereas the latter
inner process, the former tries to present the picture without the
distortion
which the other emphasis implies. The world of the
is a world of
physical sciences, in so far as they are analytic,
external relations.
side us.
Nature
is
But that is not the picture of what lies outcomposed of structures: atoms, stellar gal-
axies, tables, living beings
of each abiding within
carries
thought
itself.
all
these are organisms, the reality
The
analysis, the quest for limits
us back to elements out of which the whole
to be built up.
thing that
lies
But these
within each thing;
are not the whole. It
it is
is
be
some-
The characters
The atoms carry no
a process.
of the object are not present without
ions unless there
may
is
it.
a process; the living thing does not live un-
less there is a process.
Natural science deals with a reality of
such structures whose essence involves process.
[314]
The
reality of
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
the
atom abides within
It is
itself.
not affected by any process
of dissection, of analysis. Natural science continually brings
us back to a reality in which there
must be process
if
reality
is
to
have the characters which belong to it. Physical sciences, even,
are dealing with processes which are going on. But they find
they can most effectively get hold of them by setting up ideals
such as the idea of limit. Whitehead sums the whole question up
by saying that any structure which we find in nature is an organism. If this statement is correct, if this is an adequate account
of the reality with which the physical scientist is dealing, then
Bergson's position that
processes as such
The world
at
is
it is
only in an inner process that we find
incorrect.
an instant
a pure fiction.
is
an organization of perspectives.
these
perspectives
exist
in
their
We
The
have
natural order
is
to recognize that
relationship
to
organisms.
Process must be preserved as an ultimate part of reality. How
the process appears depends upon the position of the organism
from whose perspective
it is
reported. These perspectives can be
got only in terms of a process in which they have their locus.
All these aspects are essential to reality, the latter being nothing
more than the sum total of the former. It is my opinion that
you have to recognize not only the organism but also the world
as
having
its
reality in relation to the organism.
organized_in relation to each organism. This
The world
is its
is
perspective
from that point of view. Reahty is the total of such perspectives. Now Bergson is right in insisting that if there is such a
thing as Hfe or consciousness, anything to which a rhythm belongs,
we have
to think of this as being in the nature of reahty.
point at which he deviates from Whitehead is his inabihty
to discover this process elsewhere than in the inner experience.
Bergson's point of view is justified when we reahze that there is,
The
which is due not to the
differences of velocity
changes
but
to
recognition of qualitative
It is his desire to get inside this process, and he finds his clue
in the process of inner experience as distinct from the statement
in the physical processes, a distortion
about reality which
is
presented by the exact sciences. These
[315]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
sciences distort reality through their quantitative presentation
of
The
it.
real
is
qualitative,
and you cannot get quality at an
whether it be color, melody, or
instant. It occurs over a period,
the ionization of an atom.
For the same reason that he
finds the static statements of the
exact sciences inadequate, Bergson also turns
away from
sociational psychology. This describes the conscious
the as-
life
as a
attempts to account for the
to
fact that a certain book happens
appear in memory through
series of separate, distinct units. It
mere
association;
it
seeks to find the causes of an act in terms
of similarity, contiguity, and so forth.
Thought,
But
this is inaccurate.
presumes an organization prior to
Neither
can
its eventuation.
an act be explained in terms of
pleasure and pain. These belong to the end of the act. Statements of this sort are superficial. They are useful in determinas well as conduct,
ing certain relations of things in thought, just as the static picture of the world has
you get below
its
use in the physical sciences. But
which
is
you
this surface account,
states interpenetrate each other.
You
find that the
when
mental
can always separate that
characterized by this interpenetration, but the rela-
is not that of mere contiguity.
So you see, from every point of view the Bergsonian statement
is one of interpenetration. All you have is a set of processes.
tionship of states of consciousness
The
real
is
a set of continuities.
This takes away the element of determination which has been
a constant charge of the philosopher against the scientist, as
Kant indicated
earlier.
Here Bergson turns again
to
an inner
experience, this time to the experience of the living organism.
determination of its goal. The question is
freedom is an expression of an accumulative
set of experiences which work from behind, or whether in some
sense this freedom is the result of future conditions, that is, is
influenced by ends still hidden in the unrevealed future. According to the mechanical statement, the past is gone and the
future is not yet here. Therefore, the future cannot determine
what the change is going to be. The mechanical statement is unIt has freedom
whether or not
in the
this
[316]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
able to give us the reflection of the future into
And
yet this
the essence of conduct. It
is
is
what
going on.
is
directed toward
goals, ends which, while not yet actual, are operative in the de-
termination of the directions which conduct shall take. The
organism is free in the selection of its goal. Conscious selection
quite as really influenced by what is yet to be as it is by what
has been. This leads Bergson to turn again to experience to see
is
just
what
it
really
is like.
terpenetration there
is
He
finds that in its characteristic in-
no sharp, knife-edge separation between
The interpenetration of experience does go
future. The essence of reality involves the future as
to itself. In this way he rescues freedom. The coming
past and future.
into the
essential
of the future into our conduct
dom.
We may
is
the very nature of our free-
be able to get the reason for everything
we do
mechanical statement; but to see 7
conduct as selective, as free, we must take account of that which
is not yet in position to be expressed in terms of a mechanical
statement of events which follow one another as a series of
atomic experiences.
But, again it seems that Bergson has failed to recognize that
this process upon which he lays so much stress must be recognized wherever an effort, a process, is essential to the nature of
after the act, according to the
the object.
atom,
for
future as
the description he
is
makes must hold
just as
much weighted
for the
with the
more
specifically "organic" structures. In his
Memory he
again deals specifically with the psycho-
it is
Matter and
logical
Thus
which the present
for
problem of the mind and body. Here we have the ques-
Nerve
But there
tion of the function of the nervous system.
cells
may
answer to the seat of certain excitations.
is,
no discovered relationship between a certain sensation of color
and the excitement of a certain nerve cell. There is nothing in
the path of nerve current from one cell to another, and then to
another, and so on, which answers to the appearance of color
as such. The functional process is one of action, and here you
have nothing which answers to the static character of the sensation itself. Bergson points out in reference to these static con[317]
as yet,
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
tents of sensation, the reporting in consciousness of successive
qualities, that the response in
each case serves as the selection
of the stimulus. In other words, the older statement, which put
the stimulus
first,
made
it
the condition, the cause of the re-
You
sponse, had, so to speak, put the cart before the horse.
cannot deal with psychological data adequately if you insist
on the causal, associational statement in regard to them. We
are at any moment surrounded by an indefinite number of
possible sensations.
Which
of these will be picked out
decided in terms of the response that
is
is
de-
already being made.
There you have the future, the conclusion of the act, implied in
what is now going on but which is not yet achieved, coming in
to set up the conditions in terms of which stimuli shall arise.
This mechanism selects certain responses; it selects the stimuli
which shall be effective. The inadequacy here, as I indicated a
moment ago, is that this is an account not only of living organisms but of every object which involves a process. It can be
said equally of the atom. Out of the total field in which the ob-
may
respond in terms of processes that are already set up
are the conditions for its acting in one way or another.
Partly through this limitation, this failure to extend suffi-
ject
within
it,
ciently his doctrine to include
all
processes in reality, Bergson has
to face the alternative of stating his world not in terms of
is
going on but in terms of images.
any other way, according
our
way
into
it,
we
when we
stop the process which
is
what
cannot get to reality
to him, because,
being. In this, his approach
is
We
is
in
try to think
requisite to its
not unlike that of Locke. Bergson
interested in the organism which as such has this selective
On
character.
scientist, a
particles.
the one hand he sees the world of the physical
world which he describes as a world of physical
On
the other
hand
is
the experience of the individual
through which he reaches the hypotheses which the scientist sets
up as a thought structure. This is the idealistic picture. Both of
these Bergson tries to avoid by turning to a world of images.
Our perceptive world is one which centers about
The more distant the object imaged, the more
[318I
the organism.
indifferent its
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
characters.
Take
from a moving
the illustration of your perception of objects
train.
rapidity, while those
The
real process
is
The
objects near at hand change with
which are
far
away
are relatively stable.
revealed to us in immediate perceptual ex-
But over against this we have a world of objects
independent of the organism and by which we correct
our perceptual experience. This latter world, the world which
science analyzes, was there before the organism appeared. How
does Bergson set about to fit these two worlds together.''
The perceptual world, says Bergson, is a world of knowledge.
It appears as a representation in the cognitive sense. The image
perience.
which
is
is
All the conduct of
a cognitive representation of something.
mapped out in your central nervous system.
an enormous number of possible reactions. But there
the organism
There are
is
nothing in the central nervous system which answers to the
structure of the representation. You cannot find the representais
you find sensitivities. You find nothing in it which
answers to the representation of this table as such, for example.
The table is not in our heads. What is there is what we are
tions there;
it: read on it, sit on it, eat from it. Whenever
change my position, I change my perceptual world. All the
stimuli change because of the relation of the organism to them.
They are expressed in terms of our reactions. We make the
world from the point of view of our reactions to it. If you state
the organism in terms of a mechanism, you get the logical relationship between the perceptual world and the scientific world.
Your perceptual world is a statement of the scientific world in
terms o^fj^our possible reaction to it. This is Bergson's ap-
going to do about
I
The sensation is a clue; it helps us to pick out the
memory image which we will use in action. This memory image
proach.
had ho place
in the scientific world.
Yet
it
plays a great part in
the determination of stimuli; and this determines the world to
which we
shall respond, the
world which
will
be presented in our
perceptual representations at the present and which will bethe memory images of the future. These images will then
play the same role in regard to the multitudinous stimuli from
come
[319]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
which are pertinent to what
then going on. Thus the future image, which has no place in
which our conduct
is
IN
will select those
the scientific world, plays a great part in actual experience.
Bergson starts off with a freedom which is there for all the
world of images. This gives the world the meaning it has for us.
By including within this world of images the future as well
as the past, Bergson hopes to have established not only the fact,
but also the efficacy, of freedom. But we must examine into
more deeply. How does it
happen that we have perceptions and yet only incomplete repthe nature of these images a
resentations of reality
if,
as
little
Bergson contends, these perceptions
are really representational? Perception
ence, he says.
Thus he has
is
a restriction of experi-
to bring in other aspects than those
which he has thus far stated. The problem, he says, has been
to add to the perceptual experience something that is not there.
This is an insoluble problem. It is far easier to diminish the
content of what is given than it is to add something to it that
is not there. Thus, in undertaking to explain how our perceptions are called out from reality, he starts out with what he
calls "pure perceptions," Perceptions arise only in so far as
objects affect the bodily organism. These perceptions represent the interrelations, the interconnections, of the rest of the
universe.
verse
is
He
accepts the theory that every particle of the uni-
interrelated with every other particle. Perception repre-
sents the passage of the different forces of the universe.
The
organism is distinguished from all other objects in that it
an indeterminate center which serves as a focal point for the
vital
is
processes in reality.
When
certain processes, certain activities,
reach the nervous system, they are checked. This checking of
the processes which are going on in nature seems to Bergson to
be the essential character of the living form. This characteristic
involves not simply the selection of stimuli but also a stoppage
of the process of experience itself until a decision in regard to
future activity has been reached. He does not elaborate the
ground
flict
for this stoppage,
but
it
may
of the different sensibilities.
[
320
be stated in terms of a con-
The organism has
]
tendencies
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
which would lead
Out of
stimuli.
it
to react in different
ways
different
to
these different tendencies arise conflicts which
require deliberation.
This deliberation means
that
the
life-
process has got to be held up, so to speak, until the various
possible responses have been held passive long
selection to be
will
made among them. This
is
enough
for a
the difference which
be most immediately noticeable in comparing a living
organism to a stone. The part of the response which is held up
in this way, Bergson says, constitutes the representation; in
i
other words, it is the conscious perception. If it were not for the /
checking, we would perceive the whole universe.
Thus we are really brought to the core of the whole doctrine.
The implication clearly is that our conduct, in so far as it is not
conscious, in so far as it simply goes on as a part of an inclusive
process, is sensitized, so to speak, to the whole of reality. Could
we catch it in that condition, we would see the nature of things
as they really are. But the way into that vision is not through
conscious reflection. That stops the process. Consciousness
arises
only when our impulses lead us into conflict
conflict that
must be solved before conduct can go on effectively. As long as
conduct is held up, we get conscious representations of the
stimuli which are relevant to the solution of the present difficulty. But we have representations only of these. In selecting
some, we neglect and ignore others. If we are to catch reality at
its
we must
core,
catch
it
turn to a more instinctive level.
while the process
is
going on. Since this
consciousness, Bergson says that consciousness
We
must
impossible in
is
inadequate.
is
this we are directed to pure perception, that is, to the
perceptions which would show us the total interpenetration of
Through
things,
were we able to become aware of this inner process. Conwhen the process is checked, and
scious perception arises only
thus never gives us the "inside" of
"intuition."
Only
which comes with
it,
so to speak.
We must
use
intuition can save us from the distortion
reflection. In other
words, Bergson
is
inter-
ested in intuition as opening the door to another type of meta-
physics than
^
'
that which
can be gotten through reflection,
[321
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
through scientific description. This is why his. system is ultimately an irrationalism.
Paralleling this field of pure perception is another, the field of
pure memory. Here again, as in the case of pure perception, if
the influence could go through, there would be no image, no consciousness. Just as there are many objects about us to which
we
we
memory images which
were an undifferentiated field of memory
adjust outselves without perception, situations to which
give only slight attention, so there are
are present, as
which never
if
there
rises to the level
of reflection. These images are
present as a part of the ongoing process, but their efficacy
is
not
required in setting up the process by which stimuli are selected
out; they are not required as means to the direction of our conduct. Therefore, like pure perception, pure
memory
represents a
more fundamental aspect of the basic process. Our conmemories are an expression of the selection that we make
among the stimuli presented. Pure memory, on the other hand,
answers to the whole of our experience, as pure perception answers
to our instinctive contact with the whole of reality. It is not
connected with our central nervous system. It must be independent of this system, for the central nervous system is itself
simply one of the images. Pure memory is, of course, as different from memory as it enters into our experience as pure perception is from ordinary perception. The function of the central
nervous system is the same in each case it is a selecting and
deeper,
scious
dissecting organ.
This brings us to another individual and interesting point of
Bergson's position. This dissection of experience that goes on
under the influence of the central nervous system and which
gives us the world of ordinary perception and which calls up
our usual memory images is a materializing process. His doctrine involves an assumption of a world of images over against
the customary psychological doctrine, which assumes that sensations and memory images are functions of the central nervous
system. This is, of course, true of ordinary perception and memory in so far as each is a result of the process of selection which
[322]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
is
carried out in the central nervous system.
Even
here,
how-
not the one ordinarily presented. The selecspeaks is something very different from
which
Bergson
tion of
ever, the relation
the process that
is
is
implied in the idea of the functional relation-
ship of the central nervous system and the images presented.
The images are a part of the process
memory, which are themselves not
of pure perception and pure
the result of any structure
within the organism but a part of the world of images in which
the representations of the organism and of the central nervous
system are included. These particular images are caught at one
moment and then another. Having been selected, presenting,
as they do, the stoppage of the process, they are mechanized
bits. Using Bergson's illustration, they are the dead fragments
of an exploded shell through which the process must keep pushing on, only to reach a new point of conflict in which the same
materialization occurs again.
The
process itself
is
interrelation of the parts of the universe so that
common
reality.
the complete
all
share in a
According to Bergson, the philosopher has
been led astray by the analysis of the scientist into thinking
that the conceptual object
On
is
a clue to the real nature of things.
the contrary, these are not concepts of anything; they are a
part of the process of the materialization which occurs in perception.
I
The
object
is
there as a reflection back of the process.
must confess that what
this "reflection
back"
is I
am
unable
to isolate.
It is interesting in this connection to note that the world of
images which Bergson presents is adequate for scientific statements. Scientific objects are objects of hypothetical character;
and, as such, they have imaginable contents which are essential
to the hypothesis to which they belong. At least this is the way
I see it. Scientific hypotheses vary constantly. The test of
them comes back finally to the test of our own experience.
Now the question is whether or not conceptual objects appear
in our hypotheses without any imaginable content. I do not see
any reason for abandoning the imaginable world with which
Bergson deals. Our
scientific
experience always implies the dis-
[323]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
tance experience and the contact experience. What the distance experience is, is immaterial to the imagination. The
microscope and the telescope extend our powers of contact in
two very notable directions. But imagination goes beyond
them. The electron, if not the atom, is conceived in the imagination. These are not, at least as yet, contact experiences.
This simply means that some sort of distance experience is esgential. The problem, then, is of the nature of these concepts.
Concepts are not supposed to involve any necessary imaginable stuff. The concept is defined in terms of the conditions
under which a process of analysis is carried on. Here you get a
conceptual account without filling your concepts out with stuff.
Does the reality of the object involve the effective occupation
of space as revealed by the contact experience.^ You cannot
have a concept which is itself an object. It is a concept of
something, conceivably of a matter that occupies space. The
contact experience would give the material stuff which answers
to the distance experience.
But
can give no exact statement of
at least
size, for
we
are sure that
we
example, of the stuff
who points out that
no absolute size to which the material universe could be
reduced. Then, too, the scientist sets up a noumenal world
of the contact experience. It
there
is
Poincare
is
which Hes beyond contact experience. It is true that some of the
relativists, notably Einstein, assume that our spatial time world
is entirely relative to the individual. Such a doctrine gives to
each individual his
own
world. But
among
these worlds
we
find
uniformities which seem to lead us even here to the necessity
of setting up a noumenal reality the events and interrelations
lie beyond our own experience. It is this problem which
Bergson proposes to meet through his doctrine of the world as
images; and, as I said before, I do not see any reason for abandoning this imaginable world.
Where Bergson gets into his greatest difficulty is in failing to
of which
see, or at least to state
adequately, that the reflective part of
is the source of our inadequate representaonly one part of the whole process which he
consciousness, which
tions of reality,
is
[324]
VITALISM; HENRI BERGSON
identifies
with analysis. Bergson
insists that objects are in ex-
without our being
in pure experience, so to speak
aware of them. Becoming aware of an object is an analytic
process. Of course, if your fundamental position is that when
we know things we tear them to pieces, then you are going to
have distortion. But if you have objects in your experience
which you can enjoy as well as analyze, the necessity of the
intuitive relation seems, to me, to disappear. In other words,
Bergson's immediate intention furnishes the blind spot in his
perience
philosophy.
He
fails
to see that the flow, the freedom, the
novelty, the interpenetration, the creativity,
sets
upon which he
such store, are not necessarily limited to the interpenetra-
tion of experiences in the inner flow of consciousness.
also be gotten in
that the objects of experience have the
tration, the
same
They may
an objective statement just as soon as we see
same type of interpene-
essential spread, as that
covers in our inner experience; as soon as
which Bergson
we
dis-
see that the ideas
which we get in reflection, the objects which we get in science,
and against which Bergson is particularly vehement, are the
result of analysis and are not presumed to be reports of the
nature of the objects themselves. It
Bergsonian philosophy which,
has^
mos t
efi^ectively
made, up
it
is
this correction of the
seems to me, Mr. Whitehead
to the present at least.
i^S
CHAPTER XV
SCIENCE RAISES PROBLEMS FOR PHILOSOPHYREALISM AND PRAGMATISM
WE
TURN now
from the Bergsonlan philosophy to the
realistic movement and its reaction on modern science. This realistic movement is, in a sense, a con-
^'^
tinuation of the rationalism of the eighteenth century, that
which went back to the logical structure of the object of knowledge. Over against this rationalism was the empirical doctrine
represented by the English school Locke, Berkeley, and Hume.
The
as
It
empirical doctrine dealt with the structure of the object
appears in our qualitative experiences. It was interested
in the
content of the object rather than in
its
And
form.
this
school attempted to get the structure, the form of the object,
out of the relation of the different elements as they appeared in
sensation, in impression, in experience.
trine started with a certain structure
rationalistic doc-
which belongs
mind was supposed
to the ob-
have immediate knowledge. The empirical school started with the experiences that came through the senses, and tried to find in the association of such experiences the details of the structure of objects.
That structure was largely expressed in two conceptions: one
of cause and effect, and the other of substance and attribute.
The critical doctrine of Kant, you remember, recognized both
elements. And still, Kant's leanings were more toward rationalism than toward the empirical side. He assumed that the
mind must give the form to the object, but this structure was
one which was simply a form of the mind and not a form of
things-in-themselves. The mind had the forms of the categories,
twelve in number, of which the important ones were substance
and attribute, and cause and effect. The empirical school had
ject itself; and, of course, the
i.
The
[326]
to
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
attempted to show how mere association of the different experiences with each other would lead to the appearance of such
conceptions as that of cause and effect and of substance and
attribute. Kant recognized that these must be logically ante-
cedent to the object. There could be no object except in terms
of substance and of cause.
The
recognition that these forms
came from the mind
led to
the idealistic school that undertook to regard the whole of the
world as a structure of the mind, applying not simply to categories already fixed in the mind but to the very evolution of
the categories themselves.
The
evolution in this case was that
of a^self that thought the universe.
When we come
school,
we
to the situation after this
find that people
had abandoned
Romantic
this
idealistic
conception of
the self that thinks of the world, but that they retained these
two phases of experience, the form and the content. The realistic school undertakes to come back to the formal side of the
object, only it approaches it from the standpoint of a new conception, that of the more modern mathematics and logic. These
conceptions are of the relations which lie between the ultimate
elements of things. They were conceived of not as forms of the
mind but
as relations that exist in the world. Neither are they
regarded as
the, association
of states of consciousness with each
other, as the empiricists conceived of them. Until
skeptical statement of Berkeley
sumed that
we
get to the
and Hume, the empiricists
as-
there were relations which answered to the relations
which arose in the mind, that is, relations in the world, such
as cause and effect, that answered to the association of one
experience with another. Of course, they could not prove any
such connection, and Kant's critical philosophy came in to
present another point of view.
tlhe
realists,
on the other hand, as distinct from the propo-
nents of these two positions, believe that the relations of
ele-
ments with each other are directly cognized, directly perceived.
They are there^ And the relations form some of the elements
which are discovered in analysis. If you take an object of knowl[3^-7]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
edge and analyze it, break it up into its content, you will find not
only the substantive content, the impression in experience, but
also definite relations. And what the realist does is to attempt
to present both of these contents, those which appear in sensuous experience and those which we think, as relations given in
the world. The assumption is that we have direct knowledge of
these elements and of their relations in the world
itself.
The
no longer dealt with as acts of thought.^ In the
idealistic school the relations were always the impressions of the
realizing mind, so that relations were taken back to the thought
of the self. Our own selves were parts of the Absolute Self.
The realist, on the other hand, assumes the relations as simply
there. We think them; and if we think them, they must be
there, for we must be thinking something. The something we
think is Being. Whether it has existence or not depends on
whether it is located in our spatial, temporal experience.) Existence is the relation with reference to which other relations are
found actually in spatial, temporal experience. But we can
think relations which are not in these forms. We can think of
various relations existing between things but which do not
exist. They must have being, otherwise we could not think
them. We have, then, direct relationship or cognitive relationship with the objects of experience and their forms.
The interest of the realist has been in this process of analysis,
of breaking up the object of knowledge into its various elements,
with the isolation of the connection as well as of the things
themselves, carrying with this the doctrine of the external character of relations. The relations do not exist inside of that
which is realized; they exist between relata, between elements
that are connected with each other. Realism is indicated by
the term which implies that that with which we have cognitive
relations is real. It is not phenomenal. It is just what it aprelations are
pears to be in experience. But, to find out just what
must discover
it
as
it
it is,
we
appears in the analytic, rather than in the
synthetic, phase of experience.
The
synthetic phase of experi-
ence was dealt with by the empiricists under the head of "associ[328]
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
atlon." If experience
associated with
ence A, or one
it,
follows after experience A,
so that in the future
similar to
it,
it
becomes
when we have
experi-
the other experience, B, which had
been associated with it, arises also. It is purely a mental affair,
a connection of these various states with each other.
Thus reahsm gathers about the world-old problem of episte-
mology. The form which that problem took, you remember, was
dictated by the very development of Renaissance science,
which, as finally formulated, set up a world of physical particles
moving with reference
to each other in accordance with fixed
world had to be put over into consciousness. While there was supposed to be a world of these physical
particles moving in accordance with natural law, the question at
once arose: How does man get outside of the world of consciousness.'' How do you know there is anything else but what
laws.
The
rest of the
you have in your own experience? The epistemological problem has been thought out in this way, on this issue.
As I said, the answer of the realist is to give another statement of knowledge. ^Knowledge is finding a relationship between an object that lies in consciousness and an object that
hes outside of it.jlf you say, for example, that the table here
is nothing but a congeries of your own perceptions and images,
you have a table anyway. That is an object. You know it.
What you ask is how you can get from such an object which
lies simply in your consciousness over to the group of electrons
which constitute, as you say, the reahty of that table. And the
question is practically unanswerable when stated in this way.
There is no way of getting from the inner to the outer. All is
inside your experience; all is consciousness. W%at the realist
says is that this is an improper statement of what knowledge
mean^^JKnowledge is not going from an object already in experience over to something that lies outside of experience which
by definition you must reach. It is simply the relationship between the mind and that which it senses, that which it perceives. It is thought in a direct relationship, and that is all that
you can say about it. Vt is a fundamental, connotative, relation
[329]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
which exists between the mind and that which is known. We
have no problem of getting from the object which is in the mind
over to an object which Hes outside of the mind. What knowledge consists in is this relation between the mind and its object.
It is that shift in the conception of knowledge itself which is
characteristic of the realistic doctrine.
You
particular form of the question which
have said was praccan one get from con-
tically
unanswerable, namely,
"How
sciousness over into something that
form of the question
is
not the
not consciousness?" That
Renaissance science. The
between the mind and the object
arises out of
realist said the relationships
is
is
see this
an immediate, given relationship.
This was anticipated by the so-called Scottish school, who
said knowledge is immediate intuition. But their statement
was bound up more or less with the earlier form of the cognitive
doctrine.
They
still
kept the object in consciousness as the im-
mediate object of knowledge, and they
still
set off reaHty
beyond it. The reahsts said the object is simply the relationship
between the mind and the object, a direct cognitive relationship. That relationship in a certain sense guarantees the object,
and one of the great problems of the realistic philosophers is,
therefore, the problem of error. If knowledge is given in the relationship of the mind and its object, how can there be error?
And, of course, there are errors.
What has been of still more importance, perhaps, from the
standpoint of the
realistic doctrine
has been
its
recognition of
the objects of thought as they appear in the process of analysis.
one whose method has been analytic.
mathematics used, however,
It has sprung from mathematics
in the large sense of that term, the sense in which logic and
mathematics come together. The earhest of the group, as you
might call Leibnitz, goes way back to the Renaissance period.
He at least sketched out the implications of the realistic doctrine. He was one of the great mathematicians of the world, one
who had an implicit faith in the possibihties of analysis. If, he
said, you could take objects of knowledge and analyze them
["The realistic philosophy
I
y'
is
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
you get back to the ultimate elements, as, for example, in mathematical problems, those immediately given to
you, those which in one sense cannot be defined, which can
be set up as indefinable but which can be specified in the sense
of having their outlines given so that you can combine them
with each other, you would be able to build up all possible combinations. You could have charge of the ultimate elements,
and all the relationships that lie between, if you just pushed
your process of analysis to the limit and got these elements \
spread out before you, as a watchmaker spreads out the parts
of his watches. Then you could get all possible combinations y
so that
>
of things.
It is this
method with which
the realist operates.
He wants
back to those ultimate elements which are just there,
is no
question. If you could get back to those ultimate elements, and
particularly to the relationships that lie between them, they
would be the basis in terms of which you could make all possible
combinations. If you can discover those which are not contradictory, those which are tenable, you have the same assurance
of your results as in the immediate experience of the ultimate
elements themselves. The realists came back, for example, to
elements
final definitions of ultimate elements in the world
which we make use of in thought itself, the so-called "logical
constants." They came back to these ultimate elements and
then defined the relationships which could exist between them,
and in this way they could build up logical structures which
could not be questioned. They found out what the possible relationships could be between all these different elements. This
has a very abstract sound, and the achievements of these
mathematicians and logicians are abstract in the highest degree, but they are very penetrating; and they did, as I said,
bring together the fields of mathematics and logic.
They carried with them a doctrine which for a while belonged
to the realistic field but which is not so certain now. This is the
doctrine of the so-called "externality of relations." I have said
to get
given in immediate cognitive relation, and of which there
[33^^
THOUGHT
/the
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
realist analyzes, takes his object to pieces,
comes back
to
ultimate elements and the relationships which exist between
them.
He
isolates the relations froi^ the elements themselves./
In this activity the relation
is
something that we
will
a wire that connects two different objects together.
say
You
is
Tike
can put
up a wire and set up different relations between objects strung
on it. The relations as such do not affect the object. The relata
are connected by means of the relations, but the relations do
not exist by themselves. This emphasis upon the externality of
relations was brought out in contests between the realists and
the idealists, especially the neo-Hegelians of the latter group.
From
the standpoint of that latter group, the relation was an
internal, not
set
an external,
up between
affair.
It
was not simply a connection
different objects, separate relata, but
some-
thing which affected the very thing related. These relations
grew inside of things rather than being connections between
independent elements. Take, as an illustration, the Hegelian
doctrine of the social individual. We speak of him as having
certain relations. He stands in his social group as a citizen,
as a member of a family, of this and that group; and all these
groups represent various social relations. We might speak of
him as a point through which any number of social relations
pass. Now, these relations of the man to the people about
him are just what constitutes the man. His relations to the
members of his family make him what he is. We cannot say
that the relationship of father to son is one that lies outside
of the character of father and son. We cannot say that here
are two different objects connected by means of paternal and
filial relations. We cannot substitute something else for this.
It lies within the individual, makes him what he is. It is an
internal relation so far as the object is concerned. And, not only
is it internal, but it makes every individual entering into the
relationship different from what he was before that relationship
was entered into. You form an acquaintance with someonexjt
becomes a friendship. That relationship changes both of you.
You are different beings from what you were before. Now the
[33^]
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
Hegelian took this situation over into the whole of social and
spiritual reality. For him relations are internal, they are
thought of as being the very nature of the Absolute Self. The
relation
is
a process of relating. Relating
ing in the Absolute Self in which our
Thus
aspects.
relations
lie in
is
a process of think-
minds are simply
finite
the very nature of things them-
selves,,..,-.
Over against
this doctrine, the realists set
relations are external.
The
up one
in
which
process of analysis takes things
up ultimate relata; and the connections between
them, the relations as such, never change the character of the
thing related. You can say that new characters arise, but they
apart, sets
are simply the expression of the relations existing between
the separate elements. The separate elements themselves can
never be changed. Connect one number with another number,
and perhaps the result gives you a larger bank account, or
may
you have overdrawn your account. Those
But they do not change the character
of the numbers that are connected with each other by addition
and subtraction. These are ultimate elements which ferain always what they are. And the relations that exist are what they
are. You do not change the relata by their being related.
it
indicate that
are very important facts.
Thus
the realists accept cognition as a simple relationship be-
tween the mind and its object. Nothing can be said about it
it is an immediate relationship between these two.
Therefore, in so far as it exists, it presumably carries with it the
import of cognition, that is, it carries knowledge, and so the
except that
truth of the experience.
But
knowledge has
fundamental principle that of
have said, it had taken from
mathematics. It is a process which leads to the breaking-up of
the object of knowledge into its ultimate elements. The difficulty which the realist got into on this basis was to account, not
for knowledge, but for error. In the older theory the object was
given in consciousness as the immediate object of knowledge.
this
as its
analysis, a principle which, as I
That
is,
the organization of one's percepts, ideas, images,
[333]
mean-
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
they lay in consciousness, into the immediate object of
ings, as
where the epistemological problem was found in
sort of a relationship between this immediate
object of knowledge and the supposed real object outside. That
is what we would consider as answering to our perception of a
knowledge
setting
is
up some
table, for
example. If we state the table in terms of our ideas,
we can say that it constitutes an object of
or our perceptions,
knowledge, but that
it is
not the real object.
The
real object
is
a congeries of physical particles that do not get into experience
at
its
all.
From
analysis,
perience
the point of view of the realistic philosophy, with
knowledge
itself.
And
of the ultimate elements in theex-
is
thus the problem becomes one of account-
The
ing for error, for mistakes.
rnents themselves
wise
it
experience of the ultimate ele-
evidence of the object's being there; other-
is
could not be experienced. Knowledge
is
the relationship
between mind and these ultimate elements. Given this relationship, both mind and the ultimate elements are there. Meaning and cognitive value, as well as other values, are also objects
of knowledge. And they, too, have to be related and organized.
Remember,
mental point
lie
the external character of relations
in the position of the realist.
inside of the object. It
ultimate elements.
The
is
The
is
a funda-
relation does not
simply the connection between the
"meaning" of the object
so-called
is
nothing but an organization of the relations that he between
these different elements. For example, we have the relationship
of distance which exists between different objects and our con-
duct in experience. The groups of distance relations which we
find in experience give us the surface of this table, for example.
The groups which
represent the relation of the individual to
each corner, to the different
lines, the different
spots of color on
the surface, taken together, give us our general sense of the dis-
tance of the object, as an object, from the organism.
It
is
an
make it up.
we come back
organization of the relations which, together, go to
If
we want
to deal with the
meaning of the
their perspective.
We
object,
which compose it, and get them in
may make mistakes in the organization
to the various relations
334
^
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
of these relations, in the meaning they have. We see an eagle
soaring over our heads as we lie in the grass, and after a while
we become aware
of the fact that
it is
nothing but a gnat a
few inches away. There are mistakes also so far as the immediate experience goes, that is true enough. But we may also
make mistakes when we organize them into ultimate relationships.
But
this leaves yet
another group of elements in that experi-
The eagle to which I referred is, after all, something more
than a set of separate experiences. It is not only something
more than that; it is something universal. It is something that
is recognized in any eagle that we see. It is the same, the
ence.
concept of the eagle, the universal eagle; and it is not only a
universal, but it is a unity. We may break the unity up into
separate parts, but it is something that belongs to the concept of the eagle. These ultimate universals have to be recognized in their relationship to mind, especially the fundamental
universals that appear as logical constants.
Not only concepts
of this character, but also those of our sensuous experiences
the reds, the blues, the high and low sounds
and we have
to deal with
them
as such.
are
They
nized from a realistic standpoint as something that
cause
we
universals; (
have to be recog- )
all
is
there be-
think about them. If we think about them, there must
be something there to think about.
In the earlier statement which was given, the concept was
dealt with as a mental structure of some sort; it was thought of
something in the mind itself. We assume that that which lies
mind answers to something outside. The realist assumes
that our knowledge of the universals is, so to speak, the contact between the universals and the mind; we must put them
in the mind, but they must also have their existence outside.
And yet, many of these universals do not have an existence, in
our ordinary use of that term. We imply that a thing is at
some point and at some definite time when we say that it
exists. If we say a man exists, we locate and date him. If he
exists, he does so somewhere and somewhen. But the idea of a
as
in the
[33S]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
chimera, for example, does not exist anywhere or any when. It
That
very characteristic, of course, of the
chimera as such or of any other mythical animals, dragons, and
what not, that have played such large roles in mythology and in
the imaginations of men. They do not exist, and yet we think
about them. If we could regard them as just constructs of the
imagination and locate them in people's minds, we could account for their being mere mythical objects. You say there are
not any such animals; they do not exist; they are just mental
pictures which people have had of possible animals which
does not
exist.
is
proved to be impossible animals. But if you take the realistic
viewpoint, there must be something to think about some universal, at least
to which our mind turns and about which we
are thinking. There are a good many other things we think
about which do not exist. We puzzle our heads over them for a
long time, over perceptions which prove to have contradictions
in them. And yet we have been thinking about them. After all,
there must have been something. We talk about such things
they are; contradicas "round squares." They could not exist
tions in terms
and yet we can discuss them. As long as we
can think about anything, there must be something that answers to the process of thought, and yet many of these things
cannot be put into existence.
What this led to on the part of this realistic approach was the
recognition of a real being which generally goes under the name
of "subsistence" rather than of "existence." There is a world
which subsists, but does not necessarily exist. You can have
thought occupied in the recognition of the response to all the
elements in experience, and not only to these but to everything
we call "idea," that is, any universal. These subsist; some of
them exist. Thus, some of them do appear. To apply one of
the terms that is used, they have "ingression" into events. This
is Whitehead's term for the process. These eternal objects, in
the sense that they are outside of time, have ingression into certain events in so far as they constitute things. What you see
taking place is the emptying-out of the whole content of the
[336]
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
mind, as the Renaissance philosophers dealt with it, into the
world. It is a setting-up of mind as that which has cognitive
relationships with
all
these different elements, allowing the con-
struction to take place through the action of the mind.
But the
realist
has not been very strong on the constructive
To under-
or synthetic side. His interest has been in analysis.
stand this interest
we have
to go back, as
cated, to a mathematical background.
One
have already
indi-
of the greatest of
Bertrand Russell; another is Alfred Whitehead.
What they were interested in at first was the perfection of
mathematical theory. They were interested in carrying back
the mathematical process behind the immediate objects of the
physical world that we follow through their various changes.
Back of this lay the development of our modern mathematics.
Mathematics, for Kant, stood on a basis of Euclidean geometry
on one side and of the traditional arithmetic on the other.
KantTyou remember, believed that the forms of mathematics
were the forms of the mind. W'cll, not long after the time of
the realists
is
to work out geometries
axiom
in regard to parallels.
Euclidean
which contravened the
It was a question of whether more than one line could be drawn
Kant two mathematicians undertook
through a point outside that line. They
took different points of view, such as that there could be no
such line drawn or that there could be a number of them so
drawn. The interesting thing was that, starting off with such
parallel to another line
an axiom, that no lines could be drawn parallel or that there
could be an indefinite number of them so drawn, they could
build up perfectly consistent systems of geometry. This was
back to experience to find a world in which
they were true. Neither of these propositions, if true, conforms
to the Euclidean axiom. Nor does actual physical experience
conform as far as that goes. Of course, this does not go very far.
not, of course, going
You cannot
structed.
actually measure the distance between lines so con-
One mathematician
the experiment of setting
up
actually undertook to see whether
triangles or parallels
which could
be measured on the surface of the earth would hold, but he did
[337]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
not measure with sufficient accuracy to get any absolute con-
What
wanted to do was not to find
parallel lines which act like rails as you look at them. It was a
question of seeing whether you could assume that there could
be an indefinite number of parallel lines drawn to any line from
points outside that line, or if you could assume that there could
be no parallel lines. Whichever side you took, you had the basis
for a possible geometry. Whichever geometry is right in the
sense of describing physical nature, you can prove all the propositions in one or the other. If you come back to experience, socalled, it is, after all, that of one geometry only. Why cannot
clusions.
these people
there be others?
And then, of course,
is always the question as to whether
cannot actually follow hnes any great
length or distance. Do they actually tend to meet? We could
never tell if they did. We have another interesting speculation
about people who live in a two-dimensional space. Supposing
a person were of no thickness at all and lived on the surface
of a sphere. Then, if one started to throw something forward in
a straight line with sufficient force, it would hit him in the back
of the head. How can we tell whether the space in which we
live is of one sort or another? Supposing, for example, to give
another illustration, we say space is of indefinite extent.
What we mean is that, given (or setting up) any limit in space,
we imply something beyond it. It is indefinite. Or, supposing
we lived in a world which got cooler as we went away from
its center, and that in accordance with these conditions the
dimensions of things changed, so that the diameters would
shrink as they got farther away from the warm center. And
assume that the diameters of all objects shrank proportionally.
Then as we walked away toward the periphery of the world, we
would get gradually smaller and smaller as we got cooler and
cooler, and our steps would get shorter and shorter. In such a
system we could never reach the limit of the world. We could
have an indefinite world inside of a definite one; we would never
arrive at the limit; and yet we would never stop. Everything
space
is
curved.
there
We
[33^]
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
would become proportionately smaller
as
we went away from
that center.
The value
is given by Poincare
simply to show us that our
of such an illustration, which
in his Science
and
Hypothesis^
is
which has a right and left, an up and down, is
something that is entirely dependent upon our experience. And
we have no way of telling whether the world of our spatial experience corresponds to one geometry or another, whether the
world is actually Euclidean or non-Euclidean. It is something
that is not open to any proof, because our experience will always
spatial world,
lie
inside our
then?
They
own
world.
What
are these irrefragable difficulties,
are proofs for a geometry, provided that the axioms
of that geometry are true.
are true or not.
We
We
can never
say a straight Hne
is
tell
whether they
the shortest distance
between two points. We have some difficulty in defining a
straight line, but we cannot set it up as indefinable, and it comes
back to the statement that it is nothing but the shortest distance between two points. You have to assume it to define
On one
it. You come back to certain postulates you set up.
can
prove
world;
and
you
a
Euclidean
basis you will set up
certain conclusions in that world, prove that there
world.
All
is
such a
judgments are necessarily hypothetical judgments.
is a Euclidean world we cannot tell. We
whether the world actually has the dimensions that
Whether or not there
cannot
we
tell
think
it
has or the dimensions of a billiard
just as well set
world
in
up
one the
your units.
all
the relationships which
size of a billiard ball,
Why not?
Your
ball.
You
you have
could
in the
provided you reduce
proofs are dependent upon certain
is much easier to prove the Pythagorean
you actually have lines drawn in a Euclidean
fashion, a number of them, and work them out. But you are
not sure that there is such a Euclidean world. Well, now, is
there anything in that Pythagorean proposition which would
be true if there were no such Euclidean world? Would it be
possible to prove propositions of geometry, and of all mathe-
given postulates. It
proposition
if
[339]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
matics, without actually accepting the postulates of our
em-
world about us?
That is the problem the mathematicians were working on,
and what they did was to set up symbols which would be
pirical
most general and universal and just as few in number as possible. And by means of these and by using the simplest processes of logic, it was possible to prove a whole mathematical
science without introducing the postulates of our empirical experience.
You
can find
this
done
propositions worked out in
in the Principia
mathematica
mathematics is presented in
so-called "symbolic logic"; and the
of Russell and Whitehead. In
it
propositions there are propositions which,
if
translated into
Euclidean geometry, would give all the propositions of that
geometry, but give them in such a form that they are free from
the fixed postulates of our sensuous experience. We free ourselves from
all
that to a certain degree.
We
say that the world
which seems to have up and down, right and left, really does
not have these characters. What we mean by "up and down"
is the relationship between the object on the surface and the
center of the earth. In this symbolism you come back to a
larger, more effective analysis than that worked out in the past,
in which you have symbols that refer to universals and the
smallest possible number of indefinables. With these you work
out propositions that would be true in any world. You do not
know, for example, if they are true in the sense that they actually exist. That is the interesting thing, says Russell, about
mathematics. You do not know whether what you are presenting is true, and you do not know what you are talking
about. You abstract from the content of your postulates. You
set up certain indefinable elements and put relationships between them; and then you say that, if such and such a thing
exists, a certain result must follow. It was this most generalized form of mathematics which was worked out by these
mathematicians; and in accomplishing it, they went beyond the
logic of Aristotle, for
of relations."
example,
They produced
in
introducing the so-called "logic
a symbolic logic which
[340]
was a more
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
powerful instrument than the Aristotelian syllogism is. And
they reduced the content of our exact scientific knowledge to
the simplest form in which it could be expressed and to a form
which
is
valid in any sort of world to which you
may
wish to
refer.
They were somewhat
excited about their success. This
was
natural enough. If you can take the whole of the object of
mathematical science and trace it to a set of formulas which
much Hke the marks of which a stenographer makes
use, condense the whole of that to a relatively small number of
pages, and have all the content there, you are justified in getting
excited. You get a symbolic logic which is very much more effective than the older logic. If you invited twenty people to
dinner and some belonged to one religion and some to another,
some to one political faith and some to another, and some of
them disliked others, and yet you had to seat them about the
table so as to have everyone at peace with his immediate neighbors, you would have quite a job on your hands. If you ever
have such a job, I advise you to familiarize yourselves with
look very
symbolic
logic, for that will
enable you to state just what the
possible combinations are that
you can make.
enable
It will
you to arrange your guests in such a way
any unpleasant experience at the dinner. There are certain situations of that sort which make us aware of the practical value
in the use of symbolic mathematics. But I must confess that
beyond that, so far as practical things are concerned, its use has
been very slight. The achievements which symbolic logic makes
in the realm of thought are very impressive, indeed. But we
still go on thinking in terms of what has been called the "logic
that there will not be
of things," the logic of inference, that
and immortality:
therefore Socrates
all
men
is,
are mortal;
was mortal. That
is
the logic of Socrates
man;
up on the in-
Socrates was a
logic built
herence of certain qualities in certain substances, \yellj now,
the world
we
live in
is
a world of things,
continue to utilize will be a logic of things.
a powerful discipline, an apparatus
[
341
and the
logic
Symbohc
we
will
logic gives
which enables us to deal
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
with relations. But if you continue to work in a world of things,
I do not think that symbolic logic will be of any particular value
except in such problems as I suggested above.
What I have been trying to bring out was the background of
these realistic philosophers. They try to get rid of the epistemo-
problem by simply recognizing that knowledge is ji^ cognitive relation between mind and the elements. And jthen they
try to state the so-called "objects of knowledge" in terms of
their ultimate elements and the relationships between them.
And in order to do that, they have to assume the externality of
relations, that is, that there is a set of ultimate elements which
are related to one another as if by wires or strings. If you want
to handle such a number of ultimate elements and their relations, you have to have a very powerful sort of technique, such
as that which the symbolic logic gives you. So all these go
along together. The realists assume that knowledge is just a
relationship between the object and the mind. Then by analysis
logical
they break up the object into
all its
elements, set up cognitive
between mind and these elements and their relations,
and then connect them all together. They give you a technique
which enables you to handle these factors.
It is in this field that the realist is occupied. Things are, or
at least they have being. Elements, anything we think about,
have being; and our problem is, not to determine whether
some things have being and others not, but to determine the
relationships between these elements of being. And the relationships between these elements also are actually given. They
are realized. Things are real. There are different sorts of reality. That of existence, for example, of something located at a
certain point at a certain time. But things which do not exist
have being, that is, they have subsistence; and the problem is to
determine what that means. In this philosophy the problem of
relations
the universal as out there has to be recognized as present be-
cause universals can be thought about.
The problem
versal, as far as our sensuous experience
some
difficulties.
The forms
in
is
of the uni-
concerned, presents
which these universals appear
342
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
among
them
as eternal objects.
"critical realists"
them
For example, Whitehead
Another group, the so-called
Santayana, Lovejoy, and others refer to
different relata are different.
refers to
as "essences."
And
the question of the appearances of
these essences, these universals, in the object and the presence
of them in the
mind becomes
somewhat
difficult question.
We
something which constitutes a
mean
by
this term, otherwise we could
table. I know what you
not talk about the object in question. We attach a particular
word to it. We may call it by any word. But there is something
we think about, and it is universal. We also assume that it is in
this thing. What evidence have we of this.^ There must be such
a thing; otherwise we could not think about it. How do we get
it into this relationship.'' That presents problems which we are
not undertaking to follow out, but to criticize this philosophy I
want to give you the point of view of a group of influential
philosophers whose doctrine belongs to this period. If you want
a further account, take Santayana's Skepticism and Animal
Faith. These realists had something of the same confidence in
the mathematical technique that Kant had in the achievements
say, for example, that there
is
of Newton.
Philosophy has in this as well as in other centuries occupied
with the interpretation of what science has accomplished.
In modern times science and philosophy are separated from each
itself
other. Science reaches certain results. It tests them.
act
We
can
upon them. Philosophy has been occupied with the ques-
tion of meanings.
and can
of science. But
further
Some
philosophers
feel
that philosophy goes
criticize the propositions, the
as
a general rule
it
presuppositions
can be said that what
philosophy has been doing, especially since the time of the
Renaissance, is to interpret the results of science. Well, now,
mathematics has been going ahead at a frightful rate during
this last century, and the realists represent an attempt to interpret it from the point of view of its own technique. You get
very strange results looking at this development of mathematics from our empirical point of view.
[343]
THOUGHT
IN
Alongside of this
pragmatism
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
realistic
philosophy
we
find
another
which has developed out of a different aspect of
movements of the period. This doctrine has two
outstanding figures: one of them is William James, the other,
John Dewey. There are differences in the formulation of pragmatism on the part of these two men. That of James is to be
found in his volume entitled Pragmatism; that of Dewey, in
the scientific
statements in his Essays in Experimental Logic, and
more elaborate statement in his more recent book, Experiand Nature. Back of the work of both lies the common as-
his earlier
in a
ence
sumption of the testing of the truth of an idea, of a hypothesis,
by its actual working.
Our problem now is to put this statement in relationship to
the doctrines which we discussed earlier. In them the test of
truth
lies in
the coherence, the orderliness of ideas, the
way
in
which ideas fit into a general logical structure as it arises in the
mind, a mind which is not only a mind but also a creator of the
world, all minds being simply phases of a more general, an Absolute, mind. From this standpoint the world was the result of
the thought process of the Absolute.
Our thinking
the finite and imperfect elements of this process
cause a mere phase.
It
would be impossible
is
but one of
imperfect be-
for us to think of
the world in a true fashion because of our finite character.
But in proportion as our thinking is coherent, to that degree we
can assume that our mind approaches truth.
The point that needs particularly to be recognized in an approach to the pragmatic doctrine is the relationship of thinking
The undertaking of the Romantic ideahsts and the
was to present thought as that which discovered the
world. It had the distinct business of finding out what the nature of things is. That is, cognition is a process which arose, so
to speak, for its own sake. One is curious, one wants to know
the world; and knowledge is a simple getting of the nature of
to conduct.
rationalists
the world. Its tests
in the
from that standpoint, in the product or
is known. This is a copy theory of knowlmind the impression of that which exists
lie,
nature of what
edge; one has in his
[344]
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
may have a coherence theory such as that to
have referred above, that which fits into a structure
lies outside. The function of knowledge in either case is
to give as close a resemblance as possible to something which
lies outside the mind.
If we approach the world from the standpoint of the sort of
experience with which the psychology we have been presuming
deals, we can see that intelligence in its simplest phase, and also
outside; or one
which
which
in a later phase, really lies inside of a process of conduct.
animal, even the plant, has to seek out what
life.
It
has to avoid that which
is
dangerous
is
The
essential to its
for
it
in its life-
by driving down its
roots, in its adjustment to the climate. When you get into the
animal kingdom, you find much more adjustment and an environment which involves more dangers, in which the getting
process.
plant shows
its
intelligence
of food, the avoiding of enemies, the carrying-on of the process
of reproduction, take on the form of an adventure. Intelligence
consists in the stimulation of those elements
portance to the form
itself,
which are of im-
the selection of both positive and
negative elements, getting what
is
desirable, avoiding
what
dangerous. These are the ways in which intelligence shows
is
it-
self.
For example, the intelligence of the human form is one which
its abiHty to analyze this world by discrimination, and, through significant symbols, to indicate to other
forms with which it works and to the form itself what the elements are that are of importance to it. It is able to set up such
a structure of symbols, images, which stand for the object that
it needs. Thinking is an elaborate process of selecting, an elaborate process of presenting the world so that it will be favorable
for conduct. Whatever is its later function
it has one of knowledge, which is for its own sake in its earlier phases we have
intelligence, and then thought, as lying inside of conduct. That
is, the test of intelligence is found in action. The test of the object is found in conduct itself. What the animal needs is its
food, freedom from its enemy. If it responds to the right stimuli,
has arisen through
[345]
THOUGHT
it
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
reaches that food, that safety.
as to
whether
made such
has
it
The animal has no
other test
a proper selection except in the
You
can test your stimulus only by the result
is in answer to it. You see, that takes
the research method over into life. The animal, for example,
faces a problem. It has to adjust itself to a new situation. The
way in which it is going brings danger or offers some unexpected
possibility of getting food. It acts upon this and thus gets a
result attained.
of your conduct which
new
object; and
if its response to that object is successful, it
be said to be the true object for that stimulus. It is true
in the sense that it brings about a result which the conduct of
the animal calls for. If we look upon the conduct of the animal
form as a continual meeting and solving of problems, we can
may
find in this intelligence, even in its lowest expression, an in-
method" when this has been
developed into the technique of the most elaborate science. The
animal is doing the same thing the scientist is doing. It is
facing a problem, selecting some element in the situation
stance of what
which
There
may
is
we
call "scientific
enable
it
to carry its act through to completion.
inhibition there. It tends to go in one direction, then
another direction;
it
tends to seek this thing and avoid that.
and until they can be
cannot
The
only test the animal
go on.
reconstructed, the action
can bring to such a reconstruction of its habits is the ongoing of
its activity. This is the experimental test; can it continue in
These
different tendencies are in conflict;
action?
And
Take such
that
is
exactly the situation found also in science.
a problem, for example, as that of the radiation of
is assumed that that radiation is
due to the compression which comes with attraction. Then,
knowing what the mass of the star is, what the direction of attraction is, and the compression that follows from it, one can
the sun or of the stars. It
figure out
was
how much
figured out
some
heat the star can radiate.
in its present condition for a period of
years and that
fore
it
it
On
that basis
it
forty years ago that the sun has not been
more than twenty million
might be perhaps seventeen million years be-
became dark and
cold, so far as the earth
[346]
is
concerned.
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
Geologists, on the other hand, were turning back the pages of the
history of the earth and working out
its
history. In this process
they got various tests as to what the time periods had been.
And
all
these tests called for far longer periods than the astro-
was willing to grant. The former dealt in terms of a
hundred million years. In recent research we have discovered
a new test which is perhaps the most accurate of all; that is
the radiation of radioactive bodies. We know, for example, that
bodies of this type are continually breaking down. We can see
them doing it. In the dark we can see the sparkling which
represents a continual discharge of energy, the breaking-down
physicist
At first this process
was worked out, it was
of higher atomic structures into lower.
seemed to be indefinite; but when it
found that such a process in radium might last for several
hundred years. The rate of disintegration could be figured out.
We know something about the elements, the parts of the earth,
that are radioactive; and in that way we can determine what
the rate is at which certain minerals which result from such
a disintegration as this could have formed, how long a time
would be necessary to build them up. Taking this and all the
other tests, the scientists set up their theory of the history of the
world ^the geologist writing his history on one time schedule,
and the physicist writing his on the basis of another. We get a
clash here. One calls for a period of several hundred million
years; the other denies any period longer than twenty million
years. There you get a typical scientific problem.
What I want to point out is that it stops the scientist in his
process of reconstructing the past. You are reconstructing it on
one doctrine or the other. You cannot use both of them. And
yet there are facts which lie behind each of them. What is the
source of the energy of the sun? It is not burning up coal. It
undoubtedly produces heat by the very compression that follows from attraction. That is the only source of heat which can
be found. On that basis the age of the earth is twenty million
years.
And
yet, here
we have
a history which the geologist
and
the archeological zoologist and the botanist have been writing
[347]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
on the basis of other data.
And
the two stop each other.
The
process of writing the history of the earth cannot be continued,
because the two theories are in conflict with each other. You
have these exceptional situations arising over against each
What
other.
taking place
is
the recognition that there
is
is
another source of energy which has not been attacked, so to
speak, in the doctrine of the scientists themselves. This very
energy, which
make
is
found
in the process of radiation
which we
use of in our radium watches and clocks, represents a
source of energy which the suns
upon.
In
may
themselves be drawing
process of radiation, the sun
is actually turning
out more than four million tons of energy per square yard
every few minutes. It is using itself up. Its mass is passing
its
We know that light has
Of course, that weight represents just so much mass.
Mass must come from the radiation of the sun. The sun is
breaking down its own atoms and getting the energy that is
in them. We do not know just what the exact process is by
over into the form of radiation.
weight.
which this takes place, whether it is due simply to the immense crushing power of such a great mass as that at the center;
but v/e know that there is much energy in an atom. If you
could explode an atom, I think it is said that you could carry
the S.S. Leviathan across the ocean on the amount of atomic
energy found in a drop of oil ^perhaps it is two or three
drops if you like, I have forgotten the figures but there is an
enormous amount of energy shut up in the structure of the
atoms themselves.
Given such a problem as that, what does the scientist do.'*
He
proceeds to start to write his history of the stars as he finds
them, the giant and the dwarf stars, the white and blue and red
stars, in their different stages of evolution.
He
starts to write
of them on the basis of the hypothesis that these suns have
been continually expending the energy involved in their atomic
structure in the form of radiation. And that is brought, of
course, into its relationship with the geological and biological
history of the earth. Could one go on writing the history of the
[348]
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
and of the surface of the earth so that they do not come
into conflict with each other? It was found that there is plenty
of time provided under the now recognized form of expenditure
of the energy of the sun a hundred miUion years or so, instead of twenty million years. So the process of interpreting
the world, working out the scientific statement by means of the
stars
new hypothesis, could be continued.
Now, what constitutes the test of
of
the hypothesis?
The
test
that you can continue the sort of conduct that was going
it is
same
which the animal finds. If it
finds itself in a difficult situation and sees escape, it rushes ofl^
in that direction and gets away. That is a fair test, for it, of
on. It
is
the
sort of test
what we
call a hypothesis. It did not present ideas to itself in
terms of significant symbols, but it was a good working hypothesis. It could continue its action of living that way, where it
could not have continued
it
otherwise.
Well, in the same fashion, from a logical standpoint, the
sci-
engaged in stating the past history of the world, and
he comes up against this blank wall of insufficient time. Now,
when he collates the history of the surface and the history of the
which
a hole, so to speak
radiation of the sun, he gets a clue
entist
is
will let
him escape from that
That constitutes the
means that he can con-
difficulty.
test of the truth of his hypothesis.
It
tinue the process of stating the history of the world within which
he
is
living.
And, of course, the process of stating the world,
stating our past,
getting
That
its
is
a process of getting control over that world,
is
meaning
for future conduct.
the importance of the pragmatic doctrine. It finds
test of the so-called
these hypotheses.
its
"true" in hypotheses and in the working of
And when you
ask what
is
meant by the
"working of the hypotheses," we mean that a process which
has been inhibited by a problem can, from this standpoint, start
working again and going on. Just as the animal no longer stands
there, dodging this way and that to avoid its enemy, but can
shoot away and get out of danger, so the scientist does not
simply have to stand before a history which allows him only
[349]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
twenty million years and a history of two or three hundred
He can now continue the process of giving the
history of the world, having this conception of the source of
energy which had not been recognized before. Putting it into
beha.vioristic terms, what we mean by the test of the truth is
the ability to continue a process which had been inhibited.
A certain statement of the pragmatic doctrine implied that a
thing was true if it satisfied desire. And the critics of the doctrine thought that this satisfaction meant the pleasure one
could get out of it. That is, if a hypothesis was pleasing to an
individual, then it was true. What I have just stated is, howmillion years.
ever,
what
is
implied in this doctrine
that the
test of truth lies
continued working of the very processes that have been
checked in the problem. It is a pleasant thing to get going again
in the
we have been caught and shut in. It is a pleasant thing
have a new planet swim into our ken. But it is not pleasure
which constitutes the test, but the ability to keep going, to keep
on doing things which we have been trying to do but which we
had to stop. That is one phase of the pragmatic doctririe-:;:2the
testing of a hypothesis by its working.
The other phase I have touched on earlier. You see the attitude of which I have been speaking brings the process of
knowing inside of conduct. Here, again, you have a relationship between pragmatic doctrine and the behavioristic type of
after
to
psychology.
Knowing
this process.
Cognition
is
a process of adjustment;
is
it lies
within
simply a development of the selective
its environment and the readjustment that follows upon such a selection. This selection
we ordinarily connect with what we call "discrimination," the
attitude of an organism toward
pointing-out of things and the analysis in this pointing. This
is
a process of labeling the elements so that
each under
its
proper tag, whether that tag
you can
is
the finger, a vocal gesture, or a written word.
process
is
to enable
you
to reconstruct
refer to
a pointing of
The
thinking
your environment so
that you can act in a different fashion, so that your knowledge
lies
inside of the process
and
is
not a separate
affair.
It does
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
not belong to a world of spirit by
it is
itself.
Knowledge
is
power;
a part of conduct that brings out the other phase that
is
connected with pragmatism, especially in Dewey's statement.
This phase is its instrumentalism. What selection, and its
development into
reflective thought, gives us
the instruments
need,
we need
living in the largest sense.
to
is
the tools
we
keep up our process of
Knowledge
is
a process of getting
the tools, the instruments. Go back to the illustration I have
used above of the atoms as a source of energy. This concept
by means of which the length of the life of the
can be estimated. And when you have that, you can re-
becomes a
stars
tool
it to the age of life on the surface of the earth.
Perhaps the best statement to bring out the importance of
We
this instrumentahsm is the term "scientific apparatus."
but
the
scientist;
tools
of
think of that generally as the actual
we know that the term "apparatus" is also used for the ideas,
the units, the relations, the equations. When we speak of a
scientist's apparatus we are thinking of the very ideas of which
he can make use, just as he can use the things which he has in
his laboratory. An idea of a certain type, such as that of the
energy of an atom, becomes a tool by means of which one is able
late
to construct the picture of a star as a source of energy. There,
you
see, the object as
such
is
means which enables one
carry on a process of reconstruction such as
is
to
given in scientific
doctrine.
Well then, the sources of the pragmatic doctrine are these:
one is behavioristic psychology, which enables one to put intelligence in its proper place within the conduct of the form,
and to state that intelligence in terms of the activity of the form
itself;
the other
is
which comes back
the research process, the scientific technique,
to the testing of a hypothesis
by
its
working.
Now,
if we connect these two by recognizing that the testing in
working-out means the setting-free of inhibited acts and
processes, we can see that both of them lead up to such a doctrine as the one I have just indicated, and that perhaps the
its
most important phase of
it is
this:
[351]
that the process of
knowing
THOUGHT
lies
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
inside of the process of conduct.
For
this reason
pragma-
tism has been spoken of as a practical sort of philosophy, a sort
philosophy. It brings the process of
of bread-and-butter
thought, of knowledge, inside of conduct.
Because pragmatism has these two aspects, it will be well to
spend a little more time in their consideration. The first phase
is that of the motor psychology. We have referred to its development into behaviorism. The other phase of the problem is
that of the scientific method. The rationahstic philosophies as-
sumed
a certain structure of the object as being given in the
itself, a certain structure of knowledge
which the object has and which also lies in the mind as some
thought an innate idea, others a something which the mind
could directly perceive. The psychological approach of the em-
nature of the object
piricists translated this structure of the object
over into the re-
and
"categories"
other
so-called
and
the
attribute, cause and
were stated in terms of the mere association of different states
of consciousness with each other. If they happened to be associated in a certain way, certain structures arose; if associated otherwise, other structures would have arisen. But they
were not structures directly, not objects as such. They were
mental structures, subject to mental laws. It was generally assumed that there were structures of things that answered to
these mental structures, that lie behind them, as illustrated in
lations of states of consciousness to each other. Substance
effect,
the so-called "causal theory of perception," the theory that our
mind
is
causally affected
by things and that these things impress
themselves on the mind and that with these impressions come
not only the sense quahties but also the relations of these qualitative elements to each other. That is the structure of the ob/ject.
\
Both rationahsm and empiricism assumed that there are
mind gets hold of, and
certain structures in the object which the
through these structures that one can know the laws
of causation, the laws of the relationship of qualities to substances, and so on. Particularly, however, it was in the law of
causation that science and philosophy found the reality of
y that it is
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
What
were the uniform successions of events to each
other in a causal series? Everything, as far as possible, was carried back to causal laws or uniformities.
The history of science since the Renaissance is really a histhings.
tory of the research process.
ceived
of,
and
first
this research
was con-
largely conceived of, as a simple discovery
still is
of something which
At
out there. Discoveries followed each other
one statement of the object was rapidly succeeded by another statement. This seemed only natural, because men were finding out more about the world through the
scientific method. And this new scientific method carried with
it another criterion than that which belonged to the older
period, the criterion of experiment, of experimental tests, of experimentation that included observation. Exceptions arose, we
have seen, and a problem was formulated, and then a hypothesis
is
closely, so that
problem was presented, and then this
That is, one had to see whether or not
this new hypothesis would work. If it did, then the hypothesis
became an accepted theory; if it did not, a new one was substituted for it and subjected to the same test.
This test or experiment the research method in some
sense took the place of the mathematical method in which one
proceeded seemingly by demonstration, by deduction. xAt least
the assumption of the latter was that, if one had all the ultimate
elements of things, one could deduce from their mathematical
relations what the structure of the world is. This was essentially
the position of Descartes. He assumed that he could conceive
of the world as made up of ultimate spatial elements which were
moving with reference to each other, and, given this motion and
for the solution of the
solution
had
to be tested.
the spatial elements, could
He
work out what the structure of
things
must
sumed
a great whirl of this, with the consequent
all
the
be.
difi-'erent
identified
matter with space
particles in relation
itself
and
movement
to each other;
as-
of
and he
undertook to show how the world arose out of such simple motions. He undertook to do this by means of the mathematical
laws of physics. Leibnitz also assumed that, if one could only
[3S3]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
"T^
get hold of these ultimate laws,
it
was conceivable that one
could work out the nature of things from therrfdixfine, the ra-
went on the assumption that there were certain structpre g of things of which the mind got hold.^-^
( ,Th e practice of research science, which I have described at
some length above, was continually to approach, continually to
seek for, new problems, and with these new problems to find new
hypotheses. And these new hypotheses brought with them new
worlds which took the place of the old worlds. The test of them
was one which lay in the experience of man. It was to be found
tionalist
in the actual process of cognition as it lay in experience itself.
The
test
became the ultimate
test,
and from
this
standpoint the
mathematical theory simply presented an apparatus for working out hypotheses, for determining what the situation must be
within which the test could take place. But the assurance in regard to new hypotheses, with their new structure of the world,
rested
upon the
test of experience itself. It is this scientific
^method, which finds the test of the truth of a hypothesis in its
working^at has got its philosophic expression in the pragmatic
doctrine/]
nothing but an expression of the scientific
an experimental method. It has advanced by
the positing of hypotheses. It has advanced from problems
toward their solution, and these problems have called for
analysis. And in the case of changes that we have been describing, this analysis is of the type mentioned above. But, besides
This doctrine
is
method, which
is
these analyses,
it is
some hypothesis
necessary that the scientist should present
as a solution to the problem.
The hypothesis
not simply a statement of the ultimate elements and the relabetween them. If that were the case, one's thinking would
be mere deduction, mere demonstration. Given the elements
is
tions
and
their relations,
made and
we can
see that possible combinations
conclusions deduced.
That
can be
leads to the curious situa-
mathematical sciadvance simply by drawing the necessary con-
tion that Poincare has pointed out, that in
ence
we seem
to
clusions from the premises. In that case there should be nothing
354
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
which was not in the premises; and yet these
advanced from one achievement to another, discovering that which is new, reaching results which are foreign
to the positions from which thinking started. Mathematical science has not been simply a recording of the necessary results
which can be drawn from a set of given premises. It has been an
achievement such as that found in the physical sciences. For
example, within mathematics itself we have seen the development of so-called "transcendental numbers." How shall we
in the conclusion
sciences have
explain this: that
we
get,
by a purely deductive
process, results
not found in the premises? Actually, the conclusion that
have to reach
is
that
we
process. For, after stating our
penetrating analysis,
we
problem by means of the most
reach a point at which a reconstruc-
tion of thought takes place.
The
scientist, including the
matician, presents a hypothesis and then tests
matics this testing of the hypothesis
The way
we
are not using simply a deductive
is
it.
mathe-
In mathe-
generally hidden, cov-
which the mathematician or mathematical
/
scientist justifies himself is by giving a necessary line of reasoning, and one loses the point at which the hypothesis is made.
Put it in this way: If you should take any other view of the
world than our own such as that expressed by the Ptolemaic
theory, the geocentric theory of the world on the basis of that
account you could state the positions of all the different planetary bodies; you could tell where they would all be, could predict eclipses, and other relations. Up to some time in the eighteenth century you could have covered the whole field of astronomy by a Ptolemaic account of the world. But, by working out that doctrine with all its implications, you could not
have deduced from it the Copernican, the heliocentric, theory.
By the most complete set of deductions possible you could not
have reached the latter theory as a necessary result of the
former. When one has accepted the statement of the Copernican theory that the sun is the center, then you can show why
the conclusions that you drew from the Ptolemaic theory were
accurate. You can show why it is that, when the sun seems to
ered up.
in
[355]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
revolve about the earth, you can get the same statement of the
relative positions of sun
you regard the earth
and earth and the other planets whether
on its axis or the sun as re-
as revolving
volving about the earth.
You
can take the geocentric theory
with the heavens revolving about the earth, or the heliocentric
with the earth as revolving about the sun, and show that in
you get the same relative positions of the different
bodies. That is, you can deduce the results of the Ptolemaic
theory from the results of the Copernican theory. But you
either case
move in the opposite direction at the time when the
Copernican theory took the place of the Ptolemaic. To put it
in a more general form, later hypotheses which you present and
accept must be able to take up into themselves all the facts
gathered before, all the results which have been attained; and
they must be able to show how these results were reached. But
you cannot advance by a mere process of deduction from an
earlier to a later hypothesis. Of course, if your later hypothesis
is merely a correcting of errors, you can. If a statement of your
bank account is not right, you can go back and find the mistake.
But you cannot deduce later theories from earher ones. You
cannot deduce the theory of electromagnetism from a theory of
could not
solid atoms. But, given the theory as
it is
being worked out,
terms of electromagnetism. From the
science, we seem always to have
mathematical
standpoint of
only a process of deduction; and the point at which the new
hypothesis comes in is one which is very apt to be completely
we can
state
where the
this
!^
in
not realized that this has taken place in the mind
of the scientist who has a new idea, for, just as soon as he has
a new idea, he states the whole in terms of a set of equations
'hidden. It
(
mass
is
results follow necessarily
way he
from the premises.
And
in
covers up the hypothesis that he has fashioned.
.Actually, the hypothetical
even inside the
field
method
is
essential to
development
of exact mathematics.
Mathematical technique has shown itself pecuharly powerful
in dealing with problems which science has approached. It succeeded, for example, in dealing with the problem of change.
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
That problem was never attacked by the ancient world, that Is,
the problem of change while it is occurring. The ancient world
considered change in terms of qualitative elaboration, in terms
of degeneration and decay, but always from the point of view
of the result being attained. Motion, in particular, was studied
in
terms of spaces which were
The
elapsed.
each change while
Now,
that
in the past, in times
which had
ancient thinkers never undertook to deal with
is
it
was going on.
just the problem that presented itself in dealing
with what in modern mathematics are called "acceleration" and
"deceleration," that
is,
increase
and decrease
in velocity.
How
can you estimate the change that is uniformly taking place
within change itself? You have a body moving toward the
earth.
fall.
You
But
stant.
On
can measure the length of the
this fall is
fall
and the time of the
not one in which velocity has been con-
the contrary,
its
velocity has been uniformly in-
That seemed to mean that the ratio between the distance passed over and the time elapsed is itself continually
changing. And yet this ratio always means a certain distance
passed over in a certain elapsed time. That is, you have to take
a certain distance and a certain time as uniform. We say that a
body has fallen so far in a half or in a thousandth of a second,
and that its velocity is such and such. That means it has passed
creasing.
over this fixed portion of
next portion
may
its
path
in this fixed time.
Then
the
represent a ratio which gives a greater time
But each portion of it has to be treated as if
The problem of the falling body is the problem of
or a greater space.
it
were
fixed.
a process in which the velocity
is uniformly increased. It is that
problem that the "infinitesimal calculus," as Leibnitz termed
it, or "fluxions," as Newton called it
terms which refer to
identical methods at bottom
was invented to solve. These are
the methods which mathematics has used for dealing with a
seemingly insoluble problem. What Leibnitz and Newton did
was to find a way of stating numbers in terms of infinitesi-
mals, of distances that are so slight, times so short, that they
ca n be n eglected.
more accurate statement was one
[357]
in
which
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
these distances were stated in terms of the law of change.
more satisfactory treatment was a statement
That is, it was found out that as one approached a certain limit a certain law was indicated. And it was assumed,
then, that this law must be true of the limit itself. What was
true of the different situations as you approached this limit,
so to speak, must be true of the limit itself.
There are different ways of stating a mathematical procedure
by means of which, as I have said, the scientist was able to
deal with the law of change while that change itself was occurin
terms of
of getting at the law of the change of a change.
It is this
still
limits.
ring
that has enabled science to get inside of, and to deal with, a
The method is one of analysis which
discovers laws by means of this conand
goes farther and
tinued analysis. It was the effectiveness of this analysis which
gave prestige to mathematics. It was no longer simply a static
science of Euclidean geometry, no longer a mere statement of
equations between static quantities; it was a method by means
of which one could get inside the processes which were themselves going on, and get the laws of those changes which were
process that
is
going on.
farther
occurring.
As
philosophy has been a generalization, in some sense, of this mathematical method which has
been so remarkable in its achievements. It has enabled the scientist to enter all sorts of fields those of the changes of air, of
I
have
said, the realistic
changes with which physics and
chemistry have to deal; those of the changes of heat, for example. It was a method which, by its analysis, was able to get
back to ultimate elements ultimate at least for the time being
fluids of all sorts; those of the
and get relations existing between these elements even when
the relations were changing. Knowledge, then, seemed to congetting hold of ultimate elements and the relations between them and also the study, as I have said, of the relations
of relations, the changes of changes. It seemed to consist in
getting hold of the ultimate elements and relata and the relations between them. That has been the goal of realistic thought.
sist in
'
REALISM AND PRAGMATISM
This movement and the pragmatic are the two which are
modern period, for both of
them grow out of phases of the scientific process: the one arises
out of the mathematical technique which has been greatly genpeculiarly characteristic of the
eralized, so that it goes into the field of pure logic in which
mathematics and philosophy are brought together; the other
is a development of the technique of experimental science and
the recognition that the test of a hypothesis
ful solution
of a problem and that
lies in
the success-
human advance
consists in
the solution of problems, solutions that have to be stated in
terms of the processes that have been stopped by the problem.
is not toward a known goal. We cannot tell what the
goal is toward which we are moving, and we do not test our
Progress
movements
or direct
can set up.
What we do
lems,
is
them according
to seek solutions.
free the processes that
we
call
to
any
fixed goal that
we
do, in the face of difficulties or prob-
We
seek a hypothesis which will set
have been stopped
in the situation that
problematic.
There has been a neo-idealism
in
our modern philosophic
thought too; but it has not played a very important part, and
not complicate the picture by introducing it.
will
559
CHAPTER XVI
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETYHOW WE
BECOME SELVES
WHAT
have wanted
chapters
is
to
make
evident in the last few
that science itself has been advancing at
and has become conscious of its experimental method, which latter seemingly has been the source of
its advance. It has been natural that philosophy should take
these phases of the scientific advance as a basis for its interpretation of life, for science, as we know, is not a thing which exists
by itself, even though it uses abstruse mathematical methods.
It is an instrument by means of which mankind, the community, gets control over its environment. It is, in one sense,
the successor to the early magic that undertook to control its
environment by magical methods. It is a means of control.
Science is something that enters into all the minutiae of life. We
cannot brush our teeth without it. We cannot eat or drink
without science coming in to tell us what should be eaten, what
vitamins in the upper part of the alphabet ought to be used,
how they can be obtained in the orange juice and the spinach
that is on the menu. It tells us how to blow our noses and indicates with whom we may shake hands and whom we should
avoid. There is hardly a point in life at which science does not
tell something about the conduct that is an essential part of our
living. It is, in a way, independent of the community, of the
community life. It goes on in separate institutions, in universities that cloister themselves from the community, under sepaa great rate
rate foundations that
demand
that this
work
shall
be entirely
may entertain whatever view he cares
whatever methods he has worked out. The scientist
demands a freedom in his operations which is greater than that
free so that the scientist
to hold, use
[360I
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
which anyone
else in the
community can demand. He seems
stand outside the community; and yet, as
have
to
said, his state-
ments, the directions which he gives, enter into the whole
minutiae of social life. Society is feeling its dependence upon
scientific method more and more, and will continue to do so if
it is
to go
ahead
intelligently.
The
control over
has been a control of situations.
in the past
community life
The control, as
such, has been almost inevitably conservative. It has preserved
orders which have established themselves as social habits that
we
call "institutions."
conscious social control has taken on
The law must be obeyed;
the constitution must be
honored; the various institutions such as the family, school,
this
form:
must be recognized and obeyed; the order which has
come down to us is an order which is to be preserved. And,
whenever the community is disturbed, we always find this return to the fixed order which is there, and which we do not want
courts,
to
have shaken.
It is entirely natural
entirely justifiable.
if
what
is
that
we
one.
We
have
it
The
is
We
have
to
and, in a certain sense,
have an order of society; and,
we have no evidence
taking place shakes that order,
another order to take the place of the present
cannot afford to let that order go to pieces. We must
will get
as a basis for our conduct.
first
step consciously taken in advance of this position
that which grew out of the French Revolution, that which in
a certain sense incorporated the principle of revolution into institutions.
That
the articles in
you have,
is,
it is
when you
set
up
a constitution
that the constitution
in a certain sense,
may
and one of
be changed, then
incorporated the very process of
revolution into the order of society. Only
now
it is
to be an or-
dered, a constitutional revolution by such and such steps. But,
in
any
case,
now you can change
the order of things as
it is
going on.
That is the problem of society, is it not? How can you present
order and structure in society and yet bring about the changes
that need to take place, are taking place? How can you bring
those changes about in orderly fashion and yet preserve order?
[361]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
To
bring about change is seemingly to destroy the given order,
and yet society does and must change. That is the problem, to
incorporate the methods of change into the order of society itself. I do not mean to say that society has not always recognized
that change could take place, but it did not undertake to find
a process by means of which this should go on. It simply assumed that change was going to take place toward some fixed
goal. If you are going to have a society in which everyone is
going to recognize the interests of everybody else for example,
in which the golden rule is to be the rule of conduct, that is,
a society in which everyone is to make the interests of others
his own interest, while actually each person seems to be pursuing his own interest how can that goal be reached? It was
assumed, of course, that this was to be done through a religious
current, through a change in the heart of the individual. But
in the last analysis that goal was to be reached in the world
to come, not in this one. That was the religious solution. The
order we find is one given by God for this world and must be
preserved. The final perfect society was to be a New Jerusalem
that belonged to another world. The religious goal was one of
otherworldliness. We have other conceptions, c ouncils of^erfection set up, such as that of a society in which you should
bring liberty in the sense of everyone's respecting the rights of
everyone
scribed
else,
one's liberty being in that sense only circum-
by intrenching on
others' liberty.
That
is
more or
less
an abstraction. To take a practical illustration, how are you
to determine where the liberty of a man in the control of his
property is to be restricted? He needs controlling. We will
say that he, or rather a group of men, own shares in a railroad,
and that they choose
which will
Well now, if they are to have complete control over their property, and then the community
comes in and says that theirs is property of a different sort, that
their acts must have the approval of the community, how are
we to determine where the restriction in the control over the
property is to take place?
serve their
own
to deal with rates in a fashion
interest.
[362I
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
How
is
and
tions
society to find a
method
changing
for
its
own
institu-
preserve the security of those institutions?
still
That
problem that presents itself in its most universal form. You want a society that is going ahead, not a fixed
order, as the religious solution would have it. You want a
is,
in general, the
society that
telligent
is
progressing. Progress has
Now, how
lif^.
we
are
to get
become
essential to in-
ahead and change those
and yet preserve the security of
advance
in which we cannot state the
them? You see this is an
goal toward which we are going. We do not know what the goal
is. We are on the way, but we do not know where. And yet we
have to get some method of charting our progress. We do not
know where jthe^ progress is supposed to terminate, where it is
going. This is a seemingly insoluble problem.
situations that need changing
Science does, in a sense, present the
That
is, it
recognizes that progress
What
tion of a problem.
And
checking process, sets
scientist
is
movement
entist.
method
for its solution.
of the nature of the solu-
these problems present are inhibitions,
the checking of conduct.
this
is
it
the solution of the problem stops
free so that
we can go
He is finding out why
difficulty in
And
it is.
The
his
system does not work, what the
the test of his solution of the difficulty
that his system starts working again, goes on. Science
with finding what the problems are that exist
ess.
on.
not looking ahead toward a goal and charting his
toward that goal. That is not the function of the sci-
It finds
what the problems
definitely checked.
Then
it
are,
asks:
is
is
occupied
in the social proc-
what processes have been
How
can things be so recon-
structed that those processes which have been checked can be
The
set going again?
field
of hygiene
is
which I have given from the
as good as any, but you can find similar illusillustration
trations elsewhere.
'
Take, as another example, the social problem of recreation,
with all the dangers that gather about its various forms, par- \
ticularly about commercialized recreation. Shall we recognize
>,'
the legitimacy of the expression of the play instinct, the free-
dom
for the play
one wants, when at the same time we recognize
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
You do not set up an ideal form
what the dangers are, just what it
is that finds expression in play, what the freedom is that is
demanded there; and you see how you can combine the control
or avoidance of danger with the freedom of expression. That is
that dangers go along with
of recreation.
You
it?
find out
the sort of problem we are meeting. We have to let freedom
of activity go on, and yet dangers must be avoided. And what
science does is to give a method for studying such situations.
Again, on the social side, or on the biological side in dealing
with questions of disease, we have the question of how we
with these problems. As a further instance, take
the question of crime. What are the conditions out of which
crime itself springs? How, on the one hand, can you protect
shall deal
society against the criminal and yet, on the other hand, rec-
ognize those conditions which are responsible for the criminal
himself? What procedure can you set up by means of which you
can guard society against the criminal and at the same time
protect the individual against unfair conditions under which he
has been living? Here we have a series of clashing problems,
and what we have to do is to get a way which will recognize
that what we feel is essential in each, so that the problems can
be adjusted and the essential processes of Hfe can go on.
we
get such a method,
we have
the
means
When
for the solution of
our
problem of juveproblems. Let me
nile crime, so-called. There we have a situation in which certain
definite habits embodied in our institution of the court prove unsatisfactory. The child is brought before the court by the police.
The social habit left simply to itself would condemn the child to
the penitentiary and thus make a confirmed criminal out of him.
But it is possible to modify those habits by what we call the
"scientific method."
What I wish to point out is that the scientific method, as
such, is, after all, only the evolutionary process grown selfconscious. We look back over the history of plant and animal
life on the face of the globe and see how forms have developed
slowly by the trial-and-error method. There are slight variaillustrate this further in the
[364]
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
tions that take place in the individual forms
more pronounced variations that we
call
these, different forms gradually arise.
particular problem of an animal
the
and occasional
"mutations." Out of
But the solution of the
food problem, we will
one
which
may
take
say is
thousands of years to solve in the
gradual development of a certain form. A form which passes,
let us say, from the eating of meat to the eating of vegetables
develops a type of stomach capable of handling this latter kind
of food. Here we have a problem which is met gradually by the
a:ppearance of some form that does commence to develop an
adjustment to the problem, and we can assume that from its
progeny those particular forms will be selected which are
adapted to such digestion. It is a problem which has to be met
if there is to be development, and the development takes place
by the seemingly incidental appearance of those forms which
happen to be better able than others to meet the peculiar demands set up. If we put ourselves in the same place, there is the
same problem. The food problem faces us as it does all other
animal forms. We have to get our food from both the vegetable
and the animal kingdoms. But if it is a question of our being able
to get the food that is shut up inside a cellulose covering, we do
not wait through long periods until we develop stomachs which
will be able to digest this substance. We work out a milling
process by means of which we set free that which is digestible.
That is, we solve the problem directly by what we call the
"scientific method." Here is a certain necessity: the food which
we need is shut off from us by a cellulose covering. We work
out a mechanism to get rid of this covering. There is an evolutionary problem made self-conscious. The problem is stated
in a definite form; this, in turn, excites the imagination to
the formation of a possible hypothesis which will serve as the
solution of it; and then we set out to test the solution.
The same process is found in social development, in the for- )
mation of great societies among both invertebrates and vertebrates, through a principle of organization. Societies develop,
just as animal forms develop, by adjusting themselves to the )
'
[365]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
problems that they find before them. They have food problems,
problems of climate, just as individual animals do; but they
meet them in a social fashion. When we reach the human form
with its capacity for indicating what is important in a situation,
through the process of analysis; when we get to the position in
which a mind can arise in the individual form, that is, where the
individual can come back upon himself and stimulate himself
just as he stimulates others; where the individual can call out
in himself the attitude of the whole group; where he can acquire
the knowledge that belongs to the whole community; where he
can respond as the whole community responds under certain
conditions when they direct this organized intelligence toward
particular ends; then we have this process which provides solutions for problems working in a self-conscious way. In it we
have the evolution of the human mind which makes use directly
of the sort of intelligence which has been developed in the whole
process of evolution. It
that
we
makes use of
it
by the
direct
one finds the beginnings of the evolution of what we
tutions."
method
"mental." If one goes back to a primitive society,
call
Now
these institutions are, after
all,
call "insti-
the habits of
individuals in their interrelation with each other, the type of
habit that
is
handed down from one generation
to another.
And we
can study the growth of these habits as we can study
the growth and behavior of an animal.
That is where science comes in to aid society in getting a
method of progress. It understands the background of these
problems, the processes out of which they have developed; and
has a method of attacking them. It states the problem in
terms of checked processes; and then it has a test of the suggested solution by seeing whether those processes can continue
it
That
more valuable
a contribution of science as any of its immediate results
that we can gather together. This sort of method enables us to
keep the order of society and yet to change that order within
or not.
is
as valuable
the process
itself.
in a certain sense
It is a recognition that intelligence expresses
itself in the solution
of problems.
That
[366]
is
the
way
in
which evo-
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
lution
is
taking place in the appearance of problems in
life.
Living forms have found themselves up against problematic
situations: their food gone, the climate changed, new enemies
in. The method which nature has followed, if we
speak so anthropomorphically, has been the production
of variations until finally some one variation has arisen which
has survived. Well, what science is doing is making this method
coming
may
of
trial
Up
and error a conscious method.
have been
dogmatic theory of certain
to this period the so-called "social sciences"
gathered about the more or
less
was assumed that each institution as such
stood upon certain rational doctrines, whether those of the
institutions.
It
family, the state, the church, the school, or the court.
The
early
theory was that these institutions were established directly by
God. The divine right of kings was simply the assertion that the
state had as divine an origin as the church; and, of course, it
was assumed that God was also responsible for the ordering of
the family and the other institutions. They all came back to a
direct structure which was given to them. If the theories did not
place this structure in divine ordinance, they brought it back
to certain natures in the institutions themselves. And it was assumed that you could work out the theory which would determine what the institutions ought to be. (The development of
evolutionary doctrine had as great an effect in this field as any
it had in biology. Spencer, and others following immediately in
his path, carried
ment of human
over the evolutionary theory into the developinstitutions.
People went back to primitive
which at first were regarded as much more primitive
than they were, and then undertook to show how, out of the
life of these people^ different institutions arose through a
societies,
process of evolutional
I
pointed out earlier that a certain part of the stimulus which
the Hegelian movement. The
one sense an evolutionary one. At)
least it was particularly interested in the development of what
we term "self-consciousness," in the process of thinking whereJ
directed this thought
came from
Hegelian doctrine was
in
367
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
And it was the Hegehan thinkers who turned to the
study of human institutions, but they did so on the economic
and the pohtical side. On the economic side, we have the Marxian doctrine of the human institution in the economic process.
On the pohtical side, we have the development of the state, esthat arose.
pecially the city-state. Hegel's son Karl
was quite a notable
author in the early study of the city-state, particularly of the
in which it developed. The whole study of so complex a
dogmatic structure as the Roman law, for example, was brought
way
back to an evolutionary consideration. Later, attention was directed toward social forms as social forms, apart from any dogmatic structure that lay behind them.
Take, again, the attitude of the community toward crime.
On the evolutionary side, you go back to a situation, we will
say, of blood vengeance. A man from one clan kills a man from
another. Immediately there arises within the injured clan a
man who is determined to revenge the death by killing someone
from the other clan, and the next of kin sets out to kill the
slayer. When he accomplishes this, he sets up at once the need
of vengeance on the part of the first group. Again, the next of
kin goes out to slay in his turn. And this process goes on until,
we will say, the clans are nearly exterminated. Well now, when
clans were brought together in a tribe in order to defend themselves
against
other
tribes,
such a decimation of fighting
members of the group became a serious matter, and the tribe
came to consider how this problem could be met. A court was
worked out in which vengeance took the form of paying a fine.
And some sort of a court had to be constituted which should
pass upon obligations. In this way a means was gradually built
up of getting rid of blood vengeance. There you have an evolutionary process in which the court arises.
When
it is
ize society
what
is felt
carried through and
more exactly and
fit
it
becomes necessary to organmore definitely to
the penalty
to be the character of the crime, there arise all the
penalties which belong to a court of law.
tution of criminal law which
still
And we
carries over
[368]
get the insti-
some of
this sense
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
There must be some
suffering on the part of the man who has gone against the interests of the community, who has trespassed on the rights of others.
In the older, medieval state the community was called together
to witness the suffering of the individual who was being punof vengeance which
ished.
is
to be enacted.
The community thus
got satisfaction out of the venge-
ance, particularly any specific individuals
who were themselves
That element of vengeance
in a sense demands that where some particularly outrageous
crime has been committed, the community feels the need for
somebody to suffer. And under such circumstances it is difficult to get impartial justice. It becomes more important to the
community that someone should suffer than that the specific
individual should suffer. So in our criminal law we have this
motive of exacting suffering, and we have a partially workedout theory which states that where a person has committed a
crime he should pay by a certain amount of suffering for the
wrong he has done. If the wrong is great, he must suffer more
than if it is a lesser wrong. So we inflict punishment by putting
him in prison. If the sin is heinous, he is put in for ten or
twenty years; if lighter, for perhaps only a few weeks or months.
We fit the punishment to the crime.
But we know that that process does not work at all. We
have no such exactly measured sets of sufferings as to be able
to put them accurately over against wrongs. When the sense
of vengeance has died down, we are not sure whether we want
the other person to suffer at all. We want to get rid of crime.
injured by the so-called criminal.
And
so
we change our theory from wanting
the person to suffer
wrong he has done to seeing that we keep him from doing
the same wrong again. So we have retribution, not in the sense
of vengeance but as repression of crime itself. But you know
how difficult it is to work those two motives together, trying
for a
to find out just
how much
repression of crime does take place
through the action of the law.
offenses,
we
feel
And when we come
to juvenile
the situation should be approached from an
entirely different standpoint.
So we put aside criminal law, and
[369]
'
THOUGHT
we have
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the judge sitting with the boy or
girl;
we
get
members
of the family, perhaps some person interested in social service,
possibly the school teacher, and they all talk it over, and try to
find out just why what happened did happen, and they attempt
to discover some sort of situation by means of which the
criminal can be got back into a social position and be kept from
doing the sort of thing he has done in the past. Thus we try to
get rid of crime by a social process. That parole system has been
Very
have been obtained where politics has not come in
to corrupt the process. There we have the development of an
institution from both ends, so to speak. You can see how, out of
the attitude of vengeance, the court itself has arisen, and then
how, out of the operation of an institution of that sort, one
having conflicting motives in it, such as repression of crime on
the one hand and a demand for vengeance on the other, that
institution can be approached from the standpoint of reinstating the individual in society. There is a social problem here,
the problem of an individual who has abused the rights of somebody else but whom we want to put back in the social situation
so that he will not do it again. There we have the development
of a social process by a real scientific method.
We try to state the problem as carefully as we can. Here is a
boy who has allied himself with a gang and has been carried
away with the sense of adventure and has committed a burglary
which could send him to the penitentiary for years. But that
would be absurd. It would make a criminal out of him, and no
good would be accomphshed at all. It is very questionable
whether it would even keep other boys from doing the same
thing, for, of course, the sense of adventure makes the attitude
of the criminal something attractive in itself. It is astonishing
how, when we are somev/hat relaxed by an attack of grippe
or disease, we turn to criminal tales for our relief! If you go
through the hospitals of the city, you will find such tales being
carried over from the juvenile court into the adult court.
good
results
The creation of crime taken in itself
can be looked at from the point of view of adventure, especially
read in great quantities.
[370]
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
for the adolescent.
If
you approach things
can see what the attitude
is.
You can
you
boy has ap-
scientifically,
see that the
from this attitude of adventure, does not realize its
import; and if he is made to realize it, you can make a very
good citizen indeed out of him. What you want to do, then, is
to state your social situation in such a fashion that you can reconstitute the boy as a normal citizen, give him opportunities
for play in which he can express his demand for adventure with
proached
it
what the rights are that make a possibility of
That has to be brought home to him. He wants to
be a citizen in the community, and he has to see that he must
have the same respect for the rights of others that he claims for
himself. And at the same time you must have a situation where
the boy can lead a normal life. Work out specific hypotheses, and
by means of them you may get the boy back into society again.
Take any institution as such and look at it from the standa recognition of
citizenship.
way
which that
determined
in
society, and then you can see the development in society
it-
point of evolution, the
self of a
technique which
but
a technique
it
is
in
we
which
is
call
is
the "scientific technique,"
simply doing consciously what
takes place naturally in the evolution of forms.
pointing out that the process of evolution
is
have been
one that meets
such a problem as that of blood vengeance, where members
of the tribe are at work killing each other as fast as they
And
community works out there in a somewhat
bungling fashion, if you like a court which undertakes to meet
can.
the
becomes established, acquires a dogmatic
structure, holds on to motives which belonged to the earlier
situation. But finally we see the situation as one in which we
try to do with self-consciousness what took place by a process
of evolution. That is, we try to state the problem with reference to a particular child; we want to see what can be done
toward bringing together what was a healthful expression of
adventure on the part of the boy with rights which he himself
claims. So the juvenile court represents a self-conscious applicathis
situation.
It
[371]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
tion of the very process of evolution out of
which the courts
themselves arose.
What
am
trying to do
is
to connect this entire evolution-
ary process with social organization in its most complex exand as that within which arise the very individuals
through whose life-process it works, giving birth to just such
pression,
elements as are involved in the development of selves. And, as
I have said, the life-process itself is brought to consciousness
in the
conduct of the individual form,
He
consciousness."
gets a
much more
environment than the ox can get over
in which, in a certain sense, control
you think of
it,
the
human
is
in his so-called "self-
effective control over his
its.
The
within his
process
own
is
one
grasp. If
being as a social form has actually
got relatively complete control over his environment. The animal gets a certain sHght kind of control over its environment;
but the
human
form, in societies, can determine what vegeta-
tion shall grow,
what animals
shall exist besides itself; it
own
climate, erect
its
control
its
own
biological sense, complete control over its
That
is, it
can
buildings. It has, in a
own environment.
has attained to a remarkable degree an end which
implied in the whole living process
the environment within which
it
is
the control by the form of
hves.
To
a degree
human
society has reached that goal.
It has often been pointed out, of course, that evolution does
not reach any goal. The concept means simply the adaptation
of a form to a certain environment. But adaptation is not
simply the fitting of the form into the environment, it carries
with it some degree of control over that environment. And in
the case of the
human
form, of
human
society,
we have
that
adaptation expressing itself in a very high degree of control.
Of course, we cannot change the chemical and physical structure o things, but we can make them over into those forms that
we
ourselves need and which are of value to us.
That
is
possible
have said with reference to the question of food
and to the question of climatic influences, we can in a very large
degree determine that control. So there is, within limits, a defor us; and, as
[372]
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
velopment toward complete adaptation where that adaptation
expresses itself in control over the environment.
sense
think
we can
fairly
say that
human
social organization, does exercise control
And
in that
organization, as a
and has
in
that sense
reached a certain goal of development.
Well now, this social process I have been sketching in these
broad strokes has become of increasing interest to reflective
thought throughout this whole period. Of course, to some extent it has always been of essential interest to man in the social
situation in which he lives. What I am referring to specifically
its organization, its hisis the character of the social organism
tory, and the conditions under which it can be controlled, ^he
statement of the functions of the different parts of the social
organism Ts that study which we have in a so-called "social
science," and more particularly in sociology. This had its inception in the thought of Comte, and then was enriched by the idea
of evolution as brought in by Spencer. From that time on, the
attempt to understand human society as an organization has
been of increasing interest to the Western world. Men have
been trying to see the habits out of which society has arisen, >
to find out under what conditions it operates, and how problems that arise in it can be definitely controlled. This involves \
looking at human institutions from the standpoint I have sug- \
gested, that
is,
as social habits.
While during the century there has been
this increased inter-
study of the social organization, there has been a corresponding interest in the experience of the individual. Part of
this is due to our scientific attitude. As we have seen, it is the
unique experience of the scientist that presents the problem, and
it is in the mind of the scientist that the hypothesis arises. It is
not only in the scientist as such that this uniqueness of the
experience has been recognized as of importance. After all, the
est in the
scientist is
simply making a technique out of
gence. His
method
is
the
same
as that of
all
human
intelli-
intelligent beings,
even though it involves a simple rendering in self-consciousness
of the whole process of evolution. That in the experience of all
[373]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
pecuHar to the individual, that which is
unique in his experience, is of importance; and what the last
century increasingly recognized was the importance of these
individuals which
is
unique individual experiences.
The emotional side of these experiences, as we know, registers
of the self
itself in the folk poetry, in the lyric expression
registration of values from the point of view of the individual.
There have always been some neat ways of scientific observation,
although accurate presentation of
modern
of the Renaissance. But what
tion to
it
belongs really to the
world, that world which has grown
is
the interest
individual as
it is
we have
am
up
since the period
particularly caUing atten-
in that
which
is
peculiar to the
revealed in our literature and in our journals,
our newspapers. The curious thing about the newspaper is^ that
it records happenings to individual persons; and it assumes that
it
is
of interest to us to
know
that a certain individual at a
was run over by an automobile or that a certain
hurt himself in such and such a way, and
down,
person fell
that John or Jane has had such and such an experience in such
certain time
a place. It
is
curious to note the interest that centers about indi-
viduals as such, and the assumption that the world at large
will
be interested in these happenings.
Well now, what
want
to
connect with this journalese
is the character
interest in happenings to particular individuals
of our Hterature, not simply in
its lyric
poetry, where the emo-
can be handed on
to others, but particularly in our novels and the drama. In these
we have this interest in the experience of the individual as such
tion of the individual
presented as
it
is
presented so that
it
has been during the last century, because
it
does
answer to some very profound interest on the part of all the
individuals who take up their morning and evening papers, who
read all sorts of stories and novels, go to movies, listen to the
radio, get those experiences of other individuals which, as
say,
when one just
have an interest for us which is
stands off and looks at the situation. They seem to be so unrelated. We seem to be interested in just a particular occurrence.
rather astonishing
[374]
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
We
speak of
and perhaps are apt to regard it
on our part when we are
as sensational
it
as an attitude not entirely helpful
interested in this fashion.
What
in
is
the import of this interest?
sharp contrast to what
human
that the
self arises
am
in
wanted
to bring this
going to develop
through
of the group to which he belongs
terms of the community
its
up
later, that is,
ability to take the attitude
because he can talk
to himself
which he belongs and lay upon
to
himself the responsibilities that belong to the community; beown duties as over against others
cause he can recognize his
what constitutes the self as such. And there you see what
we have emphasized, as peculiar to others, that which is both
individual and which is habitual. The stru cture of society lies in
these social habits, and only in so far as we can take these social
habits into ourselves can we become selves.
We speak of this interest on the emotional side as "sympathy"
that
is
passing into the attitude of the other, taking the
and sorrows. That
other, feeling the other's joys
side of
side,"
tions
And
it.
is
What we
call
call
in so far as
he indicates
it
role of the
the effective
the "intellectual side," the "rational
the recognition of
which
is
common
out responses
one indicates
stimuli, of
common emo-
member of the group.
common character to others,
every
in
this
way, of course, by taking the
to himself. In this
attitude of the others in the group in their co-operative, highly
complex
riences.
activity, the individual
The
in a highly
engineer
is
complex process. But
takes the attitude of the person
same meaning
way
is
to
able to enter into their expe-
able to direct vast groups of individuals
him that
it
in
every direction he gives, he
he is directing. It has the
whom
has to others.
into the attitudes of others,
and
in that
We
enter in that
way we make our
very complex societies possible. This development of a form
that is able so to communicate with others that it takes on attitudes of those in the group, that
it
talks to itself as
it
talks to
own life this conversation, and sets
which it works out the process that it is
going to carry on, and so brings it to public consideration with
others, that imports into its
up an inner forum
in
[375]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the advantage of that previous rehearsing,
Sometimes we
is
important.
all
we can best think out an argument by
we are talking to somebody who takes one particular side. As we say, we have an argument to present, and
we think how we will present it to that individual. And as soon
as we present it, we know that he would reply in a certain way.
Then we reply in a certain fashion to him. Sometimes it is
find that
supposing that
easier to carry out such a conversation
lar protagonist
we know.
In that
way
by picking out a particuin the night
apt to go through distressing conversations
out the next day. That
is
hours
we have
the process of thought. It
we
are
to carry
is
taking
the attitude of others, talking to other people, and then replying
in their language.
Of course,
simpler situations.
human
is
what constitutes
thinking.
human
was pointing out the
is
society than in
difference
society and a society of invertebrates.
organization
The
between a
principle of
not that of physiological plasticity, not that of
holding the form
it is
That
conditions are different in a
itself physiologically to its particular function;
rather the principle of organization as found in the form of
human intercommunication and participation. It is what the
human individual puts into the form of significant symbols
through the use of gestures.
He
is
then able to place himselfm
the attitude of others, particularly into just such attitudes as those
I
have spoken of as human
institutions. If institutions are sodal
habits, they represent certain definite attitudes that people as-
sume under
certain given social conditions. So that the indi-
vidual, in so far as he does take the role of others, can take the
habitual attitude of the
community over
against such social
situations as these.
As
have pointed out, he does this in the process of indicating
to others the important elements in a situation, pointing out
those elements which are of importance in the social process, in a
situation that represents one of these social habits, such as the
family situation; one that involves the rights of different individuals in the community, such as a political situation. What
the individual does is to indicate what the important characters
I
[376]
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
in a
co-operative process are.
bers of the
community; but
as
of vocal gestures, he indicates
He
we
it
indicates this to other
mem-
shall see, especially in the case
to himself as to others;
and just
he does indicate it to himself as to others, he tends to
out in himself the same attitude as in others. There is a
common attitude, that is, one which all assume under certain
in so far as
call
habitual situations.
Through the use of language, through the
use of the significant symbol, then, the individual does take the
attitude of others, especially these
common
attitudes, so that he
same attitude toward himself that the
This, of course, is what gives the principle of
finds himself taking the
community
takes.
simply the social control that results from
blind habit, but a social control that comes from the individual
assuming the same attitude toward himself that the community
social control, not
assumes toward him. In a habitual situation everyone takes a
certain attitude in so far as
is
it is
habitual, in so far as the habit
have taken, that is, in so far as you have what
If, now, the individual calls out this
others by a gesture, by a word which affects himself
one which
all
are called "institutions."
attitude in
just as
it
affects others, then he will call out the
in himself that
he
calls
out in others. In this
same
way he
acting toward himself as others act toward him.
monish himself
as others would.
are his duties as well as
what
That
is,
he
are his rights.
attitude
He
will
will recognize
He
be
will ad-
what
takes the atti-
tude of the community toward himself. This gives the princimethod of organization which, as I have said, we can study
pal
from the standpoint of a behavioristic psychology, a method
which belongs to human society and distinguishes it from social
organizations which one finds among ants and bees and termites. There one finds societies that run up into the millions;
and we find these as finely organized as human societies are, and
so organized that individuals' lives are largely determined by
the life-process of the whole. We get far more complex and intricate organization, of course, in human society than among the
invertebrates. For this principle to which I have referred organization through communication and participation
makes
[377]
THOUGHT
IN
Tht iNiiMiTEENTH CENTURY
an almost indefinite organization possible. Now the study of the
in which this organization takes place, the history of it,~t1ie
evolution of it, is what has been opened up to the human mind
in the last century. We now see the way in which out of a
primitive group there can gradually arise the very highly organized societies of the present day. We can study that process in
the evolution of institutions, and we can see how that process
way
is
modified or
may
be modified in the presence of
probl^^jrnatic
situations.
This evolution also takes place in human society, but here
takes place not through physiological plasticity, not through
the development of peculiar physiological functions on the part
it
of the separate individuals. It takes place through the develop-
ment of what has been referred to on the logical side as a universe of discourse. That is, it takes place through communication
and participation on the part of the
common
activities. It takes place
significant symbols. It
is
different individuals in
through the development of
accomplished almost entirely through
the development of vocal gestures, through the capacity of the
individual to indicate by
means of
his
own
gestures to other
forms and also to himself, those elements which are of importance in co-operative activity. So far as
we can
see, the stimuli
that keep the invertebrates occupied are those of odor, contact.
no evidence of any language among them. It is
through physiological development and plasticity that their
very complex communities operate. But the human form, subject to no such development as this, can be interwoven into a
community activity through its ability to respond to the ges-
But we
find
tures of other forms that indicate to
is
to respond.
may
We
it
the stimuli to which
it
point things out. This pointing-out process
be with the finger, by an attitude of body, by direction of
by means of the vocal gesture,
that is, a certain vocal symbol that indicates something to another individual and to which he responds. Such indication as
this sets up a certain definite process of pointing out to other inhead and eyes; but
as a rule
it is
[378]
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
dividuals in the group
what
is
of importance in this co-operative
activity.
The pecuhar importance of the vocal gesture is that it affects
who makes it just as much as it affects the individual to whom it is directed. We hear what we say; if we are
talking with our fingers we see what we are saying; if with attitudes of the body, we feel what we are saying. The effect of the
attitude which we produce in others comes back on ourselves.
It is in this way that participation arises out of communication.
When we indicate something to another form, we are calling out
in that other individual a certain response. The very gesture
we make calls out a certain sort of response in him. If that gesthe individual
him,
ture affects us as
it
some response in
when it is a vocal
ourselves.
affects
gesture,
is
the meaning of
goes to another.
ing of
is
that a
what he
He
is
what he says
is
has a tendency to
call
out
gesture that affects another,
one which
may have
the tendency
The common
man knows what he is saying when
to influence the speaker as
expression of this
it
The
it
influences others.
saying comes to him as really as
affected just as the other
affects the other,
it
mean-
If the
is.
it
affects himself in the
same way. The result of this is that the individual who speaks,
in some sense takes the attitude of the other whom he addresses.
We
are familiar with this in giving directions to another person
do something. We find ourselves affected by the same direction. We are ready to do the thing and perhaps become irritated
by the awkwardness of the other and insist on doing it ourselves.
We have called out in ourselves the same response we have asked
for in another person. We are taking his attitude. It is through
to
this sort of participation, this taking the attitudes of other indi-
viduals, that the peculiar character of
We
stituted.
tain group.
means that
There
is
human
say something that means
But
it
intelligence
is
con-i
something to a cer-\
not only means that to the group,
it
same meaning for both.
what we would call, "unconscious
also^
to us. It has the
a certain,
tion" that takes place in lower vertebrate forms.
animals
is
said to set
up a
sentinel.
[379]
Some one form
is
direc-
group of
more
sensi-
THOUGHT
tive
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
than others to stimuli of danger.
of this one which
more
is
Now the action on
the part
sensitive than the rest, the action of
running from danger, for example, does cause the other forms
to run also. But the first one is not giving a signal in the
human sense. It is not aware of giving such directions. Its mere
running constitutes a stimulus to the other forms to run in the
same direction. It works in the same way as if the form knew
what its business was, to catch the first evidence of the enemy
and go give the evidence of it to the whole group, thus setting
them all going. But in the experience of the animal there is no
such procedure, no such content. The animal does not influence himself as he influences others. He does not tell himself of
the danger as he
tells it to others.
The outstanding
He
characteristic in
merely runs away^
human communication
is
making a declaration, pointing out something that is
common in meaning to the whole group and to the individual,
that one
is
so that the individual
so far as there
out "Fire!" he
same
any
is
is
is
taking the attitude of the whole group,
definite
meaning given.
When
man
calls
not only exciting other people but himself in
He knows what
he is about. That, you see,
what we refer to as a "uniyjsrse .of discourse." It is a common meaning which is communicated to
everyone and at the same time is communicated to the self. The
individual is directing other people how to act, and he is taking
the
fashion.
constitutes biologically
the attitude of the other people
whom
he
is
directing. If in this
makes an objection, he is doing
what the other person would do, and he is also carrying on the
process which we call "thought." That is, you indicate to somebody else that he is to do something, and he objects to it. Well
now, the person might in his attitude of the other make the same
attitude of the other person he
objection himself.
You
reply to the other person, trying to point
out his mistake or admitting your own. In the same way,
make some
your mistake to
when the individual takes the
especially when he takes the common
with one's
other,
if you
you reply to your own objection or admit
yourself. Thinking is a process of conversation
objection,
self
[380]
attitude of the
attitude of the
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
whole group, when the symbol that he uses is a common symbol,
has a meaning common to the entire group, to everyone who is
in it and anyone who might be in it. It is a process of communication with participation in the experience of other people.
The mechanism that we use for this process is words, vocal
And we need, of course, only a very few of these as
compared with those we need when talking to others. A single
gestures.
symbol
is
enough
But
to call out necessary responses.
it is
just
symbols of
language as if the whole process were expressed. We sometimes
do our thinking out loud, in fully organized sentences; and one's
thought can always presumably be developed into a complete
grammatical unit. That is what constitutes thinking.
Now, it is this inner thought, this inner flow of speech and
what it means that is, words with their meanings that call
out intelligent response; it is this that constitutes the mind, in so
as really a conversation in terms of the significant
far as that lies in the experience of the form.
But
this
is
only a
part of the whole social process, for the self has arisen in that
social process;
it
has
its
being there.
Of course, you could
carry
such a self as that over to a Robinson Crusoe island and leave
him by
himself,
and he could carry that
himself and extend
but
it is
it
to his pets.
He
on by
on by himself,
social process
carries that
only because he has grown up in society, because he can
take attitudes and roles of others, that he can accomplish
this.
This mental process, then, is one which has evolved in the
social process of which it is a part. And it belongs to the difi^erent organisms that lie inside of this larger social process. We
can approach it from the standpoint of evolution; and we can
approach it more particularly from the standpoint of behavioristic psychology, where we can get back to what expresses itself
in the mind. We also can get somewhat underneath the experience that goes on in the self in what we term "pathological
psychology," a psychology that enables us to get hold of the
various processes that are not themselves evidenced in this
stream of inner conversation to which I have referred. The
term "pathological" simply means that this type of psychology
[381]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
has been pursued largely in dealing with pathological cases. It
is a study, for example, of the way in which our special world
arises in our experience through our distance senses and our
contact experiences, through the collation of the elements which
we reach through vision with the elements which we reach
through the tactual sense, the process by which we have built
up an implemental world by the use of our hands; for a particular instance, the process by which, for purposes of food, we
reach with the hand for a distant object. Man comes into that
process and gives to the organism a physical thing which is not
the food, not the consummation, whatever
physical thing.
We
Our world
deal with things as
if
made up out
is
it
may
be,
but a
of physical things.
we could handle them.
We
think of
things as being "pulverized," broken up into parts so we can get
hold of them. A physical thing is a unit into which we break up
our environment. The process by which we build our world of
physical things is a process, too, of which we are not immediately conscious.
The
child, the infant that
is
uncertainly groping
toward a ball, is gradually building up a world of such physical
things; but the process takes place underneath the level of our
own consciousness. We cannot get at it in its immediate inception, only indirectly by this type of psychology, a psychology
that does enable us to get into the workings of the individual
process as it lies inside of the whole social process to which it
belongs.
And
this
is
what constitutes the
self as such.
so evidently a social individual that
of social individuals
is
as
much
tion as other biological forms.
it
can exist
which is
only in a group
self
a result of the process of evolu-
form that can co-operate with
others through the use of significant symbols, set up attitudes
of others and respond to them,
ment of great
is
possible through the develop-
tracts in the central nervous system that are con-
nected with our processes of articulation, with the ear, and so
with the various movements that can go on in the human form.
But they
form.
are not circumscribed within the conduct of a single
They belong
to the group.
[382]
And
the process
is
just as
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
much an
evolution as
is
ants. In those instances
that
we
among
the
get a certain particular evolution
taking place, belonging to a certain particular society,
is
one which could
the
the queen bee or the fighter
self.
That
who
another;
exist only in
is,
who
The same
is
true of
affects himself as he affects
takes the attitude of the other in so far as he af-
fects the other, in so far as
who knows what
speech;"
such a society.
an individual
he
is
using what
he himself
is
we term
"intelligible
saying, in so far as he
is
by these significant symbols to others
with the recognition that they have the same meaning for them
directing his indications
him; such an individual is, of course, a phase of the develthe social form. This is a branch of what we term
"behavioristic psychology," one in which we can see how the
as for
opment of
self as such has developed.
What
want to make evident is that the development, the
mind as well as of institutions is a social evolution.
evolution, of
As
have just stated, society in its organization is a form, a
species that has developed; and it has many forms developing
I
within
it.
You
see, for
example, at the present time in reference
problem is one which is met by
very intricate social organizations. Where the individual himself responds simply to the odor or sight of food, we recognize
it as a biological process. When the whole community responds
to the question of food that the
to the need of food by the organization of its industries, its
methods of agriculture, of milling, of transportation, of cooking
and preparation, we have the same process, only now not by
separate individuals but by a social organization; and that
organization is just as really an evolution as the stomach of the
ox. That stomach is very complicated. The evolution of a social
mechanism by which grain is sowed and reaped in South
America and North America, is carried to great milling establishments and there converted into flour, and then carried and
distributed by dealers so that the individual groups can get hold
of it and prepare it in such fashion that it can be readily assimilated
that is just as much evolution as the development of
bacteriological laboratories in the digestive tract of an ox. It
is
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
a process, however, which takes place
it is
much more rapidly than
we have something
taking place in the case of the ox. There
that answers to a physiological plasticity in the case of invertebrates
the adjustment of different organs within
the
body
accomplish what we accomplish by mechanical means. It
our environment that gives "~"""
us what
this ability to control
""""
"
to
is
we
"
term "mind."
What we
attach to the term "mind" particularly
privacy. It belongs to the individual.
there takes place,
we
And what
is
its
takes place
say, in the experience of the individual.
He may make it accessible to others by telling about it. He may
talk out loud. He may publish. He may indicate even by his
mind is. But there is
mind that never gets pub-
uncontrolled gestures what his frame of
that which goes on inside of a man's
something that takes place there within the experience
it, of course, is what answers to what
is going on in the physiological mechanism there, the suffering
that belongs to one's teeth, the pleasure one gets in the palate.
These are experiences which he has for himself because they are
taking place within his own organism. But, though they are
taking place within his own organism, and so no one else can experience the same thing, the organism does not experience it as
lished,
of the individual. Part of
own that is,
own until a self
its
example, that
in
it
does not realize that the experience
has arisen.
We
have no reason
is
its
to assume, for
lower animals there are such entities as selves;
and if no such entities, then that which takes place within the
organism cannot be identified with such a self. There is pain;
there is pleasure; there are feelings which are not exactly painful
or pleasurable, such as heat and cold. These various feelings
belong to the organism, the tensions of the various muscles, the
movements of
the joints, so essential in our intelligent social
conduct. These belong to the organism in a certain sense. But
the individual animal does not associate
cause
it
self
which
has no
self; it is
not a
can arise only where there
this self
has had
them with
a self be-
self.
its initiation.
[384]
is
a social process within
It arises
within that proc-
THE PROBLEM OF SOCIETY
For that process the communication and participation to
which I have referred is essential. That is the way in which
selves as such have arisen. That is where the individual is in a
social process in which he is a part, where he does influence himself as he does others. There the self arises. And there he turns
back upon himself, directs himself. He takes over those experiences which belong to his own organism. He identifies them with
ess.
himself.
What
constitutes the particular structure of his ex-
what we
call his "thought." It is the conversation
which goes on within the self. This is what constitutes his
mind. For it is through this so-called "thought," of course, that
he interprets his experiences. Now that thought, as I have already indicated, is only the importation of outer conversation,
conversation of gestures with others, into the self in which the
perience
is
individual takes the role of others as well as his
talks to himself. This talking
what
is
is
significant.
of importance in the situation.
elements that
call
He
is
out the necessary responses.
He
own
is
role.
He
indicating
indicating those
When
there are
problem gives rise to the hypotheses that form in
his mind; and he indicates them to himself and to others. It is
this process of talking over a problematic situation with ones'
self, just as one might talk with another, that is exactly what
we term "mental." And it goes on within the organism.
conflicts, the
385
CHAPTER XVII
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIORCAN ITS STUDY BE MADE SCIENTIFIC?
WHEN
method we have been describing
the problems of psychology, it was
the scientific
was brought
into
recognized that association could not be maintained
as the
solved.
fundamental principle in terms of which they might be
We speak naturally of certain elements as associated
Why
with each other.
are certain experiences associated rather
than an indefinite number of others? When we come back to
account for their strong association, we find we come back to
attention, to interest.
and
We
are interested in certain connections,
these get fixed in our minds.
We
give our attention to cer-
tain elements in experience, and that fixes them in the order in
which they occur. But association is itself something that needs
to be explained. Why is there selection in experience? Consciousness is selective; we see what we are looking for. There is
a character of conduct about experience that determines what
the relations are to be, or at least determines between what elements the relations are going to lie. This recognition of the importance of conduct as determining what the connections shall
be within experience
itself is
the characteristic of the latter psy-
chology. It has gone under various names.
The
was structural. That is, it took experience as we find it to pieces and found certain relations between
the various elements of it. These it explained through association.
older psychology
The
latter
psychology
is
functional rather than structural.
It recognizes certain functions of
conduct.
getting food.
We
We
have become
are hungry,
stifled
[386]
get experiences
what we are
and we set about
with the air in the room,
of distant objects, and their import for us
going to do about them.
We
lies in
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
and we get out-of-doors. We are acting, and in our actions we
determine what the relations are going to be between the various
elements in experience. The structure of the act is the important character of conduct. This psychology also is called motor
psychology, as over against the older psychology of sensation;
voluntary psychology, as over against the mere association of
ideas with each other. Finally, the development of these differ-
ent phases got expression in behavioristic psychology, which
gives itself to the study of this conduct to which
have
referred.
undertakes to approach the mind from the point of view of
the action of the individual. As a psychology, behaviorism has
It
turned away, then, from the category of consciousness as such.
Accounts of consciousness had been largely static in character.
There were certain states of consciousness, certain impressions
the imagery men had in a spiritual substance that was impressed from without by certain experiences. The senses were
the organs through which impressions were made on a substantial entity called "consciousness," and they were made in a
certain way, in a spatial, temporal order. Consciousness was
dealt with as a sort of substance which received impressions.
Following upon this came the fruitful statement of Professor
James.
For James, consciousness is not to be regarded as a static
substance receiving impressions from without. It is rather a
stream that flows on. And this stream has various characteristics, those that we express by its substantive and transitive
character. It gathers about a certain experience and then passes
on from that to another. ^Another analogy that James used was
of the bird that alights on one branch and then flies to another,
continually moving from one point to another point. The
transitive phases of experience are those answering to relations;
the substantives are those that answer to what we call the
"things we perceive." If one is speaking, relating something,
and says "and" and then stops at that point, we have the feeling
of being ready to go on to something else. The feeHng is just as
definite
an experience as that of yellow or red, of hot or cold;
[387]
it
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
an experience of "and," one that is transitive, that is moving
on. And these experiences are quaHtatively different from each
other. If, instead of saying "and," the speaker said "but," we
should have an entirely different attitude toward what is to
is
follow. In fact,
our whole grasp of what we are hearing or read-
upon the feelings we have for these different relatwe come upon a thought with a "though" in it,
we have one attitude toward what is to come; if "also," a differing depends
ing articles. If
ent attitude.
We
are ready for a certain sort of content.
We
have a definite sort of experience answering to these relations
which appear immediately in experience.
There is also another very important phase of experience
which Professor James emphasizes, that which is represented
by the
spotlight of our attention as over against the fringe of the
experience. If one gives his attention to something immediately
before him, there hes about this experience a fringe which is very
important in the recognition, in the value of that to which one
gives attention. For example, when we are reading, we often
have the experience of a world which is not immediately before us. The eye in moving over the page has caught a word
several lines below. We have to hunt for it to find out what it
was. It lies there in the fringe of our immediate experience, and
we are ready for it when it appears. But still more, these different attitudes which are connected with the different particles,
the "and," "but," "though," "also," also represent the fringe.
We are immediately considering something, but we are already
going on to something else. And the beginnings of that something else to which we are going on are already forming in the
realization of our experience. They are taking place, and they
represent the fringe of experience which comes in to interpret
that to which
we
are giving attention.
These conceptions of James's which were so fruitful for the
psychological consideration of experience do represent definitely a process which gets its whole statement in our conduct. We
are going on to something besides that which is before us. And
the structure of the experience itself depends on what we are
[388I
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
going on to do. If
in the
we
see something,
organism a tendency to meet
this experience of
what the contact
we have
it,
will
at least aroused
or to avoid
And
it.
be that comes
it is
in to give
which we actually see. We are continually
see by the something that is represented
by possible future conduct. So, to understand what is appearing
in experience, we must take into account not only the immedithe
meaning
interpreting
to that
what we
ate stimulus as such but also the response.
The
response
is
there
partly in the actual tendency toward the object and also in our
memory images, the experiences that we have had in
And this relationship of the response to the stimulus
the past.
is
one of
very great importance in the analysis of our perception.
Professor
Dewey brought out
that fact in a memorable article
on the stimulus-response concept.
attitude of being acted
fected
by the response.
process of doing
it is
He
pointed out that the very
upon by a stimulus is continually afWe start to do something, and the
continually affecting the very stimulus
we
have received. A
is sawing on a Hne. The response of the organism to the
stimulation of the line is there to determine what he will look
for. He will keep his eye on the line because he is continually
sawing. The process of listening is a process in which we turn
familiar illustration
is
that of the carpenter
who
the head in such a
way
the listening
hearing
that
is
we
will
we are
The process
way in which
be able to catch what
essential to the hearing.
always present, determining the
our so-called "impressions." That is, the organism is not simply a something that is receiving impressions and
then answering to them. It is not a sensitive protoplasm that is
of responding
we
is
shall receive
simply receiving these stimuli from without and then responding
to
them. The organism
is
doing something.
When we
When we are
It is primarily seek-
we
ing for certain stimuli.
are hungry,
to the odors of food.
looking for a book,
memory image
of the back of the book.
are sensitive
we have
Whatever we
are doing
determines the sort of a stimulus which will set free certain
responses which are there ready for expression, and
attitude of action which determines for us
[389]
it
is
the
what the stimulus
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
will be. Thorij in the process of acting
what elements
ing just
response successfully
the response as
it
we
are continually select-
in the field of stimulation will set the
free.
goes on
We have
to carry out our act so that
continually acting back upon the
is
organism, selecting for us just those stimuli which will enable
us to do what
Out of
this
we
started to do.
stimulus-response concept has developed be-
havioristic psychology.
Now,
ways of elaborating
there are two
the general point of view belonging to behaviorism.
consider
process itself in
the
an external way,
One
or,
is
as
to
the
psychologists would say, in an objective fashion; just consider
the act itself and forget about consciousness.
representative of that type of behaviorism.
of this type
is
interested simply in the act.
interested in the act as
Watson
gist"
it
Watson is the
The behaviorist
He
is
particularly
can be observed from the outside.
representative of the so-called "scientific psycholo-
is
who
is
observing that which can be observed by other
scientists. It is a
type of psychology which was developed
first
the study of animals. There you are necessarily shut
of
all in
off
from any so-called
"field of consciousness."
You
cannot deal
with the consciousness of the animal; you have to study his
actions, his conduct.
And
these psychologists carried over the
method of animal psychology
into
human
psychology.
carried over from the study of animal psychology a
what seemed
which could
They
new and,
to be, a very fruitful conception, that of the reflex
be, in their terminology,
conditioned the idea of
the conditioned reflex.
This goes back, as most of you know, to Pavlov's dog. Pavwas an objective psychologist who was studying the conduct of animals and endeavoring to make a complete statement
lov
of that conduct without bringing in the element of consciousness, that
is,
without having to refer to what was called "introHe took a dog and, by putting
spection" to understand the act.
mouth, collected the saliva that was secreted. If a
meat was brought within the vision and the sense of
odor of the dog, then saliva was secreted. The dog was all
food in
its
piece of
[390]
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
ready to eat the meat, and the glands in the mouth were preparing for the process of mastication. Now, taking the dog in
that way and bringing the meat, he was able to determine just
what the effect of this stimulus was in the production of saliva.
Then, when he brought the meat to the dog, he also rang a
bell. He kept this up long enough so that the two experiences
would be associated. He did not speak of it as the consciousness
of the dog but in terms of the process of the nervous system and
;
then he found that,
the
same
effect
if
he rang
the bell
was produced, that
without presenting meat,
is,
the excess of saliva
was
secreted without actual sight or odor of the meat. This particular reflex, then, the secretion
of sahva, was conditioned by the
association of the sound of the bell with the smell of meat, so
that, when the meat was not presented, the sound of the bell
actually acted as a stimulus in place of the smell of the
meat
itself.
This conception of conditioned
be carried over into all sorts of
them by way of
reflex is evidently
fields.
one that can
some of
baby who,
will refer to
illustration. First, take the cry of a
shown a white rat with which he has played
before without any fear. If the rat was associated with a
loud sound, the sound, especially if not seen, was a natural
stimulus of fright. If the white rat was presented to the child
when this sound was produced, the child became frightened;
and afterward, when the rat was brought to the child and
the sound not made, the child was still frightened of the rat.
That is, this particular reflex of the fright of the child was conditioned by the sight and feel of the white rat. This can be carried over to a whole set of situations. Take another example
for
example,
is
from our conventions. We expect a person to act in a certain
sort of way. We expect him to be dressed in a certain sort of
w ',y. This conduct goes along with a certain type of manners,
and these manners go along with a certain type of individual.
If we meet a person whose manners are not those we expect,
we have an attitude toward this person as one who lacks those
particular characteristics.
We
have conditioned our
[391
reflexes
by
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
these particular conventions,
many
of them entirely external
and having nothing to do with the character of the man. We
assume that certain manners represent courtesy. A great many
of the manners have nothing to do with courtesy; but they have
become so related to it that if we find a man who has rough
manners, we perhaps do not expect courtesy of him. We caTn
carry the conditioned reflex over into other
of language, where
we have
fields,
such as
tliat
a set of arbitrary symbols. Certain
We can associate with
each experience a certain arbitrary symbol, a sound, a written
word, and we can become so conditioned that when we hear the
experiences call for certain responses.
sound, see the word,
we
get the attitude which goes with the
original experience.
The conditioned reflex, then, was brought in and used by
Watson in his attempt to analyze conduct. You see, this makes
possible analysis without bringing in consciousness as such.
You do
not have to deal with introspection; you do not have to
go back and ask the person what he thinks, or feels, what
imagery arises before him. One studies simply his conduct and
sees what the stimuli are that act upon him under certain conditions. And a sort of an analysis can be made of conduct from
his standpoint.
What
is
this type of analysis goes
of importance in this
back
to the
goes back to his behavior, to what he
is
thinking and feeling, but what he
The
other approach
is
we had
itself,
that
is
conduct of the individual,
is doing
not to what he
is
doing.
that of Professor
the standpoint of the conduct
various values which
method
which
Dewey,
also
carries with
from
it
the
associated with the term "con-
sciousness." There arose at this time the question which
put so bluntly: Does consciousness exist?
He
wrote an
James
article
under that caption. Is there any such entity as consciousness
in distinction from the world of our experience? Can we s^y
that there is any such thing as consciousness which is a separate
entity apart from the character of the world itself? The question, of course, is difficult to answer directly, because the term
"consciousness" is an ambiguous one. We use it particularly for
[392]
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
we will say, by going to sleep
and waking up, going under and coming out of the anesthetic,
in losing and regaining "consciousness." We think of it as something which is a sort of entity, which is there, which has been,
under these conditions, submerged and then allowed to appear
again. That use of consciousness is not essentially different
from the shutting-ofF of any field of experience through the
experiences which are represented,
senses. If one, for example, turns out the lights in the
room,
he no longer experiences the sight of objects about him. We
say he has lost consciousness of those objects. But you would
He is simply unhe gets farther and farther away
not speak of him as having lost consciousness.
able to see
what
is
there.
If
from a sound, or the sound becomes fainter and fainter, he loses
consciousness of that sound; but he does not lose consciousness
other sense. If we closed up his eyes, shut off his nostrils,
mouth, shut him off from a whole series of different stimuli,
even those coming to him from the surface of the body and from
the visceral tract, he would probably lose consciousness, go to
sleep. There, you see, the losing of consciousness does not mean
the loss of a certain entity but merely the cutting-off of one's
in the
ears,
relations with experiences. Consciousness in that sense means
merely a normal relationship between the organism and the outside objects.
And what we
refer to as consciousness as such
really the character of the object.
object. If
We
access to
this
the object
is
is
a bright
close the eyes, there is no bright object there
would say that you have lost consciousness of
or simply that the bright object
are open,
is,
now you
any longer.
it,
That
is
not there.
When
the eyes
you have access to it; when the eyes close, you have
it no longer. You see, there are two ways of looking at
having consciousness of the object.
You may
regard con-
sciousness as a something that exists inside of the organism
somewhere, upon which the influence of certain stimuli come
play.
You may
made upon
in the
to
think of consciousness in terms of impressions
this spiritual
organism. Or you
substance in some unexplained fashion
may
think of it simply as a relationship
between the organism and the object
[393]
itself.
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
James in his answer to, or his attempted answer to, the ques"Does consciousness exist?" lays stress on the relation between the experience which the individual has had, that which
has gone before, and that which follows after. He took the illustration of a person going to a house and entering the first room.
Now that room and its furniture is an experience. You can say
that it enters his consciousness, if you like; and still you think
of the room as something there with its pictures, furniture,
whether he came in or not. If now, the house is burned up by a
fire, this particular room with its walls and pictures and furnition,
ture has disappeared.
The
had of the room, however,
experience which the individual has
is
not burned up.
He remembers
it,
remembers how the pictures were hung upon the walls. This,
says James, is a cross-section of two histories. And the crosssection is identical. The room belongs to the history of the
house. It has been there since the house was built. It is in that
particular history. When the person comes into the room, that
particular room with its furnishings becomes a fact of his history. He had been elsewhere yesterday. He comes into that
particular room, and that room is now a part of his experience;
he goes out, and it is related to his former experiences. He had
been in other houses, seen other furniture. He compares pictures. Each is related, you see, to his history. On the other
hand, this room also belongs to the history of the house, of the
architect, of the carpenter.
Thus
this question of consciousness,
according to Professor James's statement,
history
From
room
this
particular
this point of
is
entity,
so-called
is
a question in
what
consciousness,
hes.
view the consciousness a
man
a cross-section of his history, while the
has of the
room
in the
house regarded as a physical affair is a cross-section of the history of the house. Here we have a single cross-section answering
Or there is a coincidence of cross-sections. In that case what we would say is that the consciousness
of the man in regard to the room in the house is nothing but a
statement of that room as it lies in relationship to the man's
to both of these series.
own
history:
taken in
its
relationship to the history of the
[394I
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
house,
physical; taken in
it is
its
relationship to the history of
man, it is a conscious event.
These two are not the only implications or meanings of consciousness. That which represents mental activities of one sort
of volition, of analytic and synthetic thought, of
or another
purpose and intention on the one side, and on the other side certhe
tain contents
has been stated
in the past in associational psy-
chology as states of consciousness. On the one hand, as we have
seen, the active side can be stated in terms of conduct, while
that which might be referred to as the passive definition of consciousness can be regarded as belonging to the object
So
itself.
far as such a division of the spoils takes place, consciousness as a
private affair seems largely to disappear. There are other phases
it, as I have said, which we will not refer to now; but these
two phases, these two conceptions of consciousness, I wanted to
of
an active, the other a passive, statement. And
have said is that this active phase, that involved in the
bring out.
what
One
is
motor, volitional
side, as well as in the process of analysis
and
discrimination, can at least be stated in terms of conduct, of
the act; and this act can be stated in terms of the organism as
such.
What we
found to
lie in
refer to as the passive side, the content side,
the object. It can be regarded, of course, in
is
its re-
lationship to the individual. It does belong to his history, though
not simply to his history but to that of the object as well.
man
is
in the
ence. It
is
interpreted in terms of
the
tion.
But
room, the room
still it is
is
stated in
When
terms of his experi-
memory, of his own anticiparoom. Without attempting to discuss the
various philosophic implications of
this, I
am
pointing out that
in its passive
on the one side you may
sense and at the same time be thinking of the object, the room
speak of consciousness
itself.
In some fashion,
if
we
turn to the active side
we have impulse
as perhaps the most fundamental phase of activity; and impulse
certainly can be given a statement in terms not only of acts but
also of the organism.
There are various fundamental physioand flight, those which gather
logical impulses, that of attack
[
395
THOUGHT
about hunger and
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
These are lodged in the organism itself.
James's celebrated theory of the emotions comes back to the
reaction to the motor attitudes of the organism itself in condisex.
tions such as fear, hunger, love, joy.
That
is,
fear represents our
response to our tendency to run away; hatred represents our re-
The emotions as such are reits own attitudes under certain
sponse to our tendency to attack.
sponses of the organism
conditions.
itself to
These responses are expressed
in
more or
less vio-
lent action.
What
further involved here, that which
James did not
bring out which Dewey does, is that there is always some inhibition of these actions. If one could actually run away before the
is
terrifying object, if one could keep
full
ahead of
it,
so to speak, give
expression to the tendency to run, one would not be terri-
If one could actually strike the very moment one had the
impulse to strike, he would not be angry. It is the checking of
the response that is responsible for the emotion, or is essential
at least to the emotion. Even in the case of joy, if there were
fied.
no hesitancy about the way in which one expressed his happiness, there would not be that emotion.
We can approach the emotion, then, from the point of view
of our own responses to the attitudes of the organism. Here the
James-Lange theory recognizes the visceral, as well as the
motor, responses involved in the act. We spoke of the emotion
as our effective experience of these attitudes.
The impulse
is
something that can be stated at least in terms of the response
of the organism itself. It is, of course, out of the impulse that
desires, intentions, arise. What is added to the impulse and
desire is the image of what we intend. And here we seem to find
ourselves in what might be regarded in an unassailable field of
consciousness as such. By its very definition imagery would be
not the object, but some copy of the object; not the past event,
but some memory of the past event; not future conduct, but a
picture of future conduct. If you ask, now, where this image is,
you would be at a loss to locate it. The easiest thing is to say
that
it is
in consciousness,
whether you put that consciousness
[
396
in
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
your head or say that you cannot locate it spatially. In any
it is a relationship to something in your head. At least, the
assumption of our physiological psychology is that an image
answers to the excitement of certain nerve elements which have
been excited in past experience. A cruder form of physiological
psychology assumed that pictures of what had happened, were
lodged, so to speak, in nerve cells, and, if the organism pressed
a button, these pictures would come out. But further study revealed the fact that the nerve cells were no more than paths and
junctions of paths. They should not be regarded as cubbyholes
in which memory images or any other images are stored away.
Just where the image is, is, I say, questionable. But you cannot
say that the image is not in the objective world, for many of
case,
them are.
Here again
am
not discussing the various philosophical im-
plications of this analysis, but merely referring to the fact that
it your own memory
images of words you have read before. Your own eye touches a
line of print perhaps only twice. You take in only a relatively
small portion of the actual printed line on the page, and the rest
of it comes from memory images. I have referred to the atti-
every book you read has on every page of
tudes represented by particles, adverbs, conjunctions, prepositions, the
"ands," "buts," and "thoughs," which put us in cer-
tain attitudes of anticipation of a certain sort of
expected.
The
context
definite anticipation of
we have gone over
what
is
word that
is
gives us a pretty
going to be there, so that our
from past experience. We have not time enough to
itself. There are people, children particularly, whose eyes are bound to the page. They have to read word
by word; and if they cannot be freed from it, they are slow
readers and can accomplish little in this medium. What we have
to do is to make most of what we read a contribution of our
own. We fill out what we see. That, of course, is evident not
only at the time. You suddenly find yourself in a snarl. You
see something which is not there. The proofreader has trained
himself to notice the words and letters and not the sense.
mind
fills
in
read each word by
[397]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
is true not only of the printed page. The faces
are largely filled in by our memories of
acquaintances
our
of
them. We notice very little in the outlines of a face with which
we are familiar. The rest of it comes from memory images. If
Well, that
we
are seeing a person for the
first
time,
we regard
the features
but even then what we see in
type. You could not tell what
a
sort
of
each case is in some sense
the types of the human face are that you recognize. Yet, there
in detail, look at the
whole
face;
something about every human face that is in some sense
and you fill in there. A considerable part of our perceptual world, the world existing "out there," as we say, is made
up out of mental images, the same stuff that comes before us
in revery, only in that case we are looking at it from the point
of view of imagination. These images actually go to make up
is
typical,
we
and feel.
The imagery cannot all be put into a consciousness that is
distinct from the world about us. It goes back, as I say, to
James's question as to whether consciousness as such exists.
We have again a type of experience which from one point of
view belongs to the external world and from another point of
view to the history of the particular individual. Without atobjects
see
tempting to discuss the question further, I simply want to
emphasize the fact that the former is the passive side of our
experience, which we ordinarily term "consciousness," but
which under various conditions we do not consider as consciousness but as the object. If you should take away the so-called
"imagery" from what you say you immediately see, from that
which answers to what falls on the retina, to the sounds you
actually hear, you would find that you have bare skeletal elements; most of the flesh and blood, of the content of the world
about you, would have been taken out. What you call the
"meaning" of it will go also. The distinction you make between
what we call "consciousness" and what we call the "world" is
really a functional distinction. It
not, then, cut off
any
is
not a static one.
You
can-
particular field of content in our ordinary
experience of the world and say, "This
[398I
is
my
consciousness as
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
such. This
is
a certain stuff
which belongs inside of my head and
not to the world." There are times at which it is inaccessible.
But the printed page you see you hand to your friend, who reads
it also. A large part of what he reads is his mental image, and
what you read is your mental image; and yet you say you
reading the same page.
are
problem of psychology simply from the
what takes place in the experience of the individual as an individual, you get a surer clue if
you take the man's action than if you take certain static contents and say these are the consciousness of the man and that
these have to be approached by introspection to be reached. If
you want to find out what the man is doing, what he is, you
will get it a good deal better if you will get into his conduct, into
his action. And you come back there to certain of his impulses,
those impulses which become desires, plus his mental images,
which from one standpoint are his own but from another standIf one approaches the
standpoint of trying to find out
point represent certain of his past experiences, or part of his
future experience. So-called "objective" or "behavioristic" psy-
chology undertakes to examine the acts of the
man from
outside
without trying to get them by introspection as such, although
introspection, as I shall show, has a certain definite meaning
even for behavioristic psychology.
have already referred to accessibility. There are certain
very genuine experiences which belong to physical objects and
yet which are accessible only to the individual himself, notably,
a toothache. There is an aching tooth, no question about it; and
yet, though others can see the tooth and the dentist can tap it,
it aches only for the individual in whose head it is located, and
much as he would like to he cannot transfer that ache to
somebody else. There are, of course, a whole series of experiences of which that is typical, which are accessible alone to the
person having them. What I want to point out is that you have
no question about the aching tooth, no question about the
members of your body. Your hands have certain definite characteristics for you. They can be seen by others, but you have
I
[399]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
And
the only inside approach to them.
is
that feeling
just as genuinely a feeling of an object as
is
is
one which
that of a table.
You
feel the table, and you feel your hand. Your hand is softer
and warmer than the table. Your hand is not as large as the
table. All sorts of distinctions can be made. You are feeling
your hand as a physical object, but one having a peculiar character, and that character which it has is one which is accessible
only to yourself. Nobody else can get that feel of your hand
which you have, and yet that does not make you regard it as
less genuinely there. You do not put the feel of your hand in
your brain. You may assume that that feel is dependent on
what is in your brain, but what the hand is involves the actual
character that it itself has. Well now, if anybody else comes up
and feels the table, he has a sense of the same table; but this approach to the feeling is peculiar to the individual. The mere
fact of the accessibility to the experience you have of parts of
your own body does not lodge them, so to speak, in a consciousness which is located in the brain or somewhere else. It simply
means certain objects are accessible to you which are not accessible to anybody else.
There are various phases of nature which lie betwixt and between. Take the beauty of a landscape as an instance. From
one point of view it is the response of the individual himself and
seems to be accessible only to him, but the painter and the poet
succeed seemingly in making
it
accessible to those
who enjoy
is more or less debatable. All I
on is that mere accessibility is not in itself evidence of something that belongs to a consciousness. It is much
safer, even in such fields as these, to come back to the conduct
of the individual if you are going to study him than to come
back to something he reports to you by means of introspection.
Without discussing the various logical and metaphysical
snarls involved, we will say that the space about us is public.
We are all living in the same spatial world and have experiences
of the same world. When it comes to a question of color, the
thing seems to be dubious, for one man does not see certain
the picture and the poem. This
want
to insist
[400]
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
colors
man
which another
there where the color
is
does
see.
We
seem
private while the space
have a case
to
is
public.
And
you cannot,ppssibly separate the space from the color. And,
while you may say that the space which one person perceives
has a different degree of brightness from another, we would not
hesitate to call those spaces public. But there is also something
definitely private. Take a man's intentions, for example. We
do not know what he is going to do. He has an advantage over
us on that account. This is notable in the case of warfare, or in
the case of a man who is making a feint when he is boxing. The
intent which the person has is not evident to the other person.
yet,
He may make
going to strike
This
is
a guess at
it,
who knows
but
who
definitely
what he intends
to do.
is
also true of intent not simply in such a situation but in all
our intercourse with other people.
what we
idea, as a rule, of
but the person to
may
only the person
it is
We
have a pretty genuine
are going to say
whom we
when we
are talking;
are talking probably does not.
He
guess from past experience; but, as a rule, what a person
is
going to say would in some sense present a problem to the other
person while
it
going to say
it.
That
is
would be present
It is
also true in
mind of the one who
is
very large degree of certain types of mena field, a sort of an inner forum, in which
tal
imagery. There
we
are the only spectators
is
in the
not public property.
and the only
each one of us confers with himself.
actors. In that field
We carry on something of a
drama. If a person retires to a secluded spot and sits down to
think, he talks to himself. He asks and answers questions. He
develops his ideas and arranges and organizes those ideas as he
might do in conversation with somebody else. He may prefer
talking to himself to talking to
preciative audience, perhaps.
somebody else. He is
The process is not
more ap-
essentially
two cases, that is, of thinking and of talking
somebody else. It is essentially the same sort of a process.
But the activity, such as it is, is not of the same sort. When you
do talk to yourself, you do not ordinarily do it out loud. Sometimes you do talk out loud, and somebody else hears you. But,
different in these
to
[401
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
when you talk to yourself, you depend on subtle motor
and muscular methods of articulation. Supposing that conversation which takes place by such imagery as that is only acas a rule,
cessible to the
man
carrying
it
on.
He
takes different roles.
He
asks questions and meets them; presents arguments and refutes
them.
It
He
does
it
himself,
and
it lies
has not yet become pubUc. But
does become public.
We
it is
say he
will
inside of the
is
man
himself.
a part of the act which
thinking out what he
is
going to say in an important situation, an argument which he
going to present in court, a speech in the legislature. That
process which goes on inside of him is only the beginning of the
is
process which
is
finally carried
on
in
an assembly.
It is just a part
of the whole thing, and the fact that he talks to himself rather
than to the assembly
of a process which
is
simply an indication of the beginning
carried on outside.
is
Well now, that process of talking to one's self of thinking,
as we say
is a process which we speak of as involving discrimination, analysis. Analysis may be a very physical affair. We
can smash up an object by means of a hammer and analyze it.
We can take it into the laboratory and use more subtle methods
of disintegration. But we are analyzing the object either way.
We may analyze a thing for somebody else. He wants to find
something in it which he cannot see, and we point it out. We
point at the particular part of the object he is to take hold of.
Now, that pointing is a process of analyzing the object. For
him
it is
the selection of
some part of the object
of other parts, so that he can get hold of
it.
to the neglect
Indicating by the
up by a hammer
by chemical reagents. There are various ways of pointing at
things. There are people among certain native tribes who can
point at things by their own features, their lips, eyes, the way
in which they turn their head. I have seen people carry on
finger
is
just as
much
analysis as breaking
or
rather elaborate conversations that way.
which we do our pointing
ing of the finger
Words
is
is
The ordinary way
by means of vocal
in
gestures. Point-
a physical gesture.
are gestures
by means of which we indicate things;
[402]
MIND APPROACHED THROUGH BEHAVIOR
and, just in so far as
tures,
test
we
we
by means of our geswe put them into a
we took our hammer and smashed the
indicate things
are analyzing just as really as
tube of acid or as
thing up to find out
if
its
if
different elements. It
is
a process of
analyzing some element by means of our conduct. Thinking,
as such, can at least be stated. I am finding all sorts of problems which can be brought up. Even the most recondite intellectual processes come back to the things we do; and, of course,
for an intelligent human being his thinking is the most important part of what he does and the larger part of that think-
ing
is
a process of the analysis of situations, finding out just
it is that ought to be attacked, what has to be avoided.
have to take the situation to pieces, think it out; and that
process may be a process of pointing or of vocal gestures which
indicate certain elements in it. Those vocal gestures are the
indication of the elements which will lead to certain responses.
One of the principal differences between a dog and a man is that,
as a rule, we cannot point out to a dog what we want him to
give attention to. If you can find out what the dog's interests
are, you may be able to point something out to him; but if you
want to have the dog tell time, you can never get him to look
at a watch and notice where the hands of the watch are. Even
if a person does not know what a watch is, you can indicate to
a human individual the face of the watch and get him to see the
meaning of it. That part of our thinking process, the power of
analysis by means of gestures, is the most important part; and
we can say, if you hke, that we carry that on inside of our heads.
The sense in which we do that is to use these pointers, these
vocal gestures, the words which we utilize, to point out certain
features in a situation; but we do that inside of ourselves. Occasionally, people do hear us. We talk out loud. But as a rule
they do not hear us, and we reply to the gestures that we make
with other gestures; and in that fashion we get our plan of
what
We
action
made
Well, that
for ourselves.
is
the
way
in
which behavioristic psychology,
carried out consistently enough, can cover the
[403]
field
if
of psy-
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
chology without bringing in the dubious conception of consciousness. There are matters which are accessible only to the
individual, but even these cannot be identified with conscious-
we find we are continually utilizing them as
making up our world. What you can do is to get at the organism as something that you can study. Now it is true that you
cannot tell what a man is thinking about unless he chooses to
tell. If he tells, you have access to that as well as he has; and
you know what he is going to do, and it can enter into your
ness as such because
conduct. You can get at your own conduct and at the
conduct of other people by considering that conduct in an objective sort of fashion. That is what behavioristic psychology
is trying to do, trying to avoid the ambiguity of the term "consciousness." And what is of importance about this psychology
is that it carries us back, as I have said, to the act as such. It
considers the organism as active. It is out of the interest in the
act itself and the relationship of thought to the act itself that
the last phase of more recent philosophy dealt with above, that
is, pragmatism, arises. Out of the type of psychology which
own
you may
for
call
"behavioristic"
came
a large part of the stimulus
a pragmatic philosophy. There were several sourceSj. of
course; but that
is
one of the principal ones.
[404
CHAPTER
XVIII
INDIVIDUALITY IN THE NINETEENTH
CENTURY
WAS
referring in certain preceding sections to the social
mechanism through which the individual registers that
which is peculiar to his own experience, a mechanism which
is most strikingly illustrated in the newspaper, in its giving of
news, news being regarded peculiarly as something that hap-
Now, that which is novel
an individual as an individual.
going down, the ordinary courses of the
pens, something that in itself
must appear
The
is
novel.
in the experience of
rising of the sun, its
these happen to us all, take place for us all. There is
no necessity of bearing testimony to them from the point of
view of any particular individual. But when something strange
takes place, it can only be validated through its introduction
into somebody's biography; it must be said of it that John
Smith or A or B had this experience at such a time and such a
place. That is, we cannot give universal value to that which is
individual. It just happens; it is something that we can state
only in terms of the fact that it happened to somebody, at a
certain place and at a certain time.
seasons
have already referred to the import of this in the exceptions
which make the basis for the scientific problems and the
to laws
formation of new hypotheses. It
entist that
tion. I
is
is
the observation of the
do not mean to say that the statement
single individual.
On
the contrary,
what the
he has experienced such a novelty
under which
experience.
sci-
essential for the establishment of such an excep-
it
is
it
comes
to
them
confined to a
scientist does
when
to state the conditions
has occurred, so that others
But
is
may have
the
same
also as a separate experience.
TJie^data of science, especially the exceptions that are noted,
[405]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
and located with reference to individuals. When we
come back to those precious events which are the starting-point
for the testing and carrying-out of the scientific problem, we
come back to the experience of individuals as such, experiences
which are the so-called "hard facts" of science. What is meant
by their being "hard" is that they just happen when they are
not expected. You stumble over them and scrape your shins
against them. They are something there that you are not adjusted to, and they have no universal value as yet; so you have
to state them in terms of your own experience only.
All this shows again the two sides of the scientific experience:
one, its laws, which give meaning to the world; and the other,
the experience of individuals just as individuals. Both must be
kept clearly in mind. They are the two poles, the foci about
which the orbit of science runs. What I want to point out is
are dated
that even scientific observation of this individual sort
tially
news. That
is
what constitutes news.
gives import to so-called news.
mere
fact, of course, that it
a single individual.
The important
That
thing
is
What
is
is
essen-
It is that
which
of interest
is
not the
has taken place in the experience of
is
going on everywhere
the fact that that which
all
is
the time.
going on in
some way runs counter to
accustomed. For example, the result of
the experience of the individual in
that to which
we
are
the measurements of the positions of the stars about the sun
during an ecHpse was news when
The
Einstein.
And if it
is
flourishing of a
new
or Harry;
started the hypothesis of
star in the heavens
is
news.
recorded, that record has to be in terms of the experi-
ence of individuals. It has to be
who made
it
the observations.
it
known just who
It could
the people were
not be any
Tom, Dick,
has to be a competent person, from our standpoint,
may be of importance. It is necestook place, the exact second and fraction
of a second, as well as the location which gave the conditions
for the proper observation. The time at which it took place has
in order that his experience
sary to
know when
it
to be stated. And it has what we may call from the journalese
standpoint "sensational value." The data of science, if they can
[406]
INDIVIDUALITY IN NINETEENTH CENTURY
be brought out so that people can realize their merit, are
sational.
When murders and
all
sen-
divorces are recorded, they are
sensational just in so far as these immediate experiences run
counter to the customs and habits, to the valuation of the group
to which the persons involved belong. They are sensational for
the
same reason that the records of the
positions of the stars
about the rim of the sun were sensational. The same data which
are presented in the sensational press become scientific data
when a competent social scientist studies them, examines them,
gets them into such shape that they can be evaluated. There
is nothing we may assume that is improper to appear on the
front page of a paper which does not have its perfectly legitimate place if only it is reported by a competent person who can
evaluate it. But what I am insisting on now is that what gives
it its importance is that it takes place in the experience of the
individual.
I
have perhaps given
sufficient
emphasis to the reason
for this.
Just because it is in some sense exceptional, you cannot state
it in terms of uniformities. You have to state it, then, in terms
of somebody's biography. It just happened to him. Well, what
modern experience has succeeded
in
doing
these exceptional experiences and
make
is
to get control over
use of them.
Look
through the literature of the ancient world, through such a
really marvelous book as Aristotle's Habits of Animals, which
sums up the biological knowledge of the ancient world. You
will be struck by the fact that there is not a reference to a proper
name, to an individual, as a basis for the accounts which are
given of the animals with which Aristotle's treatise deals. He
refers to a num.ber of philosophers whose opinions he is combating; but when he comes to the statement of the character of
animals he is describing, he never once refers to any individuals
as having made this observation or that. He does not rest the
value of the thought he is presenting on the testimony of anybody. On the other hand, if you are to look, for example, into
that natural historian, Pliny, you will find recorded observations,
statements of events with seemingly no basis for criticism
[407]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
He gives you a remarkable account of the overwhelming of Pompeii, of the eruption of
Vesuvius; and the facts he cites are such that any school child
would discount. There is no basis for the criticism of the value
of what we term "observation." The ancient world did not
of the value of the evidence.
what we call the "scientific method." It organized the
experience and works of men such as Aristotle the experience
of the community and put it in more or less systematic form;
but there was no mechanism for its reconstruction, no mechanism for the test of the experience of the individual, and for a
utihze
statement of the
scientific
problem, for the formation of hy-
potheses and the testing of these, which constitutes our
entific
method.
It
because
is
we do
utilize this
method that
sci-
these experiences
of individuals qua individuals have come to have such supreme
importance in our lives, and I am calling your attention to the
fact that the newspaper is simply the popular expression of just
this fact. And that which appears in the newspaper is logically
of the same character as that which appears in scientific magazines. We can just as well refer to these magazines as constituting newspapers.
They
record observations, happenings, experi-
which are things that happen to certain
individuals; and the importance of these events lies in the fact
that they have happened to just these individuals, that they
can be put into the experience of this man whom we know to
be competent, who can state just what the custom or law or
theory is that this particular event has contravened. Consequently, we can state the problem and the ideas of the individuals that are brought forward. The hypotheses are brought
forward not in the form of the newspaper editorial but as the
interpretation of events. The newspaper editorial in some de-
ments of
scientists,
same thing. It undertakes to give the
what has happened. It takes the events of
the day or of the preceding day and picks out what is peculiarly important, and interprets it either in terms of older laws
or of some new idea. There is not the scientific control, of
gree, of course, does this
interpretation of
[408I
INDIVIDUALITY IN NINETEENTH CENTURY
course, in the editorial that
you have
in
the scientist's hy-
pothesis; but the newspaper editorial does put before us the
community problems. And what appears in the editorial is an
attempted interpretation of them in some sense, giving the
meaning of them so far as they are novel, implying that some
change, some reconstruction, ought to take place in order to deal
with them.
Our whole literature from the period of the Renaissance has
become increasingly more journalese in its character. We have
become distinctly interested in biographies, for example. Go
back again to the ancient world, and you have in Plutarch
the biography of the ancient world. Read his Lives, and you
find that he presents his figures either as typical heroes or
typical villains, one class or the other.
They embody
tudes and the views, the values, of the community
belonged.
Or they stand out
to
the atti-
which they
as striking criminals, people of the
type of Alcibiades. But, on the other side, you have the person
who
what
is
is
These figures present
which represents the virtues and
essentially of the hero character.
characteristic, that
the vices of the
community. What we
fail
to find in these bi-
ographies as contrasted with modern biographies
is
just that
which commonly goes under the caption of "local color." They
do not try to record experiences just as they took place; there
is no reference to the form of, say, the food the hero ate,
nothing of particular interest in the matter of clothes, or his
golf score, the elements which we bring in by way of making a
person seem real to us. These elements are all omitted. What
the modern biography does is to try to reproduce as far as possible those little things which enable you to put yourself into
the situation of the individual so that you get his experiences
and experience them.
To get an analogous contrast, go to the Louvre and see the
statues which have come down from the ancient world
"Venus," "Hermes," in their calmness and perfection; and then
Luxembourg to see modern statues. You get
of movement. The one with that perfection of the
step across to the
a sense of life,
[409]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
type which ancient art has given and which has never been
given in any such transcendent type since that time. When
we undertake to represent that which is typical, we always
present what is abstract. Look at the statue we have put on
the Chamber of Commerce building, which represents "Commerce." Compare it with the ancient statue "Hermes"; or the
statue on the Courthouse representing "Justice."
The
and give
ancient
it
world was able to take that which is
tent and the meaning which belongs to such a philosophy as
Plato's. What we present is that which is immediate, living,
because we are able to utilize that, because we can take that
typical
which occurs
tion of
to the individual
and
the con-
utilize it for the interpreta-
life.
great expression of this, of course,
is
in the novel,
which
undertakes to present the meaning of life in terms of its occurrence to the individual. You can see that the novel and the
newspaper belong to the same picture. They are taking happenings and putting the meaning of life not into a moral theory,
not into a social theory as such; they are trying to give
it
actually happens
to individuals, to
life
as
men, women, and children.
and when a person is able to see exactly
what it is that he gets from the novel he is reading, he feels in
some sense enriched when he has read an admirable one. His
life has had content added to it. He has been given a new point
of view, a new approach, a new way of looking at things; and
It takes place there;
the novelty involved in
it
leads to a richer experience, just as
way makes us feel that
problems which we face has been
novelty in some
the meaning of the
social
revealed to us.
makes us
It
our consciousness as such is a continued
meeting and solution of problems, or an attempted solution of
them. This is not abnormal; it is just the nature of consciousness itself. And, as I have insisted, the problem has to appear in
realize that
the experience of the individual.
in a generalized form.
The
comes universal. The problem
The
The problem never appears
we work out and test be-
solution
itself is
always individual.
place of the individual as an important, extremely valu-
[410]
INDIVIDUALITY IN NINETEENTH CENTURY
comes into our thought by way of religion. The
human soul was made central in modern
experience in religious terms. The soul was that which was to
be saved, and saved from an eternity of suffering. That was the
yardstick, in some sense, by which one estimated the value of
the individual. But we have another sense of the import of the
individual as such, namely, that the problems with which our
able, thing
preciousness of the
reflective consciousness deals are in the experience of the indi-
vidual.
They must appear
in the experience of the individual;
they come in some sense as a new view of
life, as an aspect of life peculiar to him. If we do not get this,
we lose a certain kind of experience, a certain amount of it.
There are problems that arise, as we all know, in the lives of
and
for the individual
every one of us; and in so far as they are not mere mistakes,
they, represent an onward movement. Progress, as I have
pointed out, even from the point of view of evolution,
constant meeting of problems and solving them. It
is
may
the
take
nature five hundred thousand years to solve a particular probin digestion. But the problems that appear in the experi-
lem
ence of each individual represent the poles of hfe
what we are doing: we
are solving problems,
itself.
This
is
and those prob-
lems can appear only in the experience of the individual. It is
that which gives the importance to the individual, gives him
a value which cannot be stated. He has a certain preciousness
which cannot be estimated. You cannot tell what will happen
to him, what must happen to him. Take cattle, on the other
hand; one is like another. There is nothing represented in the
experience of one ox that is peculiar to him. But a human individual, when he is a self, has this capacity to state and meet
problems peculiar to himself. There is something that takes
place in his perspective that does not occur for
anybody
else.
Each one of us has an outlook on the universe which belongs
to each one of us alone, and it appears in so far as we have in us
a reflective consciousness in which
life seems to be interpreted.
do not write epics in our day; or, when we do, nobody
reads them. We write novels, and we write dramas, which rep-
We
[411]
THOUGHT
resent
life
and
its
import
individual as such.
able in the sense
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
in
terms of that which happens to an
Of course, this makes the individual invalunot in terms
that we cannot evaluate him
of the eternity of suffering, or of more or less abstract blessed-
what his function is as an individual in the
community, that function which belongs to him in his particular perspective. I have brought in the term "perspective" both
because it expresses this point of view which I was presenting
and also because it brings us into this latest expression both of
science and philosophy, "relativity."
From the point of view of the most abstract of physical sciness, but in terms of
ences,
it
has been recognized that the world, taken from the
point of view of any particular physical particle or any particu-
even such as that of an atom of iron, is
you think of it for a moment, it is really astonishing the change that has taken place recently in the mechanical
sciences from that in which every physical particle could be
given its place in an absolute space and time. By the mere development of physical science itself, especially through the
theory of electromagnetism and the analysis of the spatial and
lar physical structure,
shifting. If
temporal conception, we find abstract physical science taking
this most extremely novel point of view: if you give a certain
velocity to a certain particle, the world from the point of view
of that particle is a different world than it is if the particle has
is a different time; and the space is
you cannot regard the universe except
another velocity; the time
a different space.
That
is,
from the point of view of this particular particle in its essential
characters. Well now, perhaps that particle does not exist by
itself. There is a consentient state, a group of other physical
particles which have the same velocities. Take them at rest,
and the whole world has a certain value from that standpoint;
put them in motion, and it has another value; change the motion
again,
and again the value changes. What we had assumed was
that such a relative statement could always be read over into an
absolute statement.
tion of the
We realize
heavens as a
we cannot take the revolupresentation of the real movement of
that
[412]
INDIVIDUALITY IN NINETEENTH CENTURY
We put
things.
the earth
is
ourselves in the position of the sun and see that
moving about
sition of the
its axis;
and when we come
sun with reference to other
stars,
we
to the po-
see that
it is
moving; and so we
set up so-called "co-ordinates" of the fixed
But we know there is no such thing as a fixed star. Thus,
stars.
end we have nothing to which to attach our Cartesian coWe cannot take our point of view and the point of
view of a man from Mars and that of a man in the sun and reduce them all to a certain absolute space in which we can tell
what the real mass of a body is. All we have is an indefinite
number of perspectives. From the point of view of the physical
sciences, that shift of perspectives is analogous to what we have
been presenting from the point of view of society. That is the
reality of the world: it is an organization of the perspectives of
all individuals in it. And every individual has something that is
in the
ordinates.
Our
peculiar to himself.
science has grasped that precious pecu-
him to get hold of the problem
whose solution gives a new heaven and a new earth. And we realize this in our daily talk and conversation, where we see that
eac h o rie..Qf u s h as his own value and own standpoint.
Now, from an earlier point of view that meant what the
philosophers called "solipsism." It meant that the real world
had to be translated into the perspective of each one, and that
there was no way of getting out of one's perspective into that
of somebody else. That is, it means the defeat of any universal
philosophy or, seemingly, of science. And, of course, there have
liarity of the scientist that enables
been
want
all
sorts of philosophical battles
to point out
is
waged over
simply that science
itself
this.
What
has never been
disturbed by this sort of so-called "subjective idealism." It has
gone on utilizing that which is peculiar to the individual, seeing
the world in terms of the individual, getting the problem involved there and then obtaining a solution which is one that belongs to the more inclusive consentient set, which belongs to the
member. The individual
comown particular perspective arises in that com-
community of which
himself
is,
munity, as
after
his
all,
the individual
is
there only in so far as he arises in the
[413]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
munity. In some sense you may say that that represents the
form of the philosophical problem which has been presented
through relativity.
Another striking phase that has arisen in modern scientific
and philosophic thought is found in the category of emergence.
From such a relativistic point of view as we are stating, people
will recognize, for example, that there is such a thing as color
in the world. It belongs to the perspective of people that have
normal retinas. If your retina is not normal, then your color
perspective is different. The color does not exist in your "soul";
your self to the world. It is a different
world in its relation to you than in its relation to me. There are
slight differences if you like, and there are other differences which
we can interpret as real differences. Well now, if that is true, when
retinas appear, in their relation to the central nervous system,
it
exists in the relation of
color appears. It
is
presented not in the consciousness of these
particular forms, but
to
it appears in the relationship of the world
organisms that are endowed with retinas. When the canals,
which developed into an ear, appeared in the side of the head
and enabled the form to orient itself to sound, noise and music
appeared. It did not come to exist in the consciousness of the
individual as such, but in the relationship to the world of the
organisms endowed with such apparatus. When individuals
with appreciation for beauty appeared, beauty appeared. It did
not reside in the consciousness of these individuals but came
into existence, emerged, through the relationship of the world
to the individual.
The problem which
faces thought, then,
is
the problem of
the relationship of individuals to each other, or the perspec-
each other. These philosophical
appear
in
terms
of
problems
relativity. It may be that it presents an attempted solution in terms which are thought to be
consistent with Einstein's statement, as is the case with Bertives of these individuals to
trand Russell's book called Philosophy^ which
perspective
more or
less in the
still
leaves each
consciousness of the individual
but does set up some unknowable world outside. This
[414]
is
one
INDIVIDUALITY IN NINETEENTH CENTURY
philosophical attempt to solve that problem.
Or
it
tempted from the point of view of Whitehead, with
may
be
at-^
his recogni-
tion of an organization of these perspectives themselves.
I
will just call
your attention again to the fact that the state-
ment we have given of the self as it arises in the human community is one which does definitely represent such an organization of perspectives. That is, the individual comes to realize
himself just in so far as he can take the attitude of the group to
which he belongs.
He
those terms.
He
can approve or disapprove of himself in
stands on his
own
legs just in so far as
he as-
sumes his own perspective, criticizes it, and reconstructs it.
Other people can put themselves in his place, as in the novel and
newspaper; and then the same reconstruction can take place.
There you seemingly have just this organization of perspectives
going on.
munity
They
What
as such
all
society represents
is
is
exactly
this.
The com-
the organization of the perspectives of
ization of the perspectives of real
all.
But it is an organindividuals. Each one has his
belong to the same consentient
set.
own perspective, and he can assert it against the group.
And the scientific method is that by means of which the
indi-
vidual can state his criticism, can bring forward the solution,
and bring
to
it
consciousness
the test of the community.
ness"
is
an ambiguous term
That
is
what takes
made
We do have
or, better, in social experience, since
place.
in social
"conscious-
real organization of perspectives.
Whether that can be taken over and
the basis for a philosophic solution
is
another question.
But the problem as it lies is whether to take it in terms of relativity and of a space-time world or whether to take it in terms
of the lives of individuals in a human community. W^hether in
terms of scientific advance in any direction, the problem is
definitely one of this organization of individual perspectives and
the finding-out of what is universal, but with the recognition
that,
when we do
find that out, the very character of one's
an individual lies in discovering some exception to the
universal and going on to the formation of other universals. It
also requires the recognition that this is not simply a series of
self as
[415]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
revolutions but the very quality, the very nature, of reflective
experience. It is that which distinguishes each individual from
every other in the whole group to which he belongs. That is the
form of the problem, then, which science, philosophy, and reflec-
approach at the present time.
There is another phase of it I wanted also to call to your attention particularly. As I have said, a subjective idealism takes
the content of the world and puts it into the consciousness of
the individual. And as you remember, the romantic idealists
took the meaning of the universe as a whole and put it into the
consciousness of an Absolute Self of which our separate consciousnesses were mere aspects or phases. They took the whole
of the world and put it into the consciousness of the individual.
I have referred again and again to the ambiguity of this term
''consciousness." What the modern movement is doing is taking what has been the consciousness of the individual and carrying it out into the world again and realizing that it belongs to
the latter, and yet keeping this relationship of the world to the
particular individual. The world is a different world to each
individual. That does not mean that the consciousness inside
of me is different from yours, but that the universe from my
point of view is different than it is from your point of view.
Those are genuine aspects of the world as such. The relationtion
ship of the universe to the separate individuals
is
genuine.
One
can, from this conception, return the stolen goods to the uni-
back its color, its form, its meaning and beauty,
which had been lodged in the consciousness of separate individuals. They can be returned to the world when we realize
verse, give
it
that the universe has a different aspect as
it
exists over against
each separate individual.
What
science has always assumed, whether
to give a philosophic statement to
has a definite import
And
it
or not,
we have been
is
able
that the universe
in its relationship to separate individuals.
some way we have to get an organization of those differences in the whole, the meaning of which shall be different from
in
that of absolute idealism. Absolute idealism tried to solve the
I416]
INDIVIDUALITY IN NINETEENTH CENTURY
problem by uniting
all
these different individuals into a single
Absolute Self, and the attempt broke down, because it never
could state the scientific method as such. But the scientific
method goes on. And the continued reconstructions of the world
go on
The
reconstructions not only of the future but of the past.
we study is not the history of a few years ago.
cannot say that events remain the same. We are c ontinually reconstructing the world from our own standpoint.
And that reconstruction holds just as really with the so-called
"irrevocable" past as with reference to a future. The past is
history which
We
is. We do not know what the
Caesar or the Charlemagne of the next century will be. We
look over histories which have dealt with Caesar, but we find
a different Caesar portrayed in each one. A dozen different'
Caesars have crossed the Rubicon. We are continually recon-
just as uncertain as the future
structing the world, and that
means
is
what our consciousness means;
it
from the standpoint of the individual.
as broad a form as I can, this is the philosophical
this reconstruction
Stating
it
in
problem that faces the community at the present time: How
are we to get the universahty involved, the general statement
which must go with any interpretation of the world, and still
make use of the differences which belong to the individual as
an individual.^
417]
APPENDIX
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY IN THE
NINETEENTH CENTURY
HE
background of philosophy in France in the nineis, in one sense, the background of all
teenth century
philosophy in the nineteenth century, that of revolution
and the varying reactions to it in the different communities of
Europe. One reaction was found in Germany in the Romantic
idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. In England the reaction was determined by the so-called Industrial Revolution. In
France the background was that of a defeated Revolution^
Revolution that had suffered a double defeat. The undertaking
to establish a society or a state on a rational basis, an enterprise
for which Rousseau's Contrat social furnished a model, broke
down because it was found impossible to build an adequate concrete political structure on the abstract rights of man. It was
defeated in the second sense because the imperialism which
sprang out of this failure got its expression in Napoleon's military genius. This produced a reaction in the whole of Europe
in the form of an attempt to turn the clock back. It is this
double defeat more than anything else, perhaps, that characteratmosphere of France during the last century.
L-^^^.-yln one respect the Revolution had been a success from the
0>r^^6v!\\. of view of the French. It had put the land into the hands
^^ ?^\i^ ^ ^^ peasantry. The land was and remained the great source
of wealth in France. The French peasantry had been fighting to
.
izes the peculiar
get control of
it.
They had been carrying on
And
lawsuits with the
was the peasant who was successful in the cultivation of the land. There was a marked difference between agriculture in France and in England. In England, successful agriculture was carried on by landowners who
feudal owners of the land.
it
[418]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
to break up the
them under the control of a single
man who would put through the improved methods of agriculture which were characteristic of England in the latter part of
farmed large
tracts.
The whole tendency was
small holdings and bring
the eighteenth century. In France, on the other
owners of the land took no interest in the cultivation
were absentee landlords; they sought only the rents,
spent in Paris. Agriculture fell back to the peasant,
hand, the
of it.
They
which they
and he was
eminently successful in his agricultural processes. He had an intense love for the land itself. He wanted to get it for himself.
The whole class of yeomen had disappeared in England, and
there was no passion on the part of the English peasant to get
hold of the land and work it himself. The French peasant had
this passion, a love for agriculture; and when he got the land, he
worked it successfully. The passage of the land into the hands
of the peasantry was one of the most fundamental and important results of the Revolution in France, and it was a result
which could not be overthrown or put aside. In many respects it was possible to return to the old order, but even the
rulers themselves with all their armies could not take the land
away from the peasant. He remained in possession.
This was a result of importance to France in determining the
attitude of the French nation, but it did not show itself in the
reflective processes of the French nation. Those of the French
people
art
and
who were
articulate,
literature, in
ately touched
by
The changes
this
who
could express themselves in
philosophy and science, were not immedichange. It did not affect them.
that took place in England were changes that
put the control of the land into the hands of the large landowners, the men who were the controlling poHtical body. The
landowners were represented in Parliament. They had been in
control of England ever since the Revolution in 1689. This
party, with its control over the land, was the controlling power
in England and gave the cue, in one way or another, to all the
thinking, to
all
the artistic expression, to science and philosoIt was a minority of the
phy, during the eighteenth century.
[419]
THOUGHT
IN
English people, but
it
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
was a minority that was
that regarded itself as having got
its
in control
and
liberty through a marvel-
ous constitution. Its advantages were almost lyrically sung by
Burke. It was the constitution of a monarchy, but of a monarchy which was under the control of Parliament. And this
Parliament represented the nation, but secondarily the landowners, who bore the prestige of the people themselves. Parlia-
ment had
the possibility of developing in the direction of de-
mocracy. Its
possibilities
the franchise in England.
worked out later in the extension of
But at the end of the eighteenth cen-
tury the power was in the hands of the squirearchy
itself,
owned the land and held the power.
Growing up in England, however, was a new class,
which had put itself in opposition to this control of the
which
a class
squire-
archy, the class of industrial entrepreneurs and financiers.
Industrial Revolution that
which, while
it
was going on
in
The
England was one
increased the wealth of the nation and brought
groups of men into prominence and a sort of power, still left the
control in the hands of Parliament and of the men who made
efforts to
buy holdings
in order to
become
a part of the control-
England. So the ideas and ideals of the eighteenth century about the control of the land were maintained
during the years of the nineteenth century. The reconstruction
ling squirearchy of
that was taking place was not deep; but
it
of mill-owners
and manufacturers and
change, such as
it
was, took place at
all.
was through the
class
that
this
financiers
It
was brought about
through the labor movement which began early in the century
and which presented a new social problem to England.
That is the picture that we have of the development which
was taking place in England as over against what was occurring
in France. In France the land itself had passed into the hands
of the peasantry, out of the hands of the nobility. The nobility
were largely deprived of the land they had had in the past.
They became a landless aristocracy. Many of them were provided with estates; but as a class the aristocracy was ousted
from the land, and the peasantry came into possession of it and
t42ol
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
it
was the
mary
first
Land being
source of wealth in France.
the pri-
source of wealth, and being so effectively cultivated by the
peasants, the wealth from
the wealth
it
that went with
The land
increased.
it,
itself,
with
represented the inarticulate
part of French society, a group that had espoused revolution
to get control of the land. It
ideas of Rousseau, but
its
had been swept on by the abstract
interests lay not in political recon-
struction but in rights that the peasants themselves
entering into their
new
holdings.
had got by
The peasants having
attained
that result, their interest in the Revolution largely subsided,
after the excitement of
Thus
Napoleonic imperialism.
the changes that took place during the early part of the
nineteenth century in France were changes that were not motivated by the mass of the French people. They were largely
revolutions in Paris; they took place in Paris and the other large
communities. There was no interest in them that took hold of
the French people as a whole.
selves
on the
soil
and were,
exploitation of their
new
The people had planted them-
for the
time being, satisfied with the
possessions.
This situation did not
lead to any profound reconstruction from the point of view of
the thought of the world, such as that which took place in Ger-
many, in Italy, and in England during the Industrial Revolution. The people themselves had changed the attitude when,
from being feudal tenants, they had become the owners of the
soil, and their attention was turned back to the political movements going on. That is the feeling one has with reference to the
changes that took place in France. They were superficial in
character, for the great number of the people in France were not
interested in them. The thought out of which they developed,
the expressions that were given to the national
sions
which did not reach down
in the great
life,
were expres-
that had taken place in
Germany were more
profound, because the Revolution continued to be
felt in
Ger-
many. The small states the small dynastic states were too
numerous to be reconstituted. Many had to pass over into the
[421]
masses of the French /
people themselves.
The changes
',
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
control of the larger states.
Here
a political change
was going
on which affected the mass of the community in a profound
fashion. Particularly, it brought liberty to the great states in the
German part of Europe. First of all to Austria and then to
Prussia, those two states which became rivals. That movement went on finally to the formation of the German Empire.
It was a movement which was profound because for the first
time it was bringing German nationaHsm to articulate expression. It is that which lies behind Romantic idealism. France
and England and Spain had attained nationalist sentiment
and consciousness two centuries
tion of these states
earlier.
The
divided up into dynastic states.
was dynastic, not
But Germany was
principle of the organizanational.
It
did not turn
about the national heritage of the people. They were of the
race, had the same traditions. But they were subjects of
different dynasties, and it was about these that the organization of the communities gathered. For a time an attempt was
made to turn the clock back through control of Europe by
Metternich, backed by the czar. This control laid emphasis
against all these small dynasties and their communities; but
the map of Europe could not be reconstituted as it was before the Revolution and before Napoleonic pressure in the
Rhine districts. The small dynastic states had been broken
down. Their people had been affected by their contact with
the French. The ferment of the Revolution had been more active there than elsewhere in Europe, People in that part of
Europe continued to feel tendencies toward that national expression which, during the war of liberation, found its most
effective expression through the Prussian state. It was a Prussian state which was a means of bringing to successful conscious-
same
ness a sense of nationalism.
The
great exponent of nationalism at that period was Fichte
in his addresses to the
German
people.
These were not
Prussians as such; they were addressed to the
Fichte undertook to bring to the
German
German
to the
people.
people the awareness
that their peculiar nature was a part of their peculiar heritage.
[422]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
He
pointed out what their task in the civilization of a feudal
world was and was to be. It was the efficiency of the Prussian
administration that gave a certain popular character to this up-
throw the French out of
Germany. The Prussian state could take over the institutions
and developments as though they were the expression of the
German nation, though they were not such politically. Prussia
could give instruction, and the army could be made a national
institution. The schools and the army were the two institutions
by means of which the Prussian people and the Germans in general, so far as they were affected by what was going on in Germany as a whole, got control of governmental authority. This
lift
which took place
in the struggle to
authority was in direct control. It was in control in so far as
it
fostered the spread of intelligence, the development of public
and the undertaking to make the intelligence of the
community in some sense the director of the life of the state itschools,
self.
Frederick the Great undertook to develop a state which
was eminently
intelligent.
But a new end was brought
into the
army which
should take in all those that were capable of bearing arms. As
was the case with the school, the whole of the youth of Germany
life
of the people with the institution of a national
which they would be trained
it was an
autocratic state, although all the power belonged to the monarch, as such, was a state which was undertaking to train its
should be brought into the army,
for their national
life.
in
Prussia, therefore, although
citizenry not for fighting alone but for intelligent political
life.
")
During the period of the war of nationalization there was an
intense national life which spread from Prussia throughout
Germany. That was the spirit which got its expression in the
Romantic philosophy. Thus, while this philosophy was a system of great profundity, while it lay beyond the comprehension
of the masses of the people, it was also an expression of the
spiritual life that came up from the people themselves.
On the other hand, in England we have a development in
which the national movement was brought into the life of the
community, of the masses, not through those that owned the
[423]
\
/
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
land but by the urban laborers, the factory laborers.
They had
been brought together in organizations, in trade-unions, that
gave a sense of understanding which the masses of the people
had never had before in England. The labor movement reached
all the way down into English society. It was a movement which
got
its
expression in industrial
got
its
expression in Parliament.
strife,
As
and that industrial
strife
a result, the development
of English democracy throughout the nineteenth century had
been what
it
movement
so evidently
utilitarians,
Bentham and
was capable of
place
is
today, a national movement. That
also got its expression in a philosophy, that of the
among
the Mills. It was a philosophy which
a simple statement;
it
was one that could
find its
the trade-unions themselves, one that could get
its
movement toward free trade, in the demand
for cheap bread, and the demand for internationalism by way
of free trade. It was a movement that was connected with the
poHtical and philosophical thought of the community itself,
expression in the
reaching out beyond England to other communities.
with those two countries
England and
French community. The result of the political revolution was of profound importance for
the French people. France, like Germany, was affected in some
degree by the Industrial Revolution. But France was not as
It is in contrast
that
Germany
much
ist
affected as
want
to put the
Germany. In Germany there arose the
theory which took hold of the masses of the people, for in
Germany
the factory system worked itself out earlier and gave
the background for the development of the
ButillFrance the wealth lay in the
i
/
I
social-
soil.
Marxian
doctrine.
The manufacturing
in
France was of luxuries. The products did not get into the wholesale markets. In England the peasants had been loosened from
the soil. They were free to go to the city. When England began the development of coal and iron, she had a supply of labor
that was glad to work at starvation wages. In France the
peasantry were satisfied to remain on the soil. There was little
of the large production which was essential for the development
of the national labor movement as such. This movement got its
[424]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
expression in trade-unionism in England and in socialism in
Germany. Both were popular movements; both got into politics. But the labor of the French peasant was not affected by
the political situation. It was only in so far as taxation bore on
him that he was interested in the political situation as such. J
('
(As
was
have
said, the
attempt during the nineteenth century
to put the clock back. In France
men
returned to the
spiritual order of the church, the Catholic church. Nationalism,
so far as
it
expressed
itself,
was
a chronological expression.
France went back to the medieval situation, not exactly as the
Germans went back to it or as the English went back to it, in a
romantic attitude, but to find an expression of the society of
France itself. The Revolution had been a failure politically.
From the point of view of its transfer of the land to the peasant
It
it had been a success, but politically it had been a failure.
on
rational
lines
that
had
been
the
failed to_reoranize society
its goal. The rehgion of reason, which went with the French
Revolution, had a life of only a few duties, and, when the latter
failed, men drifted back to the church, which again became the
center of the life of the community as such when men turned
back in a romantic fashion to the medieval period, but with the
sophisticated attitude that belongs to the beginning of the
nineteenth century. They went back to rediscover in the medieval period something which they felt they had lost, something
which was different from the experience of those who lived during the medieval centuries. That life had been a direct life. The
attitude of the romanticist when he returned to it was one of
appreciation and enjoyment. It was an aesthetic reaction. All
the paraphernalia of the religious service was looked at from
the point of view of men who had been estranged from it and
returned to
it,
and who undertook
attitude that they had gained.
people in the medieval period.
to appreciate
it
with the new
They were playing
the roles of
Another phase of the Revolution in France must be kept in
mind. France exhausted itself emotionally in the Napoleonic
period. The enthusiasm in the French armies had arisen out of
[425]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the sentiment of defense against the outsider. Here you have the
peasants with the same sentiment as that found later in the
Russian peasants, who, without interest in the government as
such, were determined to hold on to the land which they had
secured. They were ready to fight battles against invaders
and protect themselves. They proved themselves the most effective infantry in Europe, and they had a great general. Out
of this arose Napoleonism in France. It became identified with
Napoleon himself. He was not a dynast; he did not represent
the history of France.
The justification
for his position
was that
he made possible a larger community that otherwise would not
have existed. He brought together people separated socially,
geographically, but who still recognized themselves as belonging
to the same community because they were subjects of the same
monarch. The dynast, the emperor, had been the center of the
medieval period. He was the
symbol of Europe as a single society. While having slight politi
cal power, he stood as an impressive symbol of a larger community^
a community that was surpassed only by the church, one
which might take in the whole human race, which was organized
about the church. The dynast in the position of the emperor
was the political symbol of that larger community.
We must go back to France or England in the feudal period to
realize what the monarchy meant. Means of communication
were slight, customs were different, different dialects were
spoken. There was no organization, no France, no England as a
whole; but through the monarch it was possible for the feudal
tenant, the serf, to recognize himself as having a relation to
everyone else inside the national bounds. Running up the line to
the monarch was a community made up of parts, of different elements, that were hostile to each other. Thus, only the monarchy
made possible national life in Napoleon's opposition to the feudal
order. In France the Bourbons, and in England the Plantagenets, were able to root out the feudal order and make a national life possible. We must remember this in order to recognize the importance of the dynasty Napoleon wanted to step
social organization during the
[426]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
This would have identified France with himself. But he
it, for his hold on the people was not a historic
hold. He represented a revolution; he had overthrown the old
state and broken down the principle of authority; and when he
into.
could not do
undertook to place himself on the historic throne of France and
make
himself the representative of the line of the oldest dynastic
family in Europe and to
make
symbol of national
He
his peace with the people which
Europe,
he failed. All the emotional
had the longest tradition in
life that he was able to arouse had been spent in the glory which
victory produced, in a sense of enlargement that came with the
enlarged empire. It was impossible that this should remain.
The country broke away; and when France came back to its
own boundaries. Napoleon was a stranger. He could not be the
life.
undertook
to carry over the
He showed
ciency of the Prussian state.
to his military genius in the reorganization of the state
basis of an autocracy
The
which undertook
effi-
a genius comparable
on the
to control everything.
There was the same
was of the soldier in the army.
was organized with great efficiency, and Na-
schools were turned into barracks.
training of the child that there
The whole
state
poleon was the center of
it all.
He
undertook to pass over into
the field of the arts, to get an expression for the principle of his
state in the field of philosophy, to direct the
He
of the commumen and women.
life
gathered about himself literary
nity
itself.
The
philosophers, he thought, could be utilized in the organiza-
tion of
France as the monarchy of Napoleon. But
in all this
he
failed.
The one hold he had on the community was that of his military genius and success. The Revolution had done its work. It
had overturned the earlier state, and Napoleon could not set up
that state again arbitrarily. The emotion of the French people
was exhausted. They had been on a long military debauch.
Their operations
in the field, the glory of their victories, the
plunder they had brought back from Europe, were the signs of
that debauch, and they were exhausted. The one pre-eminent
change which had taken place besides the breakdown of Na-/
[427]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
poleon's hold was the passage of the land into the hands of the
peasant, and the peasant was now indifferent to what went on.
The masses of the people were outside of the life that went on
among the intellectuals. There was no connection between the
thought of the time and the mass of the
French peasantry. Napoleon had almost decimated France by
filling his army with those who could bear arms; he had materially weakened her physically; he had decreased the population
literary, philosophical
who were left rethat when the Bourbons
of France by his continual warfare. But those
mained on the soil and were satisfied, so
were put on the throne and undertook to turn the clock back
they found that France was exhausted and the mass of the citizens were indifferent to what went on. Thus, while there was a
rich life in Germany and nationalism expressed itself in vivid
ways a national literature sprang up there and science flourin France there was the deadness
ished in a remarkable degree
of the morning after. There was the interest of the people in the
soil itself. They were looking down and not up. They were satisfied with what they had and were not looking ahead. They did
not wish to carry on the life of the old Napoleonic state. I think
it is
necessary to appreciate this situation in order that
we may
comparative poverty of spiritual development in
France as compared with that which took place in Germany and
in England.
realize the
II
The enthusiasm
of the Romantic period, as
it
turned back to
Germany.
army which was
the medieval period, was expressed in England and in
In France what occurred was the return of an
melancholy and defeated. The great expression of the romantic
movement in France was religious. In this connection there are
two or three figures of importance for the time. De Bonald and
De Maistre represented a return to the philosophy of the people
an attempt
to restate the
medieval philosophy, that which be-
longed to the period of the twelfth and thirteenth century.
They
restated
it
from the standpoint of France
[428]
in the nine-
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
teenth century.
They were both men
of imagination,
men
of
very great intellectual power and of supreme devotion. They
took the fact of the religious organization of the community
most seriously. What they undertook to show was that no community could exist except through religion; that the only bond
that could hold men together was the church; that the church
was the presupposition of society. They found themselves not
in touch with the historical development of the church in
France itself however. The Gallican movement in France,
which answered to the Reformation, left the monarch in power
within a national church. That movement was, of course, entirely outside of the conception of life represented by De Bonald
and De Maistre. They fell back onto the conception of the
Holy Roman Empire as representing the single community of
Christendom. In its time it was the oldest possible organization
of Christendom as such. Europe had been broken into feudal
states which were more or less hostile toward each other. Only
from the point of view of the church could all the tenants, the
the underlings, conceive of themselves as belonging to a
serfs,
community. There was, in the medieval period, the presupposition that society must have a religious basis. Only the
church could make Christendom possible. However, the further
the development of this organization went, the more it tended
toward the national church, and rulers undertook to get control
single
of
it
within their
own boundary. So
far as the
church repre-
sented the spiritual organization of the community, the state
insisted on having its hands on it. So Louis XIV and Henry
VIII were acting logically when they undertook to set up national churches inside the Catholic church. That was possible in
France; in England it was not possible, and a complete separation took place. The return of De Bonald and De Maistre to the
Catholic tradition, their attempt to revive the conception of
the thirteenth century, was an inevitable failure. They influenced religious schools and convinced those who did not need to
be convinced, but the mass of the people was not touched by
them.
[
429
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Chateaubriand came forward with a work which was superas compared with the arguments of De Bonald and De
Maistre. He presented Christianity as a civiUzing power, a humanizing power; he appealed to the aesthetic phase of Christianity and called out the aesthetic response in the process of
worship itself; his was essentially a sentimental reaction. For
the time being, however, it had very considerable influence in
Paris among the intellectuals. It was distinctly a romantic movement, but not one which had its roots in the past life of the
community. Chateaubriand failed to connect with De Bonald
and De Maistre. The latter were undertaking to bring back
the church of the thirteenth century; the former, to bring men
into the church of the nineteenth century, a church which was
Galilean, national, and opportunistic in its relations to Napoleon; a church which had lost the philosophy of its earlier
life; a church which did not have the consciousness of being the
organizing principle in the whole of Europe. That proud consciousness did belong to the people, and its hierarchy could be
aroused again in the nineteenth century. But the only approach
Chateaubriand could make to the church was on the sentimental side. De Bonald and De Maistre represented an interest in
the development of the church itself. Their doctrine was planted in the dogma of the church; Chateaubriand appealed to the
ficial
ritual.
Ill
The philosophy
of the French Revolution was represented in
the pre-revolutionary days by Voltaire and Rousseau.
The
group of men who gathered about them were called Encyclopedists, after the
ment
who represented the EnlightenThe philosophy which lay back of them was
Encyclopedists
in France.
imported from England. Voltaire had carried over from England the philosophy of Locke and put it on French soil. In this
period those who were found within this school were called
"idealogues." They stood for the ultimacy of a state of consciousness, an impression, a sensation.
[430]
What Locke undertook
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
to
do was
to find
to analyze experience into simple elements,
how our
and then
experience, especially our collective experience,
arose.
It is interesting to see that it
was the philosophy of Locke
that was carried over to France rather than that of Berkeley
and that of Hume, both of whom represented developments of
the Lockian philosophy. But the transplantation of this English philosophy by Voltaire and others was taken from Locke.
To see this is to see that the hold French thought got of this
phijosopliy .was superficial. The development that went on
from Locke through Berkeley and Hume was an essential, logical development. The contradictions which were involved in
the Lockian statement came out in the subjective idealism of
Berkeley and in the criticism of Hume. For Locke, all our
knowledge falls into sensations and impressions those of the
outer sense, and those of the inner sense. The outer appears to
those of color, sound, taste,
us in our sensations and contacts
and odor. The inner impressions are those that come from our
processes of thought, from our emotional
desire
and of
will.
From Locke's
life,
from the action of
standpoint, the
mind
is
mo-
His interest was to take our ideas, or
presuppositions of thought, and break them up into ultimate
elements, and then to show the connections that lie between
saic of these impressions.
these ultimate elements.
philosopher
who
is
The
first
orientation
was that of a
fighting the doctrine of innate ideas, a sort of
neo-Platonism of the time, one which was used by the
church and by political philosophers. This philosophy lost the
profundity of the Platonism from which it sprang. It located the
idea, as such, in the mind and presented the mind as a tablet on
which were written certain fundamental ideas. Locke's ideas
were oriented by his opposition to the doctrine of innate ideas.
His position was that there was nothing in the mind that had
not previously been in the senses. Everything was reduced to
superficial
sensations, to impressions.
The memory had impressions
of the
outer sense and also the inner sense.
'Ideology and the philosophy which
'^'
[431]
it
presented in France
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
were brought over from England through the translation of the
works of Locke, without the recognition of the development
which had taken place as represented by Berkeley and Hume.
The emphasis lay upon analysis, so-called. The interest behind
this was the elimination of the abstract idea. You remember,
in
one sense, these three were
all
nominalists.
They assumed
that the abstract idea, the universal, had no further existence
than was found
in the association of certain
symbols with
differ-
The problem involved in the similarity
Eetween particular things was passed over. They insisted that
in the process of thinking the mind was dealing with particulars
ent individual things.
and with the association of these particulars with each other.
The interest in the problem which the French of this period had was in getting rid of the abstractions about which
religious, ecclesiastical, and governmental theories gathered.
there such a thing as absolute divine right.^ Were there
such things as transubstantiation, ideas of which could only be
presented in terms of particular objects.^ The theology, the
political science, of the period dealt with speculations from
these particular objects. Did these abstractions have a unity
Was
one have to come back to particular experiwelcomed a philosophy which analyzed
The
Idealogues
ence?
experience into ultimate elements of sensation, which came back
in themselves, or did
simply to particular experiences as such and advanced the abstractions which were built into the theories and political doctrines of the time. The ideological philosophy was regarded,
then, as the philosophy of the Revolution. It was used by
Voltaire in his attacks on the church;
who were
by Rousseau, and those
was
As they conceived of it,
influenced by Rousseau, in showing that the state
actually an organization of individuals.
the state existed only in the contract between individuals. There
was no such thing
as the unity of the state as such.
the individuals that
made up
existed between these individuals.
the problem, especially as
stitution.
From
it
There were
the state and the relationship that
You
see
how
this simplified
involved an attack on the whole in-
the standpoint of the medieval period there
[432]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
were universals. These universals existed in the mind of God; on
earth, in our own minds. About these universals the whole doctrine of the church and state was gathered. If one could attack
those universals and substitute for them individuals and their
experience and the relations that existed between them, one
could exorcise those abstract units and come back to what
seemed the immediate situation, that is, to men and women associated in various ways. The universals were to be found in
the images of these men, in their particular relations. These were
to be brought into the mind. Institutional organizations were
to be analyzed into the physical relationships of people.
The
problem of empirical philosophy as it appeared in England and
in France was, then, essentially this.
That this philosophy did not bring about political revolution
in England, as in France, was due to the difference in the political situation. In a certain sense, that revolution had been going
on in England ever since the Puritan Revolution. The people
were conscious of a change taking place. There had been the
institution of Parliament, with its representation in the coun-
However inadequate that might be for the absolute
ties.
power of the crown, the crown was no longer necessary for
holding together an English community. Parliament with its
powers accomplished what the crown had accomplished. The
revolution was taking place. Furthermore, England was, after
all, a Protestant community. There was a state church; there
were also dissenting bodies; and a large proportion of the population of England was found in these dissenting churches. They
were free to carry out their own process of worship. There
was no organization or group of people in an ecclesiastical organization that undertook to determine what their ideas of the
world should
theology.
be.
They
The people were
free to formulate their
own
were, of course, subject to various political dis-
they could carry on their own religious life.
been
fought through; and they were left, in that
battle had
sense, free. The revolution had, in its essentials, taken place in
abilities,
but
still
That
England.
[433]
THOUGHT
The French
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
thinkers were satisfied with the application of this
empiricism. This does not mean that the French mind was less
profound in itself. You have only to turn back to the period of
the Renaissance to realize how profound a philosophical power
the French mind has. This attitude indicates that the interest
of the French mind was turned toward the revolution, a revolution which, as I have said, had in its essentials already happened
in England. The problem, then, was a different problem. The
philosophy was one which could be used by individuals, by the
revolutionists, for the disintegration of the institutions which
they were trying to pull down. It could be used for the theory
of the reconstruction of the institutions that they proposed to
put in their place. Philosophy existed in their minds for that
purpose; and when they had mastered the idea enough to be able
to use it in this analysis, they had no further interest in it. Their
interest lay in the revolution they were undertaking; it did not
lie immediately in philosophy itself.
IV
After the revolution,
when
the restoration took place, there
appeared philosophies of the church, reconstructions of the doc-
on the previous ideas of the church
These were formulated by De Bonald and De Maistre,
as we have already mentioned; and they were consistent and
very able doctrines. They turned on the empirical philosophy
of the time and insisted that it was skeptical, that it made
knowledge impossible, that it reduced man to a simple congeries
of separate sensations. It was known as "sensualism" instead of
the philosophy of sensation. Man was reduced to the sensations
out of which he was built up, and nature was reduced to the set
trine of the institution built
and
state.
of experiences that people had.
For a time, ideology remained the philosophy as far as philosophy existed in France. It had sunk to a very low ebb. It
almost disappeared from the universities. But where it was
taught, it was taught in terms of ideology. There were, however, those that were interested in carrying this philosophy
[434]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
through to certain skeptical results like those of Hume. But even
they were rather interested in the psychological problem and
wanted a psychological analysis revealed. Cabanis and De_^
Tracy pointed out that there were elements in experience of
which Hume took no account, elements which did not appear
in the analysis of substance and of cause. This content was the
content of activity. If the analysis had been carried through
to that point, it would have gone on to criticize Hume's skepticism as reducing experience to a set of instantaneous presents.
These men made their statement in terms of factors present
in activity itself and in an analysis of conception as involving
something besides passivity. They recognized that in perception
we
are passive so far as the qualities of sensation are
But, they said, our knowledge of these involves
an act, and this act is something more than mere association.
in that respect they were taking a step in advance. They were
concerned.
advancing toward the psychology of education as distinct from
the psychology of association. In one sense they were advancing
ahead of their time. In England it is not until after the period,
or during the later period, of John Stuart Mill that the theory
of education
The
is
recognized.
interest in this type of analysis in
ferent forms.
The
France took quite
dif-
sensationalism of Condillac was the philoso-
phy of the Revolution. It was an attempt to get back to ultimate elements so that they might be reconstructed. His interest
was in the analysis of the governing ideas in the French community. What was wished was to get back to more primitive, immediate elements so that a plan of reconstruction could be set
up. The reconstruction of the Revolution was a failure, of
The
was successwhich one must keep in
mind in comparing these philosophies. The result, from the philosophical standpoint, was that the position of Condillac seems
superficial. He was not interested in such problems as Hume
was interested in. He was interested in the immediate application that could be made of this analysis in testing and overcourse.
ful.
analytic discussion of the older ideas
It is this difference in attitude
[435]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
throwing the structure of church and state. After the revolution, with its failure, came the restoration and the philosophy of
the reaction. That philosophy was expressed by men who did
not simply accept ideas but who undertook to formulate them
with their implications. It had, however, a definite political and
practical social interest at that time, just as the philosophy of
Condillac had had a political and social interest. The later philosophy was naturally the direct opposite of the revolution. It
denied the rights of man there were no such things as rights
which inhere in the individual;
istence of the individual;
it
it
denied the independent ex-
went back
to a society
which was
organized for the church on the authoritarian basis. It was quite
powerfully presented. It represented, however, the philosophy
of reaction; and, beyond
its
rather successful attack on the
it had no political effect in French
was succeeded by a new movement whose chief
was Guyau, with a connecting link in Royer-Collard.
philosophy of sensationalism,
thought.
figure
It
V
Royer-Collard was a lawyer by profession. He became a
What he brought to French thought
philosopher late in Hfe.
was the attitude of the Scottish common-sense school, the
school of reason. This school was that of the individualists, and
was the dominant philosophy in American colleges fifty years
ago. As indicated by the term "common sense," it appealed to
the common judgment of the community as carrying with it a
conclusion which should be accepted, and accepted as final, as
that which is always true. Of course, there must be some sort of
philosophical background in so abstract a statement as this; and
this was found in what was a different statement of the process
of knowledge itself. The doctrine of knowledge as it appeared in
the empirical school
and
is
found
in the relationship
ideas. In the first place, the empiricists
of impressions
would say that hav-
ing an idea or impression and knowing an idea or impression are
the
same
it.
It carries its
thing. It
is
there in consciousness; that
own
existence with
[436]
it.
is all
there
The impressions
is
to
are
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
connected with
memory
images.
By
the process of association
they are connected with other impressions that occur at the
same time. If one sees an object with which he is famihar, there
arise other impressions with which he is famihar and which are
Hke
it;
there arise impressions of other things that have been as-
sociated with
it
in
space and time
in the past.
When
one ob-
serves a place, certain memories of persons he has seen there ap-
This relation of ideas and impressions to others comes to
take the place of knowledge, or what we mean by knowledge.
pear.
Knowledge
is
reduced to the relations of the impressions and
lie in the mind.
ideas to each other as they
was assumed by the rationalists that we have, besides that
knowledge of things which is present in the mind, knowledge of
things to which this refers. Beyond our immediate experience
there are things that appear in that experience. For example,
there was the assumption that we know there is such a thing as
It
"matter." Our experience of matter
is only in our sensations.
mind. But there is back of these sensations some
substance that we call "matter." We experience our own experiences. W^e have memory of our own experiences. But we are
supposed to know that back of these states of consciousness lies
a mind, a conscious mind, a substantial spiritual something in
which these experiences inhere. And we are supposed to know
They
lie
in the
that there are causal relations, as well as substantial relations, in
We
have a set of ideas such as those of unity, multiplicity; we have all the logical concepts as such; and we are
supposed to know that they unify our knowledge. And from
these ideas and concepts we deduce results that follow or not bethe world.
That is, it was assumed that we have a knowledge of what lies beyond the impressions. What the empirical school did was to carry back, step by
step, all this inference of something beyond experience to the
simple relationship of impressions and ideas that lie inside of
cause of the nature of the laws indicated.
experience.
The most
to
striking result of this analysis
show that the causal
relation of things
[437I
was Hume's attempt
was nothing but the
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
a succession of impressions one
mind
past we
pictures that arise in our
find one event following another
been repeated, then we expect that it will happen
again. That is all there is to the law of causality. It does not
show that every cause must have a certain effect, every effect
a cause; that there must be like causes for like effects; that
there must be an adequate cause for every effect. We do not
know this as a law of the universe. What we find is this fixed expectation an expectation that comes so frequently, so unconsciously, that we are not aware of it. When the sun rises, there
after another. If in the
and
this has
will
be day; when
it sets,
there will be night.
If
we
follow the
course of these events, there will be only certain anticipated results.
You
can see the result of
all this
was
to resolve
knowledge
mere relation of impressions and ideas to each
other, remembering that I am using the term "idea" in Hume's
sense as merely the copy of the impression. Every image must,
of course, be of the same character as the impression itself.
The change that is involved in the position of Reid and the
Scottish school is to bring back knowledge as the immediate relationship between the mind and an object. Reid recognizes
what has been called the "inner sense." According to Reid, we
can have knowledge of something that is not given in the state
as such into the
of consciousness
itself.
The
intuitional character of the Scottish
With experience we have an
immediate knowledge of something that is not given in the
state of consciousness, in the mind, at the time. In this sense
the school seems to hark back to Locke's position. What the intuitional school said was that we have an immediate intuition
of the table as extended and as solid; that this knowledge as
such is an immediate relationship between the mind and the object. There is no association of common impressions and ideas
with other impressions and ideas. There is a cognition of someschool of philosophy
thing that
is
lies in this:
not in a given state of consciousness.
If the
Scottish school were asked to explain this, they would say you
cannot go behind it. We just know. Ask them to explain seeing, or vision, or color, or
sound, or taste, or odor.
[
438
They
are
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
there;
we know them. That
is
a position that you cannot over-
throw. But this school had to recognize that matter does not
have the characters which appear in our vision, in our hearing,
in our taste, in our sense of temperature. That which answers to
color is motion; that which answers to odor is change; what answers to sound are vibrations of the air. Now these physical
characters are not what appear in experience. Color, sound,
taste, and odor are not motion; they are not chemical structure.
So, the Scottish school had to answer the assumption that these
lie in the mind and are appHed to physical things that we immediately know. In these experiences we are subject to all sorts of
possible errors. The extended matter is there; sound, color,
taste, depend on surroundings. Put it in one surrounding, and
matter has color; in another, it has not. There are possibilities,
then, of error; and the Scottish thinkers had no way of accounting for them.
Royer-Collard carried over into French philosophy the doctrine of common sense, but he gave a somewhat different interpretation to
is
it.
He
dealt with
common
uniformity in everyone's judgment.
sense in so far as there
This recalls Kant's
as-
sumption or implication that minds have universal character.
It is not simply that they have common forms but that there
is some general consciousness of which all the different minds are
different expressions. This is an implication of a good deal of the
Kantian doctrine, although Kant himself did not carry it out.
He avoided these implications so far as he could. Something of
this sort becomes evident in the statement which Royer-Collard
made of the common-sense school. He comes back to the statement, to the assumption, that we have immediate knowledge of
that which is outside of ourselves and that that knowledge is
simply given; it is there. We can verify what is immediately
given by common sense that in which everybody else agrees.
This French transportation of the doctrine of common sense
across the channel carried with it an assumption of a common
consciousness in which different minds agree, from which, in
some sense, different minds arise. Thecharacteristics which be-
[439]
THOUGHT
long to this
IN
common
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
experience are given, in a certain sense, in
advance of that which takes place in the separate experience.
Thus we have a statement in France of the Kantian transcen-
the
dentalism^
mind. That
logical
priority of certain
characters of the
one striking difference between the doctrine of
the Scottish school of Reid and his followers as it appeared in
the British Isles and the doctrine as introduced in France.
There is another character also that belonged to this philosophy and which became emphasized later. That is the element of activity, especially in our normative states. This
arises in some sense out of a criticism of the empirical school.
As we have seen, for the empiricists having an idea and knowing
is
it or having an impression and knowing it are the same thing.
There is no difference. So far as our impressions are concerned,
what they insisted on was that we are passive. You open a door
to enter a room. If you have never been there before, you do
not know what you are going to see, what the furniture will be,
what the decorations will be. Furthermore, you have no initiative in the matter. You open the door, there is a light in the
room, and you see what is in it; but you are quite passive in
that experience. The experience which will come to you is something of which you will be aware, but you will have done nothing
about it. Having sensation and knowing are the sarne^dijng
from the point of view of the empirical school.
What the French school insisted on with growing emphasis
was the distinction between cognition and perception. They
admitted that, as far as the sensations are concerned, we are
quite passive. No one can, by willing, have a sensation of a certain type any more than he can add a cubit to his stature. If
the object is there and the eyes open, one will have a sensation;
one is passive in regard to it. The act of cognition, on the
knowing. If
other hand,
is
this table is
not simply the presence in
pressions but
knowledge
is
not passive. It
is
is
my
a knowledge that the table
the result of an active process.
report of a set of sensations.
What
[440]
that
my
relationship to
mind of
is
It is
means
a set of im-
there, then that
is
not a simple
that the mere
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
having of a
from knowing the
set of perceptions is different
ta-
In the latter the analysis must be carried on farther if one
to say that the case is correct. Getting a glimpse of a face, one
ble.
is
someone
else
When
he meets the person he finds it is
he has never met. He has made a mistake.
sees an acquaintance.
whom
Our perceptual
process and conceptional processes are passive
in regard to the
elements over which we have no control. But
If we are taking certain
we
are continually building things up.
experiences from the past,
we have
at the time relatively few
We
are experiencing what the
meant and what they imply for the future. We
start off with an image, a sensation; and we expect something.
We bind the whole thing in our perception. We set up the ob-
impressions that are immediate.
last impressions
jects
we
look for next.
There were, then, these two elements
French school;
immediate knowl-
in this
the taking-over of the Scottish school with
its
edge of something, the acceptance of common sense,
tain sense, the criterion of that
in the
is
as, in a cer-
which we are sure we know; and,
second place, the emphasis on the presence of activity. It
these factors that distinguish the sensationalists of the period
and represent the difference between them and the Ideologues
on the one hand and the eclecticism of Cousin on the other.
VI
One
point
want
to impress
on you
is
that
all
French phi-
losophy of the period had a pohtical bias. It is only natural that
that should be the case. France had been overthrown by political speculation in a certain sense. The French Revolution was
Rousseau, Volcalled the revolution of the philosophers
taire.
They were
the philosophers of revolution.
When
the
Revolution had been carried out, the reaction came, and with it
a philosophy that undertook to put back the old world. Then
there grew up a liberal school that tried to establish something
on the political side like that already achieved in England. In
England you find a philosophical detachment. The constitution
seemjtxi-reflect_a permanent political order. T here were r elative
[441
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
freedom and development. People were at liberty to speculate
without asking for the political implications of their speculations, but that was not the situation in France.
I want to call your attention again to the fact that the stream
of French life was flowing not through Paris but through the ex-
They
perience of the peasants.
represented the mass of the
French people, and through the revolution they had got the soil
and were occupied in the cultivation of it with a passion that belonged to the life of the French peasants. In this they are different from the English peasants. They were satisfied. They were
not interested in what was going on in Paris. Thus, much of the
thought of the period was superficial, as far as the consciousness
of the French as a whole is concerned. This is characteristic of
the whole period in France. The changes taking place in England went all the way through; and although there the expressions are the expressions of the upper class, they were felt by
the whole country. A minority was in control, but their control
aflfected the life of the whole group. They carried the community with them, and they had a sense of the racial life that they
were directing. The profoundest experience in the French public
lay below the surface; and what took place on the surface, while
it was picturesque and had back of it men of talent and ability,
did not represent the deeper currents. It has been only very
slowly that the French people have passed over into political
life, passed over by means of institutions which were brought
in from the outside, which were not their own.
The movement from this earlier position to which I have just
referred took place by way of Royer-Collard. He made a common consciousness, rather than a common assent, the characterIt was a movement, as I
istic of the process of knowledge.
pointed out, that lies within the Kantian movement. It goes
back to something that is transcendent. It. impHes a common
character which belongs
something
to
all
consciousness, to
all
intelli-
advance of cognitive experiences themselves. This was not worked out in any
gence
which
is
logically there in
such metaphysical theory as
it
finally received in the
[442]
German
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
and what Royer-Collard
something that is common in the
attitude of everyone, something that is common in conscious-
idealists,
but
it is
definitely implied;
came back
to in his lectures
ness
It
itself.
The
was
a test of
is
what
is
true.
other feature of his philosophy to which
I have referred
and which was emphasized by other writers was that of activity, and here he was in advance of the English movement. His
emphasis was placed upon the ego, upon the self. For him ego
has substance, which is soul. If you deal with it in terms of substance, it is that in which states of consciousness exist. But the
soul is more especially that which organizes experience or that
which is a statement of a process of organization. The soul, you
may say, is an ego; but it is a substantial ego in which inhere
the different states of consciousness whose faculties express
themselves in the conduct of the individual. But the soul lies
back of the states of consciousness as a substance which is unknowable and as a function whose faculties express the soul
lying behind the idea.
The
act of volition takes place; the
what he does; but the process of
is
responsible for
is
the
is
the ego of the older metaphysics, especially with
self.
The
self
cal implications.
has wanted; has
felt;
man
volition itself
has been affected. That
its
teleologi-
This principle of the activity of the soul comes
is going on,
into the process of consciousness as something that
not as something that
entity that
lies
is simply an expression of a substantial
back behind the sensation. It is something that
is^oing on.
Here Royer-Collard simply gives an emphasis to a phase of
work out his doctrine. We have only a
report on his so-called "second year" in philosophy, and his influence was one that came to those who listened to his lectures
rather than those who read his book. But he makes a connecting link between the philosophy of the revolution, which was destructive in character, and the latter thought. The point at
which he may be said definitely to depart in his emphasis, at
least from the philosophy which he had taken over, was in this
conception of a common consciousness and common will, and
experience; he does not
[443]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
not in the concept of an activity going on in experience
which, therefore,
is
itself
not stated in terms of associations which are
already there, and which
is
not to be stated in terms of a sub-
For the psychology of association the process as such
has already taken place; the association is simply an inference
of organization which is already there. You bring up things by
association. You are allowing a relationship which is already in
existence to apply itself. You have met a person at a certain
place; you pass the place, and the memory of the previous event
comes back to you. You are allowing the structure which is already there simply to express itself. It is not a process; it is not
an activity in itself. The psychology of Royer-CoUard, as it expressed itself later, comes back to what is going on. It is the
impulse that is taking place expressing itself. That is found in
stance.
attention as such. It creates relationships, sets
or, in finding relations, organizes
them.
up
relationships,
It is active in a
manner
which activity cannot be found in the associational statement.
But it is this activity which is emphasized at this period.
It is the activity which gathers about the ego, the self, as it
represents an interest in the study of the self in its psychological
experiences^, which has been characteristic of French thought
from that time on. We find also, an interest in memoirs, an
interest of the sort which gets expression in Montaigne; but that
is a characteristic of the French of an earlier period. They, too,
were looking for an activity which goes on in the inner life of
the individual. They make use of introspection, but as a different process from that used by John Stuart Mill. The difference
has to do with emphasis again, with the sort of problem for
which introspection is used. Introspection is still used by the
in
English school in the interest of the solution of the epistemological
problem.
perception.
life
The
It
comes back to an analysis of sensation and
French school comes back to the
interest in the
of the individual himself, at this period to the salvation, the
glorification, the affirmation, of himself.
It
record of the experience of philosophy as
past.
That
interest in history
is
it
took account of the
goes back into the
also characteristic of the
[444]
Ro-
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
mantic movement. Introspection as we connect it with this
earlier psychology is a distinct affair. It has to do with experimentation that starts off with extreme abstractions and quaHtatively susceptible differences. It is a different affair from the
introspection of the English thinkers and writers of this period.
Those who were working under the general idea of introspection
were endeavoring to get back to their own selves, to find out
what they were, and to try to evaluate themselves. It represents
a process of evaluation of spiritual experiences rather than the
process of locating certain cognitive experiences.
VII
Every philosophy and every philosopher appearing
during this period has a political status. This
ure Cousin,
He had a career in which
there
is
was
in
France
notable in the
difficulty.
fig-
He ex-
monarchy of Louis Philippe and the
who were seeking security and
still were attempting to hold on to that which was valuable
from the standpoint of the Revolution. They did not break with
the Revolution, as the reactionary school had. They insisted
that what it undertook to achieve liberty was essential to
the life of the individual, to the life of the soul. But it was a
liberty which had to be stated in terms of conditions under
which it could be expressed. It was a school which was endeavoring to gather together what was valuable in the thought
of the period that had gone before it and also another French
school that was moving outside of its own border to get what
was valuable in the thought of other nations. It took over not
pressed the attitude of the
school of the bourgeoisie, of those
only the empiricism which the philosophy of the revolution
had brought
from the English empirical school but also
the interpretation of the Scottish school's doctrine to which
I have referred.
Then Cousin went farther afield into Ger-
many and
in
studied the
new Continental
philosophical doc-
and undertook to get the outline of the
philosophy of Kant and also to realize what was going on in the
German Romantic school. This school set up what, in the sense
trine that
was
arising,
[445]
THOUGHT
that
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
may
have already indicated, you
call a
"transcendental-
ism." This was presented in the philosophy of Royer-Collard.
There
is
a certain structure of things belonging to a
consciousness which
It
is
is
something given
a presupposition of the act of
in
advance
the character of the object
itself.
common
knowledge.
mind
that determines
The French
thinkers did not
in the
take this doctrine in the skeptical sense in which
it is presented
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. It was taken as the test of
that which could be verified; in the sense in which it was pre-
in
sented in the Scottish school
The
figures in
Germany
what
is
common
is
true.
that most attracted Cousin and other
and Hegel. It is interesting to
Romantic philosophers. In
England a class movement fastened on Fichte, rather than
Schelling, although Schelling had a reverberation in Coleridge.
Carlyle responded to Kant and Fichte; Cousin, to Kant and
Schelling. There is perhaps an outlet of the French aesthetic
nature in the philosophy which gathered about the aesthetic
response as presented by Schelling. It was, however, also a
presentation of nature as having the objectivity of the mind
writers of the time were ScheUing
see the different reactions to the
itself.
This made the philosophy of Schelling attractive to
Cousin and other thinkers of the time.
The other expression to which I have referred, that of activity, found its statement in a psychological method which was
affirmed as the
method of this philosophy. It is the expresRomantic idealism. This was developed in
sion, of course, of
Germany
in the affirmation
of the absolute philosophy, in the
statement that our own selves are simply aspects of the Absolute Self. This carrying-back of experience, objective experience, to the self found
its expression in French philosophy in the
assumption that the philosophical method is essentially a psychological method. If one did make a consistent philosophical
system on this basis, he would find himself in the position
of the German Romantic idealists, as that appears in Hegel's
phenomenology. This metaphysical statement, however, was
not taken over and made use of by the French philosophers. They
[446]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
insisted that the study of the self as
it
appears
in introspection is
method of which philosophy makes use. This philosophy
had, in some sense, fortified itself with the Kantian position.
The structure of the mind determines the structure of the
world. The problem of getting from the mind over into the
world it knows is a problem which must first be faced; but it
presumably has built its bridges by means of the Kantian asthe
sumption, connected, of course, in a certain sense with the assumptions of the Scottish school. It has already made its established contact with the world.
The
structure of the world
some sense the same. The former will be
studied, then, in the mind, as it can be got at most readily there.
The method given is psychological. That is the French interpretation of Romantic idealism as it was seen in Germany. That
idealism, of course, had a late after-birth in England in the neoHegelian movement. But the influence of Hegel, as it appeared
in Carlyle and Coleridge and men of that sort, was literary. In
France the definite inference from this idealism came especially
by way of the Kantian philosophy of Cousin, but it had none of
the air of abandon of the Romantic idealistic philosophy in Germany. It was carefully regimented. It dealt with a mind which
has definite faculties. It takes over the problems which Kant
had thrown up in the doctrine of a common consciousness in
which are given the forms of mind which are also the forms of
matter. By this method men could turn back to study themselves with a feeling that the study of the self was also a study
of the world; that the same drama was present in the mind as in
nature; that nature was free, an odyssey of spirit. One could
study nature, its reality, its structure, in some sense, in our own
and of the mind are
in
minds.
Another characteristic which was present in this school, one
which led to greater fruitfulness, was the interest in history.
The Romantic school affected all Europe in this same fashion.
It
was the essence of the Romantic movement
to return to the
past from the point of view of the self-consciousness of the Ro-
[447]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
mantic period, to become aware of itself in terms of the past.
We have a Romantic interest expressed in Voltaire in the re-
newed
interest in the
have
it
soul,
which
more primitive conditions of
society.
We
in the reaction of a national consciousness, a national
definitely has that
tory of the individual.
which is comparable to the hisof Hegel in going back to the
The work
expression of racial and national
community consciousness exThe interest of the school
pressed itself early in philosophy.
of Royer-Collard in the history of philosophy also reflected
the
is
same
spirit.
But
it
not a history of philosophy which
is
the statement of the other side of a theory of metaphysical
was the case with Hegel. Hegel presented the developthe categories as they take place in our thought and
the development of these categories as they take place in history as two sides of a single process. The study we find in
France has more feudal interest behind it. It is interested in
men, and it led to very important advances. It is an acute critical study of Greek philosophy, particularly of Plato, It was inlogic, as
ment of
terested in the building-up of a school of philosophical thought
that was not committed to a metaphysical interpretation. Its
statement was not the reflection of a single philosophical doctrine.
The
philosophical doctrine of Cousin, on the other hand,
was tenuous and
est in the
superficial.
study of
earlier
It
never seriously had a real inter-
philosophy and in the presentation
on the basis of actual documents and
of
it
in
terms of historical criticism.
interest existing in
the period of
that idealism
You
German philosophy
Romantic
is still
idealism.
found
their interpretation
find that sort of systematic
that has gotten beyond
Something of the
spirit of
such a work as Zeller's History of
in
Greek Philosophy. It also passed over into the interpretation of
history in the
Marxian movement.
It
has
its reflection in
the
interpretation of history in the formulation of the Flegelian
doctrine of the state.
It
has
less
detachment than French
his-
tory of philosophy, as reflected in the uncertainty of the philosophical presuppositions of the French thinkers.
[448]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
vni
There is another figure of more importance to us than Cousin,
though he made relatively little stir at the time. This is Comte,
I have presented Royer-Collard and the philosophy of the revolution.
Comte has
his connection
with the philosophy of
action, that of the church in the reactionary period.
He
re-
has
but it is the other that is the taproot
of his philosophy. If we are going to understand the man, we
his revolutionary aspects,
must
realize that.
The philosophy
of the early period, the philosophy of the
De
Maistre and DeBonald the philosophy
of the Restoration, that of Royer-Collard which was the philosophy of the bourgeois monarchy, were all practical in some
revolution, that of
Another element, however, was forcing its way in and
was setting the temper for the later philosophical thought. This_
element was science, a science which was not political. The con"ftection between philosophy and science is a connection which
may be made either through a cosmology (a theory of the physical universe) or through methodology (the attempt to present
the world as a whole, to organize all the different sciences into
sense.
a single science, to criticize the concepts of the different sciences
from the standpoint of others).
we
find in
particular
science.
all
philosophy.
field.
And
sciences set
This
is
The
This attempt is one which
is occupied with his own
scientist
especially true of
modern, specialized
the very restriction of the fields of the different
up what may be
called "organic relationships" be-
tween them. You cannot consider a biological field by itself
without putting it into relationship with the physical environment in which the organism is found. You cannot concentrate
your attention on the digestive tract of an animal without taking into account the whole life of that animal. You must relate
the one in its organic functioning with the other. You cannot,
in a physical sense, take
up the consideration of physics as over
up relationships between the
against chemistry without setting
different fields.
Thus
the scientists themselves feel the necessity
of this interrelationship.
It gets its fullest expression
[449]
on the
THOUGHT IN THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
philosophical side, and in every generation there have been
philosophical scientists or philosophers
the science of the period.
who
are familiar with
There have always been those who
endeavor to present a concept of the world as a whole, with the
interrelationship of the different sciences.
It is possible,
however,
for
philosophy to approach science
not through a conception of the different
scientific fields
but
from the point of view of the scientific method. The scientific
in the Greek period was not different from the method
of philosophy. Plato was educating his young men, so that they
would become guardians or philosopher-kings, by giving them
work on geometry. The method of geometry was the method of
the philosopher. It was a process of deduction from the very
nature of the ideas with which the geometrician or philosopher
method
dealt.
Aristotle, entering the field of biology, carried into the
new method, the development of a teleomatter as potentiality and substance, as the
reahzation of matter in form. This concept he brought over
from science. It was a conception which he used both in his
studies of animals and plants and in his consideration of metaphilosophical field a
logical concept of
physics.
far as
He
dre\^^no_iine,between..p.hjlosaphy^
method was concerned. Both Plato and
themselves as philosophers
biologists.
in so far as
There was but a
Aristotle regard
they are astronomers and
single field with a single
The Renaissance introduced
method.
new method which was distime. Bacon presented it as an
a
from the philosophy of its
method which was not one of Aristotelian induction.
It appeared sharply in the work of the great scientists of the
period as the experimental method. What was peculiarly scientific in it, as distinct from the philosophical method of the time,
was that it dealt with that which was taking place not in terms
of the substance of things but in terms of events as they took
place. Galileo registered this in his statement of it as a new science. He called it "dynamics." Aristotle's treatment of falling
bodies was that the nature of heavy bodies was to move toward
the earth. He deduced their velocity from their weight: the
tinct
inductive
[450]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
more they weighed, the greater their velocity. He start ed with
the object and deduced from that what the nature of the process^
"must l)c. What GalTTeoundertook to do was to find out what the
velocity of the object wasTtTmct. If you take that method over
Into biology, you come to a statement of the physiological organism in terms of its functions. You ask what a digestive tract
Instead of starting off with the form of the stomach, you
is.
start off with the digestive tract and state its nature in terms of
the function it has to carry out. Then you can see why it has a
why it has a different function. You state your
such terms that you can define it in terms of the
process going on. This is just the opposite of what you find in
the Aristotelian science and philosophy, where you get the nacertain form,
problem
in
ture of the object
first
and define
nature of the object itself.
What I want to point out
ern scientific
method
its
in this
processes in terms of the
connection
is
that our
abstracts from the things which
philosophically, metaphysically defined,
and occupies
mod-
had been
itself
with
brought on what we now call the
"event" as the object of observation. We do not observe, as
Aristotle observed, to see through the process to what the nature of the object itself is. We observe to see what changes take
what
place,
is
is
happening.
what motions
It has
are going on,
and
at
what
velocities.
the character of the observation; and that
course, in the biological world as far as
sion in evolution.
which
is
Observ ation
it
has
its
is
That
also true, of
modern
expres-
can be ^directed toward that
taking place and can, to that extent,^be abstracted from
That is, it can ignore metaphysics.
Aj;istotelian science was bound up with its metaphysics. Our
biology, until evolution set it free, was bound up with metaphysics. It could explain species only in terms of creation. But
tITe
nature of the thing
itself.
an evolution which explains the development of form is free
from such a metaphysical statement-^ Well_th^n^.tJie_point^hat
I
am
rnal5ingJs.that]modern sciencejCateresLtfid-m
"pens'asdistinct from the thin^ which was supposed to be resp^nsibFe^lor the nature of the happening.
And when
it
comes
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
to the statement of the thing,
ess going on.
It
is
free
it
defines itjn terms of the proc-
from metaph}^^ics<^ /
Now,
ism.
the reflection of dim. ill- philosophy .appears in positivPositivism is the statement of reahty in terms of so-
called
(^
"phenomena."-^These are the things that happen, that
which is going on. Positivism abstracts the process, the event,
from the nature of the things that are involved in what is going
on. That such a process of knowledge should be possible is, of
course, due to the experimental method. This method presents
a test by means of which you can consider by themselves what
the philosopher calls "phenomena" and still standardize your
knowledge. These are the two characters of scientific method
which put it in such an independent place as over against
philosophy: it can abstract from the nature of what is involved in the process of the world; it can in that way free
from metaphysics in so far as it studies phenomena. The
philosopher has no method by means of which he can contest its
claims. The experimental method set the scientist free from the
jtself
philosophur>)
The attempt
are called
method into philosophy is found in
undertakes to deal with phenomena. They
to carry this
positivism, Vv'hich
"phenomena"
in the philosophic sense; "facts" in the
A fact is something that happens, takes place.
no problem of a certain "nature" in what is taking
place. Put it in philosophical terms, and it is something happening that has a relation to a noumenon that lies back of it.
Positivism deals with what is there, what is positive and directly
experienced, whose processes the mind can follow. It was Comte
scientific sense.
There
is
who undertook
to carry over this
was by no means
who gave
the
free
method
from metaphysical
first definite
into philosophy.
taint,
but he
is
the one
philosophical statement to the
descriptive aspect of science.
He was
the
first
He
more
one to make the
attempt to build up philosophy along the lines_of the scientific
method.
It follows, of course, that such a method is hypothetical.
What one
does
is
to follow a curve, so to speak.
[45^-]
On
the basis of
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
observation, one assumes or
curve
a
is
makes the hypothesis that the
of a certain character.
body moving
If
it is
of that character, then
such a path would have to be at such and
in
such a point at such and such a time, and one could observe and
make
sure that the
body was
may
concerned; but there
movement
be something in
has not been able to determine.
it
tion, a
is
essentially hypothetical.
way
make
means of that
later
be
the scientific
is,
Of
that
is
be and justify-
course, one can
involved in any-
In some sense everything
everything that happens.
hypothetical.
all
may
it
may
result.
a complete statement of
thing that happens.
is
method of extrapola-
is
of determining what the result
ing one's theory by
never
It
of the body
that the scientist
In that case
necessary to reconstruct the hypothesis. That
method
The
at that point in its process.
hypothesis is justified, in so far as that
is
involved in
Consequently, the theory must be
The experimental method,
as applied
by
science,
always implies that a theory is hypothetical.
What positivism undertook to do was to deal with that which
fallswithin the fi^eld^fphilosophic thought as we deal with scienfi'fic^'data, in terms of scientific method. There we deal with
the event as it appears. The event as it appears for the scientist,
tist
the observer,
the sensation in consciousness.
are connected with
be discovered, and forms a
it,
finds
will
tests this hypothesis
by future events and
still
The assumption
is
here
scien-
itself.
which these events
but a theory which
The
Then he finds out
what uniformity
hypothesis of the way in
takes the event as something by
what other events
may
is
be associated with each other.
establishes a theory,
remains hypothetical
that knowledge
is
He
in
character.
to be obtained only
through the observation of events and the testing of hypotheses
as tfiey appear in experience, and that the immediate object of
knowledge is the event and the thing. Here we have a philosophy which is positivistic in character. If we cannot treat entities in terms of metaphysical things, we can deal with them
at least as far as our experience is concerned. The matter that
lies back of the qualities of the chair is something that does not
[453]
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
enter into experience.
It is
not positive knowledge. This
is
same general character as that of
Hume. As far as his account of what we have in our cognitive
experience is concerned, Hume comes back to impressions and
ideas and the analysis of them. In thinking of the substance of
statement which
of the
is
things, he says we have uniformities which reveal themselves in
our experience in terms of habit; and that is what Hume was
interested in
the
relation of events in experience to the so-
called "laws of nature."
the case of positivism, of the form in which it was espoused
by Comte, the interest does not lie primarily in reducing naajv ture and its uniformities to associated ideas. What Comte ^yas
t
*|V /^ interested in was the relation between the events as they take
j place. He did not bring up the questicm as to where those events
Intake place, whether in the mind or in the world, whether "there
is something that answers to them as they take place in the
*^ mirid. He said here are the events; we call some subjective,
'some objective. Let us find the uniformity of their happening,
\Xd
not only for an observational science but also for philosopK^Oi,
Comte was particularly interested in the appearance oFthis
method and its relationship to the formal metaphysical content which should lie behind it. He went back into the history
of thought to the Greek period, with
and asked what
lies
behind
it.
its
metaphysical method,
He showed
the interpretation
of the world in terms of gods, of magic influences of spirits,
and then showed how Greek philosophy, becoming rationadvanced beyond this concept of gods to the concept
of certain natures which belong to things. Such a statement as
that which Aristotle gives is partly theological and partly metaalistic,
physical.
He
enly bodies
is
assumed,
divine.
for
example, that the nature of the heav-
He assumed
that there
of a divine being that directs the motion of
They
must be some
all
sort
planetary bodies.
had conceived, but deprived of the anthropomorphic aspects we find in mythology.
Aristotle conceived of them as responsible for the motions of the
heavenly bodies, although he assumed that these bodies, by naare gods, such gods as the Greeks
454
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
ture,
move
in circular orbits
and with uniform
velocities.
On
the
face of the earth this teleological element largely disappears,
and
move toward
the
you have heavy bodies whose tendency
is
to
center of the earth, Aristotle did not conceive of these as direct-
ed by divine beings. From the standpoint of nature, there is no
very great difference between assuming that the growth of a
tree is due to a dryad or to a certain metaphysical substance
which belongs by nature to the tree. The growth of trees is such
as
it is.
You can think of it in pictorial form, show it as it is, a
You can think of the force of the tree as that which
living tree.
comes-from a living being or from an inherent force of nature
that tends to develop itself in a certain way. There is a certain
nature in the acorn which, given an opportunity, will develop
Jnto a sapling and then into an oak.
A scientific statement is a natural development of the theological statement. The intermediate, metaphysical statement
is, of course, free from all the anthropomorphic characters of
the theological statement. It does not have to be brought inside
of the sphere of magic. The mind is free in that respect. But
still it is bound to the definition which it gives of the nature of
the object itself. Having given that definition, it can deduce
certain necessary qualities from it. So we find that the Aristotelian metaphysics regards not a growing science but a completed
science. Aristotle was the Encyclopedist of his period. He gathored into his statements all'that could be known, and put it in
^terms of the nature of the things that make up the world,
things that we find in the world when put in their necessary
^gic;il relations to each other. Such a statement has a certain
finality about it, provided it is carried out by a genius, like,
Aristotle, who is able to gather together and organize a great
~I)ody of diverse material. If the summation has been a very complete one, there is no invitation to anyone to carry it further.
That is what is striking, but with such a complete science interest
lapses,.^
The type of problem which comes with
as expressing the experimental
method,
[455]
is
the
work of
essentially
Galileo,
one which
>
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
comes from the method of research
science, not from the science
of the Encyclopedists, not from the type that
"systematic."
There are certain
fields
we sometimes
into
which
call
new
this
method has entered comparatively late. Biology, to go back for
a generation or a little more perhaps, took into itself everything
men knew; and anything
that they did not know, at the
There were certain groupings of
the genera, the famiHes, and their species and subplants
species. There was a principle of organization, a principle which
was worked out in the eighteenth century by Linnaeus. Into
this system could be introduced any new species that might be
found, but the system itself did not carry with it any proof.
That is not a research science. Research science has come into
that
time, could be added to
it.
biology only with evolution, for the conception of evolution
deals with species not as ultimate metaphysical entities but as
/
''
-
something that arises out of conditions. Experience, instead of
being of such and such a metaphysical entity, becomes a problem. That is, of course, presented to us in Darwin's great work.
What is the origin of species? This question indicates a new
line of approach. The earlier concept was that characters and
species were given in the creation of the plant or animal. God
gave to the plants and animals a certain nature for their preservation. The whole life-history of plants and animals shows the
development of this nature. The cataloguing system enables
us to give them their characters and place them in a complete
science. A scientific problem is itself not a statement that here
is
the oak, the ox, the tiger.
is
the oak there;
why
is it
It
is
rather the question:
oak instead of another
tree;
"Why
what
is
the meaning of this species?"
In what
have been saying, you have a very vivid. illustra-
tion of the passage from the metaphysical over to
would
call
the "positivistic state." There are, said
what Comte
Comte, these
three stages of development, the theological, the metaphysical,
the positivistic.
And
he said this
munities but of individuals.
things arid persons.
He
is
true not only of
com-
child lives in a world of magical-
loves things that
[456]
meet
hi s wishes,
an^
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
he hates things. tJigt hurt him. And then comes the later period
gives up these magical implications and takes to hard
when he
%,and fixed definitions of things. The objects about him have certain natures. They are not to be looked at from the point of
view of a fairyj:al g. It is a common-sense attitude if you like,
BuTarTa
ttitude which in itself is metaphysical in that each thing
^
from other things. Beand the child utilizes
cause of its nature, it
these qualities. It is the common-sense attitude which all persons^oTadult years reflect in regard to the objects about them.
The natural definition of a chair is that it is something having
has a scertain nature that distinguishes
it
has certain qualities;
certain necessary qualities
other qualities
cal
statement
tude toward
inhering
is
all
it
has hardness, a certain form, and
in a certain nature.
a statement as that which
is
atti-
Then we advance
Comte stated it. Such
things as they exist about us.
to the positivistic, the scientific, stage as
chair
That metaphysi-
nothing but the abstract formulation of our
had been given of the nature of the
recognized as utterly incomplete.
What
is
there that
For example, how does
depart
from the metaphysiiron
or
We
compare
with
steel?
it
cal attitude when we ask: "What happens when we do this,
that, and the other thing to the object?" We try to find certain' uniformities by means of which we can determine what
will happen. We have passed out of a world of fixed things as
such and come back to data which we can get in experience.
We have to distinguish between what the scientist refers to as
"hard facts" and the objects about us. Persons are said to
"come up against hard facts." Their theory comes in conflict
with a fact. But the fact against which the theory comes in
conflict is a happening of some sort; it is a happening which is
not the happening that we anticipated from a certain theory.
Give a certain theory, \\ e expect certain happenings; and then
ex^ erie .ce
somethi g else happens. It is the contr .diction
that is the hard fact of science.
That is the phase that we need to keep in mind in getting the?
scientific method as it appears in such a system as that of
gives to
wood
its
particular strength?
"I
[457]
THOUGHT
Comte. What one
IN
is
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
dealing with
is
a set of events that take place
you find uniformities; they never
get a final statement, however. Given the statement, we have a
theory; we are then able to determine vv^hat the results will be on
the basis of that theory. If something else happens, then the
in experience. In those events
theory must be reconstructed.
things that are going on.
The
The world
is
a world of events, of
scientist's attitude is the expres-
sion of the positivistic statement that succeeds the medieval
This exemplifies the three-stage theory of Comte.
As communities and as individuals we pass through three stages
the theological, the metaphysical, and the scientific. From
the point of view of philosophy, the importance of the view lies,
you see, in the statement of the object of knowledge. Is one considering substance or is one considering events that are taking
statement.
what philosophers would call "phenomena"? Is knowlwith these or with something that these reveal?
edge
occupied
i^
observation
a finding, an isolation, of a certain nature or
n -^ '^^ "^
form that lies back of it all? Or is it occupied with the phe/-
''k/
Stv
lf^.
.,
nomena themselves?
*vj^/,
^f
\place,
knowledge
It
is
a question as to
what the function of
is.
IX
r
^,'
'
The important
Comte's doctrine was its
recognition of what we may term the "philosophical import" of
scientific methods As I have indicated, the scientific method
recognized the object of knowledge in the experience of the individual, in that which is ordinarily termed the "fact." If one is
to identify the fact, he must do it in terms of his experience. It
characteristic of
of course, true that the observer states his observation in
such terms that it can also be made an object by others and so
is,
be tested by them. He tries to give it a universal form, but still
he comes back eventually to the account which he gives of his
observation as such.
What
is
not recognized in the positivistic doctrine
is
that the
observation is always one that has an element of novelty in it.
That is, it is in some sense unusual. It is observed because it is
distinct in some way from the expected experience. One does
[458]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
not observe that which
recognizes
it.
We
is
we
for a
book
in its place
that the object
little
is
attention as
is
after
on the
and
notes
it is
shelf, all
expected.
is
one
in its
If
one
expected place, or
he gives attention to
of the type that he expects to find.
is
it;
expect, and give attention
only to that which differs from that which
reaches for a tool that he
One
to be expected.
recognize what
necessary in order to identify
it.
He
is
gives as
More than
this would mean loss of effort and time. One does not stop to
examine the expression of his friend unless there is something
unusual about it. He sees only enough to identify him. Ordinarily, then, we would not speak of an observer as one who
merely recognizes. Observation implies careful noting of all the
details of the object. It is true that you do not observe everything about anything. What one does is to observe all that enables one to assure himself that the object is not exactly what
one expects. One reaches for a tool, thinking he is going to
pick up a hammer, and finds it is a chisel; and he pays attention to find why it was that he made the mistake. He observes
the character of a plant that misled him. His observation is
given to that which distinguishes it from the expected thing.
These are the facts of science those observations that enable
us to determine characters that would not have been antici-
i
/
!
\
\
pated.
One may
also, of course, give attention to objects that
seem quite familiar. That is what is implied. You are looking
for something that will strike your attention as in some sense
The
unusual.
L,
z:;
-\
assumes that our objects are given in (
such observation, and that is the logical weakness of positivism. }
It assumes that the world is made up, so to speak, out of facts,
is made up out of those objects that appear in the experience of
the scientific observer. Most objects we regard simply as they
identify themselves. The objects of scientific observation answer
to a detailed analysis, which implies an interest of some sort. We
can explain this position in terms of the method to which I
refer, by saying that the objects of science do not always have
positiyistic doctrine
behind them implicit or explicit problems. In other words,
[459]
sci-
,A<*r'
0^
.
,4,
^o\V'*'
--^
^"^
f
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Research always implies a problem. Where there is nothing of this sort, we are not engaged
in research. There is a type of thinking which is not problematical
that of carrying out a habitual act, of attending a machine
with which you are familiar, for example. That sort of concentrated attention is given simply to those stimuli that will enable
us to carry out a well-formed habit. There we have concentrated attention, but it is not occupied with the proceedings of our
research science. It is occupied in a world where one is awake
only to the next stimulus that is necessary to carry on an activence
is
really research science.
ity that
more or
less
runs
further step which
longs to a later period,
how
takes to see
itself.
Comte
is
did not recognize, because
be-
Evoluand undertook
these forms, these experiences, arise.
tionary doctrine started off with the life-process,
to
it
the evolutionary one which under-
account for the appearance of species themselves. It carries
us back to a world in which the nature of the object, the experi-
ence as such,
arises.
Neither
Comte nor John
Stuart Mill,
who
would be the corresponding figure in England, was influenced by
doctrine to any great degree. Mill was also, to all
intents and purposejj^ a positivist. He, too, assumed tKat the
analysis"^aftbg, scientist makes of an object reveals_tEe^tht:r-
^ J evolutionary
7^
acters of things, reveals the elements of things, the .p.grts of
diings; and
if
we want
to
know
the world,
embodied
this doctrine in his logic in
the logic of science.
scientific
It is
we must
discover
you know,
which he undertook to state
these elements which the scientist finds.
Mill, as
by no means an adequate account of
procedure; but his theory of induction and of the in-
ductive process in science, his method of agreement and difference, are definitely attempts to state the scientist's procedure.
They
are really
methods of distinguishing rather than of forming
hypotheses.
am
attempting to make clear is that the positivistic
doctrine was one which undertook to give the philosophic implications the form of scientific method. But neither Comte nor
Mill gave a competent account of the scientist's procedure.
What
[460]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
did assume that science what we would call "research
science" was the most efficient method of knowing. They did
recognize that this type of science was one which was an advance over metaphysical science, while the metaphysical was a
They
natural successor to theology.
We
have, then,
in the
French^
thought of this period, the reconstruction of science as presntingtheiormof the philosophic problem.
The
step which positivism represents
lem so that
it is
put
in the
is
that of stating a prob-
form of a method rather than of a
re-
Can
one rtta^e tliejnethpdpTscience the method of philosophy One
"great, somewhat grandiose efiPort to solve this problem was made
by the Romantic idealists. Hegel, who was most complete in his
statement, undertook to show that the method of science and
the method of human thought in all its endeavor and the
method of the universe were all the same, the method which he
sult.
Is the
method of
science jhejoieihod of philosophy?
^u
\
represented by his dialectic process. His philosophy was in one
sense~a philosophy of evolution; but the same process, the same
method, the same logic, lay back of physical nature, back of
moral effort, back of human history, back of all that science preIt was, as I said in other connections, a grandiose undertaking which was a failure. Particularly, it was unable to present the scientific procedure within each field. It could not sue-
sents.
cessfully state the
lem, then, that
physics
is
past;
is
method of research
science.
This
is
/
\
the prob- \
presented in positivism. For positivism meta-
gone. Just as metaphysics was supposed to
it is
iXT
^
^'
have wiped out theology, so the positivists were presenting a ) jjlr\
method which could be immediately applied, and through which/'
we could
get rid of metaphysics.
X
Comte had as vivid an interest in the relation of
phy to society and its values as any others of the
his philoso-
period.
He
looked for the forms of a society of the human race whose values
should determine the conduct of the individual. But, as far as
the process of knowing social values was concerned, it would be
[461]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
the same as in the physical and the biological sciences. He assumed that there could be a study of society which could be undertaken in the same way as the study of the physical sciences.
That was the most striking character of his doctrine in its immediate impact. The church had a metaphysical doctrine behind it. And this is no less true in this period of what we may
the theory of law, of ethics, of education.
each of them had essential doctrines. The sovereignty
of the state, in the attitude of an English community, is to be
found in the individuals that form the repubhc. Sovereignty
call "political science,"
That
is,
was a dogma.
power.
And
It
was that
in the state
which exercised absolute
the state had to be conceived of in terms of such
metaphysical entity as that. Similarly, the family was a certain
definite entity,
and the school was
a certain definite entity.
One
argued from the nature of the sovereign, of the family, of the
school, what the position of the individual under it must be. In
each case the attitude was essentially metaphysical. ^^0i2t Comte
presented was the demand for the use of positivistic method Jtl
the study of society. He presented sociology as a new fieldr-*
What I want to emphasize is that we do not think of it as an-
We have economics, education, political science;
and here comes sociology, another science covering the same
field and yet claiming to be different. J^ has been in veryjC:::
cent times, a great question as to whether there was any such
thing as sociology. And I have seen theses presented in this university for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the field of
sociology upon the prob lem of whether or not there is any such
thing as sociology. \^^JLis characteristic of Comte's position is
his demand that society and social events should be approached
in the same fashion that the study of plants and animals and
moving bodies are approached. He was breaking away from the
metaphysical attitude and presenting another science, that of
society. As he conceived of society, it inevitably includes the
whole human race; and he thought there could be one science of
^it.
Sociology, then, was the attempt to apply the method of
other science.
positivism, the
method of
science, to the
[462]
ifield
of spcrefy^an at-
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
__temtJjQ_^isplace--wlmtJ&:aSv aj_.t h ^^ Hnie, an essent[aJh^jTTerathg^tate, with a study oi-the pwocesse^ of socialxhanes_gQing-iiiU'
ift-^YanouS-in^sti tiitionp
affairs in the
way
Comte undertook to approach human
who simply analyzes things
of the scientist
and then
I
from that finds the laws of their behavior. JBut there lay in^thc^^H^
b ack o f Comte's mind pictures of a medieval period, ontjrTTe C !f'^
J^
would have substituted society for the pope. He was nut freed \
JixmL^that^TKis other side of Conitels-doxitrinejs one thatjiarks
back to the medieval period.
I pointed out that early in the century, during the period of
De Bonald and De Maistre, reactionary philosophers sought to
go back to the church as the source of all authority, as that
which must give an interpretation of life. Their statement, however, was different from the medieval statement. They were particularly impressed with the society of Europe in the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries, the period which is best represented by
Dante. It was a period in which the world realized itself as a
single community, in which everything could be explained by
the doctrine of the church. There was no difficulty in the explanation, because this world was so created that man can be
moral; and, if he can be moral, it must also be possible for him
to be immoral. It is a world in which sin has a legitimate place;
and if man sins, the punishment of sin follows. The world at
that period was entirely comprehensible from the point of view
of the church theology. It included everyone. Anything that
into their ultimate elements in a positivistic fashion
happened that w^ as undesirable could be explained by the fact
that God was using it to bring about the great good, including
the good of man. The Western world was conceived of as a
single society. It took in nearly the whole of the human race. It
was organized through the church. The church took over the
statement that St. Paul gives, you remember, of the church as
the body of which Christ was the head. In his concept of a unified society everyone has his place and everything can be explained from the point of view of the theory of the church.
[463]
THOUGHT
X ^i
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
!<
which was a world society, an organic society, and a society which answered to the immediate impulse of the individual that these philosophers, De
Bonald and De Maistre, went back.
Coixite.,was never influenced by this account. His positions
freed him from the dogma of the church, but he still looked to
such a picture of the whole society of man as representing the
idea that should be realized. The curious thing from our standpoint is that he should have copied to such an extent the characters of the church. His ideay_too,-j5fas~th.at.^o.ciety should be
an organic whole. It must then have some organized value.
What Comte presents, instead of welfare by the church, is the
it
was
to that conception of a society
welfare of the
community
as a whole.
This community as a
whole comes to take the place of the glory of God, which, as
spoken of by the church, is the end of all existence. For the
positivist it is not the glory of God but the good of mankind
that is the supreme value. That is the supreme value in terms
/of which everything should be stated. This point of view is
stated in less emotional form in the utilitarianism in England
during the same period. Bentham and the Mills are, in a sense,
cornp^anipjijigures^^to Comte. Their idea of the ideal society is
bne which achieves the greatest good of the greatest number.
This welfare of the community transcends the good of any particular individual. This is something all should see, and man's
attitude toward it should be a religious attitude. This should
be recognized as the supreme value that determines all others.
And Comte recognized that an emotional attitude was essential.
John Stuart Mill said that everyone finds himself and his conduct constantly influenced by others. Each can retain his own
pleasure by recognizing others in the pursuit of their pleasure.
The
individual feels continually the presence of the
community
about him forcing him to recognize the interest of others. It
seems a skeptical account which Mill gives of the origin of virtue. Comte would put up the good of the community itself
through an emotional expression which should be essentially
religious in its character. That is, men should actually worship
[464]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
Supreme Being
in the form of society. Society as an organwhich is responsible for the individual, should
be worshiped; and on this basis Comte undertook to set up
a positivistic religion. Now, this religion of positivism had some
vogue among the followers of Comte. There was a devoted
group of this sort to be found in England. It never attained any
size. A wag, referring to a dissension among them, said of the
sessions, "They came to church in one cab and left in two." It
never became a widespread religious movement, but the undertaking to set up such a religion which should find the highest
value in society and fuse that into a unity which could be worshiped was characteristic of Comte. He thought and looked for
a society that could be organized in the same fashion as medieval society had been by the church. And he attempted to work
out in some detail how this sort of ordering of society would take
the
ized whole, as that
place.
Fie did not try to substitute the value of society itself
for the Deity,
but tried to take over the religious attitude to-
ward the Deity into the religious attitude of members of the
community toward society itself.
This phase of Comte's sociology was not a lasting one. What
was of importance was his emphasis on the dependence of the
individual on society, his sense of the organic character of sociis
what
its
theo-
ety as responsible for the nature of the individual. This
Comte put
into a scientific form. It
had already found
have said, in Paul's account of the relation of men in the church to parts of the body and to the church
as the whole. That is, he conceived of the individual as determined
logical statement, as I
by society as an organism, just as there are different organs
which must be conceived of as dependent on the organism as a
whole. You cannot take the eye as a separate reality by itself.
It has meaning only in its relationship to the whole organism of
which it is a part. So you must understand an individual in a
In^t^jd..QXthmking of society made up of different enCpj3rt.thought of it in terms of a union of all which was
.ascertain social nature which ji^tcrmioedTtKe"
society.
tities,
lere are
two characteristics of
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Comte:Jirst,. his recognition that society as such
study; and second, his conviction that
is
a subject for
we must advance from
the study of society to the individual rather than from the indi-
vidual to societyTy
XI
The next
want to emphasize is that in France the
philosophic mind was dominantly psychological. It was psychological in a different sense from that in which English empirical thought was psychological. It was also different from
the psychological position of Reid and the so-called Scottish
point
For example,
school.
it
recognizes activity as a fundamental
which science was studying,
and not simply the content of experience, not simply states of
consciousness. It recognizes that the process of knowledge is
characteristic of the experience
not simply the passive reception of impressions, but that it is
an organized process in knowledge. In sensation one can say
that the
mind just has impressions. But in perception you have
mind upon its own sensations, and perhaps on
a reaction of the
the objects which were supposed to be responsible for these
Activity, then, forms part of the content with
sensations.
which the French psychologists were occupied. They were also
much more interested in the affective side of life, the emotional
side. They were not, however, any more interested in the personality, the ego, the self, from the psychological side than were
the English empiricists. The Germans, of course, in their philosophy came back to the self as basic. It is central to their
whole doctrine. But their interest was metaphysical rather than
psychological.
The
interest of the
stream of
life
French psychologists was
in the actual
of the self rather than in the psychology of the
other groups. These others regarded psychology as the method
of philosophy.
This gave to their philosophy that character
expressed in the term "spiritualism."
that what
nature
in
is
That
revealed in our study of ourselves
itself.
is,
is
Comte agreed with
In one sense,
another sense, he did not.
[
in
it
assumed
accord with
this position;
In his adherence to science and
466
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
the conception of the Individual as a product of social forces
he did not.
The emphasis
of French philosophy was upon
it went back to its psyRoyer-CoUard,
for
example,
in taking over
chological method.
the Scottish form, comes back to our immediate intuition. He
relied upon those experiences with which psychology deals.
That is, he, like Reid, did not come back to immediate experiences in the sense that Descartes did. Descartes came back to
the immediate experience of his own existence as a self, as a
substantial being. Reid came back to that experience in its immediate psychological character. In our immediate experience
we are in contact with objects that we know. This is the aspect
of experience to which Reid came back. And French philosophy
laid particular emphasis on this same aspect of the individual.
Its method was that of psychology. Comte turned away from
that and tried to reduce psychology to biology. He denied the
the experience of the individual. In this
possibiUty of a science of psychology.
If
we
are to relate the French philosophy to that of
bors in England and
Germany,
it is
The whole
essentially psychological interest.
its
neigh-
essential to recognize this
interest of the
English analysts was in carrying the division of experience
impressions,
everyone back to common
common memory images
back to that which was psychical
in the sense of being private
back to that which was
sensations,
common
common
to
not only in that it lies within the experience of an individual but
in the sense of having that particular character which belongs to
life as distinct from that of anyone else. What
and expressed on the philosophical and the literary side was the need of an active self to which these experiences
came back. Among the Germans we have seen thinkers coming
back to a logical process which is identical with experience, for
both are expressions of the single ego. But in that single ego it is
difficult to get to the common character which belongs to the
individual life, that in which sensations are identified with the
one's
own
inner
the French
life
felt
of the individual. This disappears in so far as
the experience of others and the infinite
[467]
it is
movement
known
to
of minds
THOUGHT
that are
is
common
to
it.
From
the logical standpoint, that which
pecuhar to the individual lacks
necessary
'
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
is real.
What
reality.
John Stuart Mill
universal and
is
definitely presented his phi-
^losophy in a psychological form. So did his father. But they
were interested in the analysis of the object of knowledge. They
proceeded on the principle that if they could get back to the elements of knowledge they could determine the character of
/ objects. They find these in what were called "impressions" and
"ideas," which are located by the individual in his own experience. Their method, then, was that of introspection. What the
school was interested in, and what it placed emphasis on, was
the object of knowledge as such. Thus their problem was essen-
>,
tially the epistemological
/ The
interest of the
problem.
French philosopher was not
in the episte-
mological problem. It lay, rather, in the attack on certain institutions.
They were
the church and state.
interested in puUing
This problem was
down
first
the theories of
attacked by the
was eswas recognized as having
that political bias. When philosophy was being established on
more definite philosophical bases, when France was endeavoring
to get itself out of the situation which had been left by the Revolution, a turn was made to the philosophy ofJReid, taking over
his position that one has immediate knowledge of that which
lies outside, and particularly emphasizing the test of that
knowledge which Reid had insisted on, the test of common
sense, a sense which is common to all. This left the experience
of the individual as a field which was of deep interest in itself.
It was no longer simply the field within which the object of
knowledge was found. It was that in which the experience of
the individual was found. The object of knowledge is common.
"sensationalists," as their opponents called them. This
sentially a revolutionary school. It
It
is
only in so far as
other hand,
it lies
it is
public that
it
has validity.
in the experience of the individual.
On
the
The em-
phasis of the empirical school had been on that object as
it
was
supposed to exist in the experience of all; and, while they recognized that it appeared in the experience of the individual, their
I468I
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
interest centered in finding out
common
what was the import of its being
property. If one sets this doctrine up as the theory of
knowledge, it implies that the mind itself has direct acquaintance with its object. It has, in some sense, cut the Gordian knot.
You cannot
That
ask
how you know;
the fact
is
that you do know!
leaves the field of the experience of the individual as a field
which may have interest in itself. And it was this interest which
the French took up.
As I have said, they were following out what was characits memoirs, its
teristic of the French mind and its genius
study of the experience of the individual, as found, for example,
in Montaigne. That interest belonged peculiarly to the French.
They were interested in the experience of the individual just as
an individual, and in the recounting of that experience. As I
said, they took the position of Reid; but they took it in a somewhat different form. Their position approached that of Kant.
They assumed a general experience which was common in some
sense to all, something answering to the transcendental ego. The
forms of the mind, which were common to all individuals, are
the Kantian reply to the position of the English empirical school
and their skepticism; and French philosophy took ov^r this answer. It is this interest that characterized French thought and
its
psychology.
And
this interest gives a certain definite turn to
French psychology and to the philosophy that depended on it.
To get that angle one must realize the development taking
place in Germany. After the development of the Romantic
school the
We
have,
Germans
first
of
all,
also turned to psychological investigation.
the philosophy of Herbart, which
may
be
said to answer to the tendency among the French. Herbart undertook to establish his philosophy on the basis of ideas as they
appear
in the
minds of the individual. The principal application
of this Herbartian psychology was in the field of education.
Herbart was himself a theorist in the field of education. He
looked on the mind from the point of view of the increase of
knowledge. The organization of ideas in the mind answers to
the Lockian idea, a state of consciousness which has a reference
[469]
THOUGHT
to
something
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
that out of which the intellectual
else,
against the affective and volitional
life, is
built up.
bart was interested in pointing out was that
it
made
life,
as over
What Her-
was the organizathe mind able to
mind that
Taking over the Kantian term, he called this organization "apperception," and not simply "perception" in the
sense of immediate experience not simply the organization of
that experience in terms of association but a perception which
is a unified grasp of the sense in experience. Now this Herbart
referred to as an "apperceptive mass of ideas." The gist of the
doctrine was that grasping anything, taking it over into the
mind, is dependent on there being given such a mass. There
must be a group of ideas to which one might look for connective
factors which give ideas their essential relations. The value of
this theory was to be found not only in the application of it to
tion of these elements in the
isolate others.
education but also in the beginnings of the science of language.
In those two fields the Herbartian psychology remained significant long after
There
is
mans
But another
in
its
influence
a certain
had been
lost elsewhere.
community between
the French and Ger-
connection with their interest in psychological content.
distinction
must be made. German psychologists,
especially Herbart's successors, were laying stress on the organ-
ism and its structure. This resulted in a significant physiological psychology. If youstudy what takes place in experience in
terms of the central nervous system and the nervous mechanism
in general, you will find that which is common, universal. The
technique of your study will be to isolate what your experience
has in common with the experience of others. But suppose
you get a curious experience like color blindness, where one
person
fails to
distinguish red from green.
Even
this
may
be
isolated, at least hypothetically, in terms of certain color spots
eye but are not. In this way you
universal statement of the unusual experience.
which should be present
get a
more or
less
in the
Just because this psychology was so interested in the organism
as such, it was stated in terms that belong to all organisms. The
study of the experience of the individual was put into the same
[470]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
terms.
Such an approach would
the individual that which
is
select
common
out of the experience of
in the experience of
all.
French psychology lays emphasis on that which is individual
and peculiar, on that which introspection reveals. The German
school passes over this, perhaps.
lem as
it
appears
Its interest is in the
in the organic responses
prob-
and mechanisms of
experience in the individual.
XII
The
came to have the largest
French philosophy, that about which other
problems were gathered, was that of mechanism and determinism as over against voluntary acts and free will. We have seen
that French philosophy had oriented itself with reference to
fact. Comt e had given expression to this in terms of scientific
method, as over against simply scientific results. He brought
over_a scientific method into philosophy and undertook to approach the problem of common reforms from the standpoint of
the method of science. Is there any place for common choice in
the world which science discusses? Can the worlds of will and of
law be brought together? That is the problem that fixed itself
in the mind of the French thinkers.
TTiey accepted a scientific statement that did not open the
door to the sort of miracle which you find in the statement of
Descartes, which assumes that God in some fashion enables
consciousness to react on the organism. They did not take that
course. They tried to find a place for consciousness in the world
as science presents it. There was no criticism of the scientist's
statement in his own terms; but they tried to find a way by
which choice could be brought into a mechanistic universe, a
world in which causal relations are dominant, in which one can
state, from the point of view of the causes, if he had them all,
what the effects must be. It was the sort of a picture suggested
by Laplace in his world-equation in which one would have only
to iritroduce the variable of time and solve it in order to find just
where every particle must be at any given instant. If that is
psychological problem that
meaning
for the
[471]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
your conception of physical science, is there any place, any
meaning, for human spontaneity, human freedom? That was
the problem which interested the French thinkers because of
their concern with their own inner experience. You do not find
this sort of problem dominating thought in England or Germany. It was peculiarly a French approach.
In the case of the English, we have the analysis of the object
of knowledge in terms of impressions and ideas, or sensations
and images, the interest lying in the treatment of the epistemological problem in reference to the content of the object of
knowledge as related to the states of consciousness of the individual. On the German side we have, first of all, the approach
from the standpoint of the personality, the self, and the metaphysical conception of the Absolute Self, of which the individual
self was regarded as a phase. The interest there lay in the metaphysical identification of the personaHty of the individual with
the Absolute Self of the whole universe. The later development
from this period of German Romantic idealism was found in the
physiological approach, in which the attempt was made to find
what answers to the stimulus in what takes place in the organism, especially in the central nervous system. An attempt
was made to set up a relationship between the stimulus and the
response of the organism to it. It was inevitable that the interest should be guided by that which could be actually isolated in
the study of the physiological process. A central nervous system
is a complex structure whose elements are so mixed that they
can be reached only by microscopic study, and the complexities
of the structure are so great that it was with very great difficulty
that any entrance at
all
was made into this field. It was inevitaon that which could be got
ble that investigators should fasten
Beyond
were left largely in the field of speculation and were thrown back on what introspection indicated
plus the hypothesis of nervous processes and structures that
would answer to what introspection revealed. The sense organs
hold
of.
that, they
themselves were, of course, there for study, analysis, and anatomization. These could be identified as having definite relation-
[472]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
ships to stimuli from without.
was possible
It
to
approach the
theory of color, for example, from this standpoint. The photochemical substances in the eye could be regarded as answering
to particular vibrations without.
When
back into the cenit was diffitral
cult to follow out the paths. Simple reflex automatisms or paths
could be found or were supposed to exist running through the
sense organs back to the muscles and glands, and it was possible
then to approach the central nervous system from the point of
view of these reflexes. The earlier assumption had regarded
these elements in the central nervous system as in some sense
answering to certain characteristics of the object. They even
pictured the nerve cells as that which would answer to a group
of ideas. The study of the central nervous system showed that
it consisted of a set of paths among the nerve cells. But you got
nothing but a set of paths. There is nothing static in the central
nervous system. You could not find anything there that anit
came
to following the nerve tracts
nervous system, the
field
was so
intricate that
swered to an idea of a static entity. One simply finds connections
between the end-organs and the muscles and glands in which the
nerve processes finally terminate a field of fibrils and nerve
centers which are intricate but remain in the paths. You had,
then, an approach from the point of view not of statics but of
dynamics, x^^physiological psychology inevitably emphasizes
wha t we
call
jtlie
"active side" of psychology, and this leads
back to the study of what goes on
in the experience of the indi-
vidual.
Now,
there
was no place within
this process into
which one
could insert a conscious process; the most that one could do was
to define a certain correlation. It
was
this interrelationship be-
tween what was going on in different nervous mechanisms and
what belonged
to the experience of the individual that interested
German psychologists particularly.
The interest on the French side was one which
the
field
of introspection
not neglected there.
first
of
all.
belongs to the
Physiological psychology was
Some very
[473]
valuable work was done in
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
France in the study of the phenomena of light. Many of the subwhich were dealt with by the psychology of the period were
examined in the laboratory by the French psychologists. But
their approach was from the standpoint of the individual rather
than from the standpoint of the physiological system. I have
already pointed out the positions of Royer-Collard and Cousin.
They came back to the immediate experience of knowledge as
/ that in the experience of the individual which is ultimate. I
have indicated the difficulties connected with that, but the posij
tion is characteristic of the French school. They held on to the
jects
experience of the individual.
When we
advance to the philosophical problem involved in
such an approach, we find it centers in the problem of the freedom of the will. Science assumes that everything that happens
can be explained because it must necessarily follow from previ-
The
ous events as an expression of natural law.
intelligibility
is dependent on our assumption that there are uniform laws that can be depended on. If nature were a chaos
of events that had no necessary connection with each other, it
would be impossible for science to unravel any of its mysteries.
Our knowledge would be confined to particular experiences,
sensations. Unless we can find connections between these,
knowledge is utterly impossible. The intelligibility of nature
presupposes natural laws. Science, in its faith in the intelligi-
of nature
bility of the world,
ings. It
is
this necessity
field
is
committed
to the necessity of its
and that
it
should sweep everything within this
of necessity, at least in so far as
course, took in the
must be
in
terms of
it
knows
human body; everything
it.
And
that, of
that happens there
accordance with natural law. There are laws for the
circulation of blood as for the
be known.
happen-
natural, therefore, that science should emphasize
It
this,
movement of
planets.
seems that what takes place
is
Each can
necessary. In
the succession of our states of consciousness as
The behavior
movements of the
they succeed each other seems to be necessary.
of human consciousness
is
as necessary as the
heavenly bodies.
[474]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
xni
Cousin's reaction against this assumption was a superficial
one.
He
undertook to check the statement of the necessity of
physical science against the active nature of the self and thus
which you could insert the freedom of the
of Renouvier is somewhat different in
character. He emphasized the hypothesis as it appears in science. Science approaches its field with postulates which, we
say, are based on a certain phase of experience. One of these assumptions is that the world is knowable; another is that the
world is in some sense necessary, that is, that we can predicate
events. Now, if we can predicate events, we must know the
reason why things are going to happen. But the hypotheses with
which we approach these problems are hypotheses which arise
in our own minds. The hypotheses are themselves in nature. We
must find that which answers to nature by the form in which it
appears in human thought, and what Renouvier insists on is
that in the alternatives which we have between hypotheses it is
possible for the human mind to enter as a determining factor.
There are alternative hypotheses, especially when we recognize
how small a part of the whole field of knowledge is really brought
within the range of our scientific study. We know very little
so little that we feel like a child on the seashore gathering pebbles while the ocean of truth lies beyond. Renouvier insisted
that in the selecting of hypotheses the human will plays its part;
the mind plays a part in the structure of knowledge.
tried to find a place in
individual.
The approach
This comes out
in
another form when we get to Boutroux.
was suggested by some who came back to
parallelism in a somewhat different expression than that of the
physiological psychologists. The physical and the mental side
of the world are parallel. That implies some common content.
The attempt was made to approach something that was both
physical and mental; and it laid that which was more fundamental in the mind. It was an attempt to go back from parallelism
to something that lies beyond it. This parallels Boutroux's
Still
a third answer
[475]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
we have here a reflection of the
have called your attention in Comte.
/'You remember Comte undertook to get away from metaphysical presuppositions. That which we know is what appears
it is phenomenal. Our knowledge of that is posiin experience
tive and direct. When we go back to a substance that lies back
of this, we are making metaphysical assumptions that cannot be
statement, and indicates that
positivism to which
Knowledge should confine itself to the recording
of experiences and the relationships which we find lying between
established.
them.
We cannot say
that there are certain physical bodies, en-
'Yities, substances; the most that
we can say
is
that there are cer-
which we have interpreted in this metaphysical
fashion. W^e cannot say that there is a force which acts with
necessity in the world; the most we can say is that there are certain uniformities in motion and change. We can determine this
but we cannot get back to any forces. When we speak of a force
as operating from an object, when we allow ourselves to use our
imaginations and think of the sun as pulling the earth, then we
get a sense of a necessity which impels the earth to move toward
tain experiences
on the other hand, we observe the movements of the
earth and sun with reference to each other and we find that these
movements agree with Newton's law that velocities are proportionate to masses and indirectly to the square of the distances,
we are noting certain uniformities in certain changes; and these
uniformities present a different experience from that which was
the sun.
If,
implied in the idea of a force.
It is Boutroux who undertakes to analyze what
is
involved in
this conception of knowing. You must remember the sort of
problem with which we are working: Does the necessity which
science implies as found in the world include also the action of
the human mind? You set up the mechanical universe and posit
the human body as a part of it. If you establish a strict parallelism between an organism and what takes place in the mind,
you seem to reduce the mental process to a mechanism. What
Boutroux undertakes to do is to analyze what this necessity means. He speaks of a metaphysical necessity in the first
[
476
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
which expresses itself in the formula of identity: A is A, or, in order to put it in a form which we feel to be
the most general, A is not-nothing. That is, given any certain
reality, in so far as we can identify anything with it we can affirm the same thing of that which is identified with it that we
can of the thing itself. If we can say anything about the nature
of substance, because of a given effect, then anything that we
can identify with substance can have the same thing attributed
to it. That is the nature of substance. If you say anything of it
in its relationship to an effect, then you can identify anything
which occurs with that which makes possible the same affirmation in regard to the relation between cause and effect. In so far
as you can get back to A as A, you can get back to cause as a
metaphysical necessity. But the necessity that is indicated here /
place, a necessity
does not go over to the characters of things.
We keep talking about the mechanical universe as a whole.
a whole. We have knowledge of
speak
of
them in a metaphysical sense.
various elements and
We say the table has a certain nature which was there before
and will be there after we are gone. It is substance that we identify in certain of our experiences. We can make the same affir-
But we have no knowledge of
mation about the universe that we make of the table. But we
never reach the universe as a whole. Our metaphysics necessarily is confined to those situations in which we identify the nature
of one thing with the nature of something else. If we could get
hold of the whole universe, we could get a statement which
would identify everything with the universe and give to it the
characters that belong in the universe. But we cannot do that.
Necessity from the metaphysical point of view is a necessity
that is affected by contingency in regard to the object about
which we make our affirmation. For one man a substance, an
organism, is certain states of consciousness. For another it is a
form of a phenomenal mind and does not apply to the noumenal
reality. For a third it is a phase in the logical process of development. It is a fact that there is a certain matter out there in the
world that is immediately given to us by knowledge and has a
[477]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
certain range of contingency; but
perience,
we
we go beyond our field of exwhich the positivists empha-
if
find the contingency
sized.
We
ourselves and of others
They
who have recorded their experiences.
B follows A in our own lives and
state simply the fact that
That
in theirs.
tingent and
then occurred,
we
They are the
come within the experience of
see that the laws of nature are necessary.
record of happenings that have
find A.
is all
we
We
the necessity that there
When A
contingent.
is
form,
strike a
if
you
like,
is:
con-
itself is
has occurred and
a habit of expecting
has
B when
match and expect a hght, but the
rela-
tionship between the striking of the match, as science distin-
guishes
it,
and the
light
is
certainly a contingent relation. Sup-
pose you can follow out in detail the process that goes on in the
explosion of the match: the waves of radiation that reach the
retina of the eye; the disintegration of the photochemical sub-
stances there; the effect in the central nervous organism follow-
movement from the nerve centers to the muscles
and back to the eye; and the resultant winking of the eye. There
we have a necessary succession of events. What about the light?
The light is not a chemical explosion; it is not the waves of radiaing that; the
tion; it
is
not the disintegration of photochemical substances in
the eye; nor
The
the excitement in the central nervous system.
is it
events that take place in nature are events which, as events,
are contingent.
They happen. No
scientist
can
sit
down and
evolve nature, from any ideas, any metaphysical entity.
He
can
and know
certain relationships which are there, but that which happens is
contingent. The uniformities which we discover are in themexperience objective nature and accurately record
selves contingent.
That
is,
it
the law of nature does not exclude
contingency any more than metaphysical laws or laws of logic
exclude it. In order that we may observe anything, something
must be happening. The whole point of the position in question
that it is the unexpected that happens, and there is much truth
in it. If a thing happens at all, it is in some way unexpected.
It is not entirely the sort of thing that we could prophesy. There
is
[478]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
always some element in that which takes place which is differN
ent from anything that we could anticipate a bit of novelty
attends the recurrence of even ordinary events. That is true as
far as our observation of it is concerned. It^has got to be something different from anything we could hold in the mind of ^^.^^^^j^^
w"ould~t3e unable to identify it. Our discovery of uniformity im-' /\
is
plies that
which
is
not uniform.
What Boutroux was
in_was_in reducing an event which
event to a certain identity with it.
is
different
interested
from another
To have
uniformity you must have it in that which is not
uniform; that which the genius of research is able to get out of
the world are uniformities in the midst of that which is not uniform.
You cannot have
into a world which
the one without the other.
is pluralistic, as far as
We
our knowledge
come
is
con-
cerned. We are overwhelmed with a multiplicity of things that
cannot be identified with each other, and then we set out on a
scientific approach and select something which we think may be
a clue to identities.
In order to select that element,
we must
ig-
we are going to consider a given pecuwe must not give attention to others; and if we have
good fortune when we follow the peculiarity out, we may disnore other characters. If
liarity,
W^e might have had some other clue. A
later scientist with better luck or greater penetration does find
some other clue that is more important and builds up his theory
cover
it
elsewhere.
on the basis of that clue. But a still greater genius may displace
him. The undertaking is to bring order into something which
is, in our immediate experience, wholly disordered. We must
get a method for doing this: following out clues which are involved and ignoring what we do not know. It has been pointed
out that ignoring is an essential part of knowledge. You can only
know a thing in so far as you can ignore something else. We
generally think of this in terms of getting rid of that which is
not essential to the thing. It was Boutroux who insisted that
scientific procedure is directed by the interest which we have in
the^process of knowledge and is dependent on the choices that
we make of the hypotheses that we form out of contingent
[479]
^y
THOUGHT
interests.
cause
it
want
appears
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
to leave that in
somewhat
in
ment of Poincare
your minds particularly, beform in the later state-
different
in regard to the
conventional character in
which mathematics is presented. Boutroux also turned particularly to mathematics to show in what sense his statement was
correct. A man in mathematics gets the highest degree of abstraction. In that subject you can consider things only in terms
of the content of their certain, definite relationships.
abstract everything
else.
You must
But the knowledge you get
is
at the
expense of everything else.
Boutroux, and the point of view which he represents in the
development of French philosophy, indicates the reaction to the
method and psychology of science. As
pointed out, science had
given a control over the world which went beyond that which
could be obtained by philosophy. The striking result of scientific
work,
its
research,
observation and experiment lay,
presenting that which
its results
by
other things, in
its
and the establishment of
is
among
recognized by
all
who
are competent
what the scientist is doing. That is the difference
between science and philosophy. One belongs to one philoto recognize
sophical school or another; he
realist.
One does
is
an ideahst, a pragmatist, a
not, on the other hand, belong to one scientific
school or another as far as the results of science are concerned,
if
these results are established
are consistent
is
and
logical,
by observation.
If the hypotheses
they are accepted even where there
a difference of opinion in regard to the value of any certain
one of them. They are taken as working hypotheses; and, in
so far as they work, they are accepted. There is, on the whole,
unanimity among the scientists in so far as results are concerned. Of course, in regard to the questions of accuracy of
observation, of the adequacy of absolute tests, and of the
interpretation of these results there are wide differences of
opinion. But in so far as one gets a hypothesis that is recognized as consistent in its structure, one that answers to the
problem which has given rise to it, and the hypothesis is supported by
tests, it is
accepted. It
[480]
must be accepted
to get that
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
unanimity which science presents but which is in conThe temperament of
the man himself, his background, may determine the philosophy that he adopts. There is, of course, rational development of it from his mere opinion. It is criticized by himself
and by others. One must accept certain types of criticism, but
in the end one does take the point of view which answers to the
personality, the interest, the background, of the man himself in
his philosophic creed. Thus, science has stood out in contrast
with philosophy in certain respects. It has an authority which
philosophy does not have. During the medieval period philossort of
trast with the attitude of philosophers.
ophy expressed the attitude of the authoritative church, with its
affirmation of divine inspiration; and hence it was able to speak
for science. But with the appearance of experimental science you
have an authority which
I
wish to
call
is
different
from that of philosophy.
that to your attention in order to indicate the
attitude which philosophy took. It
felt that it had to recognize
and the relationship of science to philosophic doctrine
became, in one way or another, the really important problem
of all nineteenth-century thought. The Romantic idealists un-
science;
itself. They did not
method in terms of the
dialectic. Ifjhey had succeeded, then there would have been
a philosophy of science which should have been more or less
'in harmony with both science and philosophy. The point of
conflict between science and philosophy in England was the
epistemological question. Science tells us what we know. And
what the epistemological school did was to criticize knowing as
dertook to bring science within philosophy
succeed, but they stated the scientific
such
not the
result of science, but the process
does knowing amount to; what does
it tell
us?
knowing.
What
The Germans,
of
course, recognized this problem; but their interest lay in the
carrying-out of science, particularly along the lines of physiol-
ogy and the relationships between the organism and states of
consciousness. There was an interest in finding that interrelationship through the development of psychophysics.
Fechner thought that he had found a mathematical relation[481]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
ship which could be set
up between the
intensity of the stimuli
and that of the responses. He found out that you had to inby a certain percentage of itself in order to
crease a stimulus
produce a difference in the response or in the sensation itself.
If you were to take up a weight, for example, you would have to
add a certain percentage, a third, of the weight to itself before
you would recognize that you had a heavier weight in your hand.
Similarly, a light would have to be increased by a tenth of itself.
Fechner went on the assumption that these just-perceptible differences were elements in sensation which were equal to each
other. The assumption then would be that sensation is made up
out of elements which appear in just-perceptible differences. It
is a composite. You can break it up so that you have elements
which are just perceptibly different. If that is true, you can say
that you can set up a mathematical relationship between the
stimulus and the sensation. You add a certain percentage of the
stimulus to
itself in
order to get a just-perceptible difference. If
you work that out, what you get is a logarithmic equation.
This seemed to be an open door for the mathematical analysis of so-called "consciousness." It seems possible, by means
of mathematical analysis, to get back to ultimate elements
in sensation itself. Fechner designated this as the field of psychophysics.
You
can see at once that there are all sorts of assumptions
For example, in the instances to which I have referred, it
is assumed that the sensation can be broken up into just-perceptible differences, and that a difference in one case is equal to
that in another. These assumptions are without support. Parhere.
ticularly, the theory runs frankly against the
data of experi-
made up
ence. One's sensation of weight
is
number. You can Hft a
weights and, after that, can see,
we
think, that
series of
a unit;
some of them would
it is
not
feel equal.
Suppose we have
a pound weight. That would be a guess which does not
that the sensation you have
when you
lift
the
of a
mean
pound weight
is
can be divided into, twelve or sixteen different parts.
The experience, the unitary experience, cannot be divided as the
equal
to,
[482]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
object itself can be divided.
And
then, of course, there
question of just where the equation which
applied.
What you
get
is
made
use of
is
the
to be
the response of the individual which
indicates that he feels that this weight
Now, what has happened?
is
is
heavier than another.
is
A stimulus has come in,
has traveled
around through the central nervous system, and has come out
in the process of feeling. That represents a very intricate pathway in the central nervous system. Does the equation represent
a relationship between the increase in the stimulus and the response of the nervous system.'' Have you a relationship there
between the stimuli and consciousness, between the stimuli and
the response in the central nervous system? This is a question
which you see^ when you once get over the sense of triumph at
having gotten mathematics into the field of consciousness involves assumptions that run counter to the actual data of
experience. And, on the other hand, you have got the relationship which may apply to the organism in its response instead of the relationship between consciousness and the stimu-
lus.
So, the field of psychophysics lost
its
interest rather short-
There has been a revival of it at the present time from another standpoint, however. I brought it up as an illustration of
the type of interest that was dominant in Germany
the interest in the study of our consciousness and experience through the
study of the organism as science deals with it. That is where the
interest fastened in Germany,
ly.
XIV
Now,
in
France you have the interest
in the relationship of
the individual as an individual, as a personality, to science.
What
is
the bearing of the scientific doctrine on the experience
of the individual as a personality?
that
is
What
science gives
seemingly independent of ourselves
at
is
a world
least as far as sci-
it. And, as I have indicated, Boutroux says it has
necessity the necessity which science predicates in its statements, if not one of a metaphysical character. The scientist qua
scientist does not state that the changes must take place in the
ence presents
[483]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
order in which he thinks they
will.
He has not
got back to a nec-
essary structure of the universe which can be dealt with.
have
already said several times that the necessity which science
synonymous with the intelligibility of
in which you can know the world is in
terms of uniformity. It is only in so far as you can get a law
that you can get that which is uniform, that you can get that
which can be known. Science does not state that it has discovered laws which are themselves fixed and certain. Its statements are always hypothetical. If the relationship between the
postulates
is
the world.
The only way
practically
mass, distances, and velocities of bodies
is
such as stated in
Newton's law, then such and such results must be true. If the
law of the pressure of gases is as it has been worked out, then
such and such results must follow. That is where the necessity
It is a necessity of a hypothetical presupposition.
lies.
hy-
which
has met the test of observation. That is why we can go ahead
on the basis of it. But science does not maintain that those hypotheses are necessary. It maintains, as I have said, that they
are legitimate solutions for the problems which people have met
and that they have been tested in the sense that action can continue on the basis of them. We can work out such things as
stresses and strains, can determine when motions will occur.
We do not hesitate to make these statements with the recognipothetical proposition
tion that there
may
Now,
if
ly follows that such
pothesis
time.
is
a solution of certain problems
be some more satisfactory statement. But,
as far as the situation
hypothesis.
is
is
given,
we do
we
are justified in accepting this
use a certain hypothesis,
and such
it
correct, the eclipse will take place at such
That
is
necessari-
results will be found. If the hy-
and such a
the scientific necessity.
Boutroux approached the question from the point of view of
a metaphysical necessity and asked what the justification for
this
metaphysical necessity
is.
He
pointed out that there are
always contingencies even in the metaphysical state. I think
see that the contingent to which Boutroux referred is
just that which I have pointed out in the hypothetical nature
we can
[484]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
of the scientist's judgment.
After A,
contingent, never dogmatic.
On
B must
This
is
the contrary, the scientist
is
follow.
looking for events which will lead him to another problem.
We
can regard Newton's statement as an approximation and Ein-
more accurate. Newton was the last person to maintain that there was absolute assurance in regard to the law of
gravitation. He used the unfortunate expression that he had not
used hypotheses. What he was referring to were the rather
fantastic assumptions which the scientists of the time were making. They went beyond a possibility of testing. But his statement of the law was definitely a hypothesis. His hypothesis appeared in this form: he knew what the velocity of a falling body
is near the surface of the earth; he had a rough estimate on the
basis of which he could determine the distance of the moon, and
stein's as
how much
the moon falls toward the earth
were not for the attraction of the earth, the
moon would go off on a tangent; he could figure out how much
the moon was drawn toward the earth during a second; if you
take this relation in terms of the inverse square, then the distance the moon falls in a second, its velocity, would have a definite value; the moon should fall only 1/3,600 as rapidly as a
body on the surface of the earth. That was the hypothesis which
Newton set up, and he figured out on that basis what the velocity of the moon was and then saw that it was a certain fraction
he could figure out
during a second;
if it
of the velocity of a body falling near the surface of the earth.
That
is
thinking in a
circle,
and the
entirely satisfactory; but he got a
ment of
first
calculation
was not
more accurate measure-
the attraction of the earth and found that
it
agreed
exactly.
There you get the test of a hypothesis. You can continue to
act on the assumption that the body is continually falling
toward the earth with a velocity which is determined by this
law. There is nothing that we now know that interferes with
harmony with it. If that
then we can go on and state what must follow. That
that assumption. All the facts are in
is
the law,
is
the necessity that science can appeal
[485]
to.
If this
law holds,
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
must be such and such a result. If this law holds,
there is a necessity which carries with it contingency. When
Boutroux was criticizing the necessity of the law from the metaphysical standpoint, he was implying that the scientist was
making a metaphysical assumption. Science, of course, always
works with errors of observation; and science also works with
reference to a method of limits. It does not get back to exact
there there
agreements, exact positions, exact congruence. What it does do,
however, is to get a position which approximates these. The
limit is never reached. But we get a series of which one can
say: If the limit were reached, then such and such a thing
would be true; and if that is true, such and such things must be
true
if
we approximate
it.
We
have, then, a method of approxi-
mation which enables us to state what the situation will be
when you get there. But there is an "if" there, and the whole
scientific method has this postulate behind it. Boutroux's assumption does not negate that. We cannot get back to the noumenal reality of the universe. Our knowledge is all relative
knowledge. The space and time which are the basis for geometry and mechanics are relative to our own observations. All
our observations have that sort of relativity behind them. What
we find is a correlation between that which is given in experience and what we assume there as outside.
The
possibility of getting such correlation
in a field
is
found, of course,
of thought in which mathematics and logic are domi-
Mathematics is a field of exact thought and analysis
which has proved powerful. It has back of it certain definitions,
certain presuppositions, certain postulates. Given these, its renant.
sults are necessary results.
allel lines^
Geometry has a postulate of
par-
that through a point outside of a line only one line
can be drawn that
will
be parallel to
it.
Now
you can
set
up
another postulate, that through a point an indefinite number of
lines can be drawn that are parallel to it, and you can construct
a
geometry on
this basis.
And
as a piece of logic, the latter
just as sound a system as Euclidean geometry.
still
is
You can make
other suppositions: that more than one line or a certain
[486]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
number of
lines
lines can be drawn through such a point, or that no
can be drawn through it. You are at liberty to make any
assumption on the basis of which you can build up a consistent
geometry. If we say Euclidean geometry fits the experience we
have of things, there is a great question as to how far it can be
applied. Our measurements indicate that our local world is Euclidean. But we have never made any exact measurements
which we tried to carry out to sufficient length to determine
whether it is true that space is Euclidean. It is possible that our
world is non-Euclidean. The assumption of Einstein is that it is
non-Euclidean. We cannot prove that it is or that it is not. If
we set up the assumption of its being Euclidean, then necessary
results follow. Suppose you have a geometry which is non-Euclidean and one that is Euclidean. Which one is to be adopted?
You will adopt the one that is most convenient!
Here you get the position of Poincare, which is a development
of Boutroux's statement, that our scientific theory and our
mathematical theory are the most convenient that we can get.
In the first place, we must abandon the space of immediate observation, the space in which we move up and down and right
and left. What is real space? No one can tell. You can work
out a geometry of one sort, or an infinite number of others,
which could be applied to our experience, each having various
of these different assumptions as to what the structure of the
world is. Poincare says we should adopt that which is most
convenient. It
is
like getting
persons of different races together
and saying that the proceedings
You
shall be in a certain language.
can find out the number of persons
who speak
the language
most generally known, and you take that language as the
medium of the gathering. In what language shall we express our
observation of the world, Euclidean or non-Euclidean, or some
other? That which is the most convenient! That is Poincare's
position. He said that our scientific theories are, after all, compromises. We never get back to the exact elements that science
presupposes. There is always considerable leeway in the hypothesis, but the scientist proceeds anyway. We have never had
that
is
[487I
THOUGHT
knowledge of
IN
reality.
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
We
have a compromise, a working com-
promise.
But Boutroux did not go to the point of saying that statements which science makes are simply conventionalisms. That
is the statement that Poincare makes later. The former considered himself a rationalist.
He
said
we can
find out
about the
world so that we can get an agreement between the world as it
is and the scientific statement we make. We can make a scientific
statement that comes pretty close to the statement of the
Thus we can feel that we know something
about reality. That was the position which Boutroux retained:
we should believe that knowledge reveals something of the
world. But he refused to recognize what he considered the danature of things.
tum
of science in regard to the necessity of a scientific state-
ment. As
have
in the scientist's
He was
tried to point out, he was implying a necessity
statement which the scientist does not claim.
judgments are,
hypotheses and that the
failing to recognize that all scientific
from the point of view of the scientist,
is only the necessity that you get in a hypothetical syllogism. If A is B, then C is D. However, A is B; so C is D. The
scientist's laws are always of that form. If the square of the distances gives such and such a result, then a certain movement of
the moon will be necessary if its motion conforms to the hynecessity
pothesis of universal gravitation.
Boutroux represents a movement which comes to be more
prominent in French philosophy, a movement toward the irrationality of our experience. He turned it in this direction,
gave it an anti-intellectuahst current. What he reached was the
statement that science in its rational statement seems to get a
necessary, ordered result which it does not really get. He criticizes what he considered to be the finding of science from the
point of view of its own place. His interest in it was in showing
that science is not justified supposing it makes that claim in
saying that the unity of the individual is determined, that he
has no free will, no spontaneity. The freedom of the vv^ill is a
question. We do not know that the world is such a necessary tex-
[488]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
ture of events that everything that takes place
by what has occurred
the world
before.
He
is
is
determined
interested in showing that
not such a necessary texture of events that everyis caused by what preceded it. He undertakes to show this by the analysis of the process of science itself,
is
thing that takes place
and by his assumption that what science presents is a sort of
compromise. Boutroux comes to a definite conclusion that the
realistic statement of science, as he interprets it, claims far
more than it can establish.
That
and it is
by Bergson. Both Poincare and Bergson represent
a movement which developed along that line. In this, Poincare was the scientist and Bergson the philosopher.
As I have already said, the principal figure in the movement
in the tendency which introduced the element of irrationality in
French thought is Boutroux, who criticized the conception of
necessity as this appears in scientific doctrine and in scientific
method. His theme was the presence of contingency in both the
doctrine and the method of science. From the metaphysical
is
a step in the direction of anti-intellectualism,
carried on
standpoint he insisted that each postulate of science left the
door open to contingencies. The axioms and postulates of
mathematics and the sciences could not be reduced to identity;
they could not be developed from the proposition that A is A.
The
universe could not be presented as necessary.
Therefore,
the findings of science are contingent.
From
the standpoint of method, science proceeds inductively,
discovering the laws which in their formulation are presented
But there formulations never exactly accord with
The point that Boutroux laid emphasis on was that the form of the law is one which
is made by the mind. But this universal and necessary form
does not exactly state what is presented in experience. Furthermore, the mind selects that form which seems to be the most
as necessary.
the findings of observation and experiment.
From Boutroux's
made between the demand
satisfactory for the given situation.
point,
mind
a compromise
for necessary
is
standof the
laws and the actual data as they come
[489]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
field of observation in science. This term "compromise" was the one that he used. There is an element of contingency here not only from the standpoint of the sort of data
that comes within the range of science but also from the point
of view of the mind itself in the selection that it makes of
the hypothesis it uses. In the end, however, Boutroux conceived the universe as rational. He was not himself anti-intellectualistic; he did not come back to an irrational element. But,
on the other hand, he did not believe that science was able to
demonstrate a necessary rational order, that room was always
open for the expression of spontaneity on the part of the individual. These were the principal points in Boutroux's statement. As you see, this study of science is made from the standpoint of contingency, with a view to leaving the door open to the
freedom of the will, to the expression of the individual as an individual. That was the problem that more or less obsessed the
French philosophic mind during the period under consideration.
It has before it the seeming mechanical order of the universe
which mathematical science presented and within which, at
least in its formulation, everything that takes place is necessarily determined by that which has gone before. In such a universe there seems to be no room for the spontaneous individual,
for the spontaneous mind, for our freedom or ability to determine our own conduct. This seems to be an illusion.
within the
XV
The next
figure of
importance
in this
movement
is
Poincare,
the author of Science and Hypothesis and other significant works,
and a cousin, by the way, of the one-time premier of France.
He was an eminent mathematician and physicist. He was particularly important in the development of Maxwell's theory of
electricity. He also gave a very acute and profound study of
the meaning of scientific method. Born in the year of Comte's
death, he parallels Russell and Whitehead in England. He
belonged not only to the group of men we have considered but
to these
men who
are our contemporaries.
[490]
He
is
a connect-
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
ing link between them.
He
took up the mathematical method as
such and showed that that method
is not one of deduction. So
one has simply the principle of identity that A is equal
to A
as the principle of reasoning, no advance can be made.
Nothing more can be found in the world than is presented in the
premises. He sees, however, that advances have appeared in
mathematical theory and asks what their source is. So far as
arithmetic and algebra are concerned, he brings them back to a
principle of mathematics which finds its expression in the number series, namely, the proof that anything true of n will also be
true of w I, and one goes on back until one reaches the position
of unity itself. In such a situation the mind, by immediate intuition, realizes what the law of the number series is. That im-
far as
mediate intuition is not a mere reduction to identity. It does
not come back to the principle that A is equal to A. It is a grasping by the mind of a process which, in its recurrence, exhibits
certain necessary laws. In the field of geometry we have the
fundamental assumptions of Euclidean geometry in the axioms,
These Poincare considers from the point
of view of non-Euclidean geometry. The former geometry develops on the Euclidean axiom that only one line can be drawn
through a point outside a hne parallel to that line. What Poincare points out is that we have here certain more or less arbitrary definitions. He discusses the space of our perception with
its dimensions, its structure, and its position in relation to the
space of mathematics and geometry; and he finds that the latter space is, in some sense, created by the geometrist.
I pointed out that it is perfectly possible to create other geompostulates, definitions.
which are non-Euclidean, geometries of what we may call
"curved spaces." For example, we speak of a solid as the form
of an infinite number of planes. We start from a line and reach
the plane as an infinite number of lines; start with the plane and
reach solids by an infinite number of planes. Now, suppose
those planes, instead of being level, were bent, were slightly
curved. Suppose the universe were made out of space that had
a coefficient of curvature. The point can be made perhaps a
etries
[491I
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
more concrete by the change which came about in navigawhen it was recognized that the surface of the earth was
curved. It came to be realized that the shortest distance bet\^en two points is not a direct line. Now, suppose that is true
little
tion
not only of the surface of the earth but that the whole of space
has a slight curvature. Then the axiom of Euclid about the
would not be true. Such a space as that would require a geometry built on a principle different from that of
Euclid. Such a geometry might be developed, and for every
proposition in that geometry you could find a proposition in the
Euclidean geometry, and vice versa. You could go on the assumption that you had a curved space with a certain coefficient
of curvature, and build your geometry on that basis, and still
you could utilize the Euclidean position as a particular instance. In other words, it is a matter of convenience whether
we adopt one geometry or another. The reason for adopting the
Euclidean geometry is that it has been found more convenient.
And Poincare said, suppose we should find that our space had
some such curvature, that lines which are parallel tend to meet
at a distant point. We would then probably find it more convenient to go on the assumption that there was an error in our
calculation than to change our system of geometry. It would
likely be that we would retain EucHdean geometry even in a
non-Euclidean world because it would be the most convenient.
In other words, our mathematical systems are conventional.
parallel lines
It is possible that people should live in a world not of solids
but of fluids. Suppose one did live in a world of fluids. Then
the form of this desk, as we conceive of it, when it had passed
out through the fluid would be distorted. Or, take another
il-
Let us assume that, as we
move from a center in any direction, all dimensions and positions are proportionately decreased. This table, for example,
would have a certain definite volume, a certain definite length.
Now, if it moves away from this point, its dimensions would
be altered proportionately. But not only would the dimensions of the table change, but those of the measuring-rods would
lustration
that Poincare used.
[492]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
also change.
Not only
would
same symmetry. The
that, but persons
smaller while retaining the
also
become
retina of the
much smaller. Just as a body shrinks
every object would become proportionately less
dimensions. You can see that in such a world as that
eye would be just so
in the cold,
in all its
there
would be no way of discovering
this
change, because
the individuals and the units of measurement would change proportionately.
What we have
for stating the events
about
us.
we could
in science is a satisfactory
and structure of things
language
as they take place
Now, we could have another language; and
if
we
did,
express the relationship which exists in this world in
one language or another. The system that is used is a conventional one. It comes back to the process of the mind of the individual. The whole mathematical system, then, is a conventional system. It does not give us a picture of the world as it is,
but it does pick out certain relationships in it. And it states
these relationships in terms of such convenient systems as that
to which I have referred. Thus, the mechanical system of the
universe, instead of being a structure lying outside of us in which
we are helpless elements, is really a creation which serves to
enable us to pick out those aspects that seem to be the important or essential features of the world and their relationships.
Here we have, as you see, a development of the conception of
a compromise between the mind and the world which Boutroux
had brought forward. Poincare was not skeptical. He did not
believe that it was impossible to know. What he was doing was
reconstructing what he considered to be the hmits, the actual
content, of our knowledge. We have this same conception carried further among the neo-realists, like Russell, who assumes
that the only knowledge that we have of a world outside of
ourselves is of its logical pattern, and he thinks that there is a
relationship between that pattern and the pattern of our
thought. You have a certain pattern present in Euclidean geometry. You have another picture arising out of our immediate
sense perception. You have still another pattern in the nonEuclidean geometry. Suppose there were creatures that lived in
[493]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
two dimensions only, and suppose they developed a geometry in
They have only those dimensions and move in
that plane. Now, suppose there is a hump in that plane. These
beings will be unable to state it in terms of dimensions of things.
What they would find is that, as they approached the hump, in
order to move around it in the shortest time they would have to
make a curve. They might express that in different ways. They
might assume that there was some sort of a force in the back of
what we could call the center of this hump which drove them
away. You would get the same sort of a picture if you were in a
balloon and, looking down, saw people moving with lanterns
where you could not see the contour of the earth. It would all
be a plane. But you would see forms with lanterns going over
the side of a mountain and notice that, when they got to a certain point, they went off in a curve instead of a straight line.
You would have two different ways of stating that. If you could
get the third dimension, you could state it in terms of this dimension or you could state it in terms of a force. How would
you express it if you were sailing over the ocean and did not
know that the surface was curved and found that you got to a
certain point by taking a longer path? You could conceive of
some repulsive power drawing you away when you take one
way rather than another. You would have different ways of
explaining your course.
So you can have different geometries. One geometry, the Euclidean, has proved to be the simpler way of stating our experithat dimension.
ence of spatial relations.
You
could state
it
in other terms. In
the Einsteinian doctrine you get a particular statement which
works out
pler
way
in a
non-Euclidean geometry. That
of stating
it.
That may come
may
be the sim-
to be accepted.
It is the
position in which one sees certain relationships which exist be-
tween certain events, something that is happening out there;
and you presume the relationship between that and the patterns
that you have in your own mind. You cannot get hold of those
events out there, but you find a certain structure in them. The
most striking illustration of that is found in the relativity doc[494]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
trine.
You
can get a statement
in
terms of which you get what
takes place in one space, then in terms of that which takes
place in another. Now there is a certain interpenetration be-
tween events in your theory which can be given a definite statement, and that statement can be translated into any space.
From such a standpoint you can recognize that your mathematical theory is only a link for bringing out relationships where you
do not have the things which have these interrelationships. And
you can get the correlation between that pattern and the patyour mind. From the biological point of
all convenient. That is, they are definitely selected with reference to the uses to which one is to put
them. They are selected for the sake of their convenience. That
is what we mean by "convenience." But there are certain necessary relations. Thus, Poincare was not skeptical. He was, as it
were, simply loosening the mathematical theory of the world
tern that
you have
in
view, these patterns were
was presented by the physical
scien-
had thought that the world was a mechanical
struc-
from the world
itself, as it
tist.
The
latter
ture of masses,
of bits of energy, in
motion.
He
thought of
it
as a great machine that ran in accordance with necessary law.
Poincare and the others were loosening this necessary structure
from the world itself and lodging it in the mind. We can get a
connection, a correlation, of the relations between the charac-
out there and those in your mind; but we have no such
universe actually present in experience. We have only a way of
ters
getting hold of certain characters which are there.
Do
these
characters reveal the actual structure of reality? In the matter
movement Poincare came back to a certain intuition
movement in dealing with the recurrence of the number
of
Does that
series.
intuition reveal the actual relationship of events to
each other?
He
believed
The tendency
mind.
of the
This
is
here
is
it
did.
to assimilate the nature of things to the
a tendency toward a certain type of idealism.
But we have a fundamental break between the mind, on the one
side, and what we call "matter," on the other. It involves the
[495]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
and quality. Our experience tends
Our mathematical techtechnique, picks out that which is quantita-
distinction between quantity
to pick out that
which
nique, our scientific
is
quaUtative.
tive. So, we speak of color in nature as a certain motion, of
something with definite vibrations. We measure the world and
deal with it as a measurable quantity, but no measurement gives
us a control over it. The color, sound, taste, odor the quantend to be put in the mind. That bifurtities of the world
cation of the world has been the most convenient to use. As
Poincare pointed out, it is a great convenience to have these
statements; but the only thing
we
get hold of
is
certain defi-
nite relations in the world, and those relations from Poincare's
standpoint, as stated in terms of geometry, are, in a certain
sense, a creation. What is the relationship of those statements to
reality itself? Poincare denied that the logic and metaphysics of
identity could reveal to us the world as it existed, but he did
speak of an intuition which could see through to certain essential
one in which
relations. We want a world made up of events
things have definite lengths, can be definitely measured one in
which objects can be put into geometric relations with each
other, have perfectly definite successions, certain velocities, certain accelerations.
That
is
the sort of world
we want
so that
we
can control it. In order to get such a world, we must abstract
from our experience as it takes place immediately. This table is
colored; it has a feel; it is warm; it is smooth. We cannot state
its characters in these terms; but we can state them in terms of a
geometry, in terms of a dynamics. We can utilize the materials
of nature for this or that or the other thing, and by giving a scientific
statement we can get control of reahty. But to do that
this conventional framework of ours into the world.
we must put
XVI
We have in
these conceptions, which follow from
Comte up
Poincare, the setting for the philosophy of Bergson. There
is
to
one
important addition. The thought of Boutroux and Poincare was
occupied with mathematical physics. The problems of biology
[496]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
were only incidental
to their discussions.
life
was assumed that
It
terms of the inanimate world;
life-processes could be stated in
could be dealt with in terms of chemistry and physics. This
position could not be proved, but
it
was a legitimate assumption
that the whole world could be included in such a mechanical
The
statement.
justification for that
what Boutroux and
is
Poincare were discussing.
Bergson starts with the science of biology, particularly the
theory of evolution.
He
is
a true French philosopher in that his
Time and Free Will
he starts off with the assumption that the universe and the field
of our experience are fields of what he calls "imagination."
method
They
is
a psychological one. In his book
are the impressions that belong to a
organized mind.
it
is
You
can see this
is
an
self,
idealistic
mind, an
to a
statement; yet,
not romantic, spiritual idealism, nor yet the subjective
idealism of Berkeley. Bergson comes back to experience as he
finds
it;
he recognizes the table as an experience that can be
stated in terms either of physics or of psychology.
chooses the psychological statement of it.
jects in the mind.
They can be
or nature, as you like.
mind
or not
is
mind
in the
but are the same in both cases. There
He does
is
And
he
not lodge ob-
or out of the
mind
an identity of structure,
The question whether they
are in the
a question that does not necessarily arise. Sup-
have given before of the face of a
person that one sees and mistakes for an acquaintance. When
one approaches the individual, he sees that he has made a mistake. In a certain sense he takes off the face that he sees and
considers that it is a different individual. He has put something
pose one takes the illustration
the
face, form,
image, of his friend
he approaches, he sees that
that he saw?
Was
it
it
on
does not
fit.
out there, or was
it
and when
Where was that image
in the mind? W^hat is
this person;
the meaning of any such question as that?
We may
say the
image could not be there, for, when we come to study it, it is
different and what was seen was only a mental image, and a
mental image must be in a mind. But, for the purpose of ex[497]
THOUGHT
IN
perience the image
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
out there. That
is
is
a phase of experience
of which French philosophy never lost hold.
Bergson presents himself at this point. His is a different approach from that which we have indicated was being made in
Germany. The approach in Germany was to take the physiological
organism over into the
field
of psychology.
It states
what
corresponds to states of consciousness in terms of what goes on
And this psychology which wants to be sciensimply gets a parallelism between these two. As far as it
can, it subordinates the mental to the physical, or rather the
psychical to the physiological. If it can only get hold of what
goes on in the central nervous system, the self, then it will have
in the organism.
tific
data of a
scientific sort
more uncertain
field
and
will
of the inner
be able to interpret this
life.
natural science into the psychical
It goes
self.
much
from the ground of
Bergson reversed
this
procedure. His approach was from the psychical side, and he at-
tempted
to deal with the physical
He
standpoint.
ley did.
tal
does not, however, use the distinction as Berke-
Berkeley wiped out the distinction between the men-
and physical and
association of ideas.
cal, school
looks at
and physiological from that
it
tried to state the
The German,
problem
in
terms of
or physiological-psychologi-
does not, of course, wipe out the psychical; but
from the point of view of the physiological. That
the psychical tends to
it
is,
become phenomenal, merely a psychical
shadow which accompanies certain physiological happenings.
That which is given, the whole process, is found in the organism. Only a part of this reveals itself in consciousness which
flares up here and there. If we want to understand states of
consciousness, we must go over into the field of physiological
psychology. That is the attitude which the scientific psychologists took,
although a philosopher could interpret that attitude
in different fashions.
manding an
But the psychologists
as such
were de-
attitude in which they interpreted the psychical in
terms of the physical. They did not, however, say that consciousness
is
a secretion of the brain as the bile
[498]
is
a secretion of
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
the liver.
They had
got beyond that form of crude materialism
which belonged to the 1840's.
The position of Bergson is that the fundamental reality is
given in mental experience, and that the statement of what we
call physical and physiological must be interpreted in terms of
the psychical, of the mental.
cal world, as science deals
what goes on
He
with
it,
undertakes to treat the physias a
phenomenal statement of
There is a distinction
is a distinction which is
in the psychological world.
between knowledge and the real. It
is one which is undertaken in the interest of conduct, for the sake of utihty. If one does not undertake to set up
the experienced world as the ultimate metaphysical reality, there
is no criticism to be made of our statement of it in such terms.
But the content of reality is that which is revealed within, in
that which is in some sense psychical. We have taken the realities that go on in our inner experience and have fixed them so
that we can control them, but we must not assume that the
legitimate. It
petrification of these experiences
The
first
is
a living, pulsing reality.
question, of course, that would be put
up
to such a
How
do you know that this is the approach to
ultimate reality? Science knows a world in so far as it can measure it, in so far as it can find laws of uniformity that are stated
in terms of the relationship of things in space and time
and
its statement in terms of time is, after all, spatial. If you ask
the length of time that it takes to walk through the park, the
answer is so many minutes. What is that? It is the representation of a certain distance on the face of your watch. If you are
going to put the time that science deals with in measurable
terms, you must put it in spatial terms. How can you get the
different inner realities if what your science deals with is stated
in terms of an outer physical world? It is in the former that
you get to exact measurements, to ultimate realities. But how
do you approach that inner world in which you say the outer is
a distinct phenomena? What Bergson does is to set up a metaphysical method. He has rejected the scientific formula. He regards it as academic. He calls for an immediate return to inner
philosophy
is:
[499]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
experience, a return to that inner experience which does not take
place in terms of
what he
calls
"concepts."
The
field
of distinc-
Bergson special fields. And he places
tions and
in the former not only what the measuring-rod deals with but
also the whole of scientific technique. The only thing he can
measure is something that he can put a measuring-rod on. You
have the falling grains of sand in the hourglass, the drops of
water in a water clock, the slow melting-away of the candle, the
of reality are for
swinging of the pendulum of a clock.
All these are spatial
events, and the only time that science deals with
is a time that
can be petrified in such spatial form, that is, where one can apply measurement. Motion, to be measured, must be stopped.
You measure a motion, and what you get is a simultaneity at
one end of the hne and a simultaneity at the other. You get the
point on your watch at which the hand of your watch stands
when the runner starts; and when he stops, you may reduce
that and get back to an infinitesimal bit. If you are measuring
in terms of space, your motion must be put in a spatial container. You have to stop your motion in order to measure it.
As far as science deals with processes, then, it must petrify
them in spatial forms.
Our concepts, says Bergson, have the same
What
they do
is
ceptualization breaks
to concept B.
characteristic.
to divide things off into discontinuities.
up processes and simply
Con-
relates concept
It analyzes the living object into certain
quan-
and puts all these together; but it carefully distinguishes
one from the other. It is this, that, and the other thing; and
they must all be held separately. You take a reality to pieces
and can get your conceptual view of what its nature is. It
is made up of a set of situations which you describe in terms
of movement, but a whole set of separate concepts would be
required to define the thing. It is not as simple for Bergson to
make his conceptual world spatial as it is for him to make his
temporal world spatial. But he undertakes to show that our
tities,
conceptual analysis inevitably stops the living process. It does
not give the reality of something that
[500]
is
going on. If you are to
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
know
it
all this, know reality in terms of concepts, you must get
by the approach of intuition, by a sudden turning-back to the
inner
life,
grasping
it
in its reality.
Bergson distinguishes sharp-
ly between that reality and the spatial, conceptual statement
which one finds of it. In that world of change, of process, of
spontaneity, Bergson is able to preserve freedom. The other
statement is that which science makes in concepts, in measurement. The former is the statement which you get in Bergson's
volume translated under the title of Time and Free Will.
The ideal of a scientific statement is that you get in an equation the assurance of a reality of such sort that it makes no difthere is no accident in it. Everything
ference what happens
must happen according to that which has taken place. That is
the scientific ideal of accuracy. That
undertakes to obtain.
with
it
is
the picture that science
But, Bergson says, that does not carry
the nature of duration, of what
is
happening. Under such
You would have absomonotony, no way of distinguishing one moment from
circumstances, happening would cease.
lute
another.
The
scientist tries to
wipe out
all
such distinctions.
Bergson turns to the inner life for the expression of this other
type of succession a type of succession in which it is always
the unexpected that happens, in which it is that which is universal that makes us aware of succession, of duration. You cannot recognize duration, happening, experience, except in that
which is changing. There must be change in order that there
may be awareness of what is going on. Duration, then, is
something that lies in our immediate experience. But duration
is not found in the world as science presents it, that is, not as
mechanical science has presented it. Here you do not find that
which is characteristic of this inner experience. It is the state-
ment of
Bergson faces, and it is more or less
original with him. To Bergson there is for the scientist nothing
but a succession of separate, instantaneous moments, one of
which replaces another. Now that is not duration. What does
this situation that
characterize duration
and on
is
a passage from the past into the present,
into the future.
Something
is
always taking place
in
THOUGHT
which there
experience.
may
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
some past and some future. This is true of every
Whether that is to be called "interpenetration"
is
be a question, but that
is
the
way
in
which Bergson pre-
past is actually crowding into the future. The
which we can get that duration is by a sort of intuition, a sudden turning on one's self, grasping experience as it is
going on. But, if you try to state it by means of analysis, especially in terms of the external world, you kill it. In such a statement you have to anatomize it. You can dissect it, but then you
no longer have a living process there.
It is this attitude of Bergson which makes him an antiintellectualist. Of course, Bergson is not an anti-intellectualist
in the sense that he denied intelligence of a sort, but he says it
has a particular function. From that standpoint Bergson may
sents
only
The
it.
way
in
be called pragmatic.
is
The
function of conceptional thinking
action. It presents a world in terms of
mechanisms.
It is a
mechanical thing and gives the mechanism by means of which
we can control the content of experience. Man is a tool-making
animal.
He works by
tools;
and
his concepts are tools, just as
machines are. They are legitimate for their purpose. But
the purpose is not that of revealing ultimate reahty. If you
want to get ultimate reality, turn within, where you have experience itself. Bergson has the same difficulty in terms of philosophy and metaphysics as do the mystics. You get intuitions
only in a glimpse that can be recognized now and then, and you
cannot determine whether or not you are going to get them.
In the very nature of the case there can be no conceptual theory
of intuition. That is perhaps the most fundamental obstacle to
the development of the Bergsonian philosophy. But the escape
from this difficulty which Bergson presents is his identification
of life with this reality which we have within us. I pointed out
to you that in scientific development there is evolution, and the
theory of life which appears in science is revealed in the Bergsonian philosophy. In other words, Bergson finds in life all the
characters which he has identified in this inner experience. But
his
what
is life?
As
it is
presented to us
[502]
in the
modern
physiological
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
it is an interaction of process going on all over the
body. The different elements must be there affecting each other
in order that there may be life. You can kill a living form and
statement,
them into test tubes, but you can
from the point of view of Bergson,
another illustration of that which we find in our own inner life,
another illustration of reahty.
We have seen that the center of Bergson's position is found
in what he terms "intuition," the recognition of duration as it
appears in the inner experience. This involves interpenetration
of characters intensity, rather than extensity, of qualities.
This is a method which is given immediately, obtained through
a conceptual analysis and construction. From Bergson's standpoint the reahty of the world is that which is revealed in the
inner experience. This inner experience belongs to the individual.
It is not essential to the nature of reality. It indicates,
rather, the path by which the individual gets this intuition. But
that of which he gets an intuition is not a state of consciousness;
it is of the nature of reality itself.
get
all
the elements and get
never get
life.
Life then
is,
XVII
In discussing the relationship of mind and body in Bergson's
doctrine
we have
seen that the center of reality
is
to be found in
the psychical experience, as he indicates in the use of the term
"image." These images answer
in one sense to the impressions
and ideas of the empirical school. For Bergson the center of
reality is the psychical experience which is revealed in intuition,
as distinct from conceptual knowledge and also as distinct from
the organism of the spatial world. For Bergson the category of
time, as he conceives time,
The time
to
which he
closer to reality than that of space.
is
refers
is
duration, duree^ that which ap-
pears in the inner experience, that within which there can be
different types of interpenetration.
trast with the spatial world,
which
is
This he puts
external,
of quantity, while the inner experience
is
in
which
sharp conis
the state
the state of quality;
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
which is a matter of extensive magnitude over against intensive
magnitude. He refuses to recognize that this intensive magnitude can be dealt with from the point of view of the extensive
magnitude. In Bergson's mind, concepts involve the same sort
of externahty which he criticized in the attempts to state our
inner experience in terms of external stimulation. When we
think of things in terms of concepts with the sharp differences of
which they are capable, separating one from another, we are
doing the same sort of injustice to reahty as that to which I just
referred in the relation of an extensive stimulation or an extensive physiological response in its relationship to the inner ex-
perience. Bergson does not say that a concept
is
a spatial event,
same character of externality.
but he says that it
Concepts are exclusive of each other, and that exclusiveness is
has just the
almost externality.
What Bergson
in the biological world,
is
finds in the world, especially
a creative process which grows out of
that which has taken place but which
is
not
itself
given in that
which has come before. Duration is always the happening of that
which is novel. If you get a spatial statement of time, you get
that which has no succession in it, at least no duration in it.
Duration involves the appearance of something that was not
present before.
The account which Bergson
what he speaks of
gives of this world, as against
as a "distortion of reality,"
is
in
terms of the
characters in which the organism, the mind, puts its experience.
He assumes that the nature of the individual fixes the world, and
fixes it in terms of the uniformities of an individual's past experience in order that he
may
utilize
it.
The mind
certain characters of experience on which
it
selects
out
can depend, on
which its past experience indicates it can depend, and states a
world in these fixed forms. It is a pragmatic sort of procedure, a
selection of characters which are relatively permanent and a
statement of these in the interest of the solution of problems.
The externalized world is, therefore, a fixing, a freezing, of
reality in terms of certain uniformities that are applied to the
world as
if
they dominated and expressed that reality.
[504]
The
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
mind, then,
is
that which within itself
is
psychical, and which
own universe and its own organism for the purposes of
conduct. The great instrument for this purpose is the central
fixes its
nervous system.
Bergson passes on from this sort of a statement which is in
psychical terms over to a statement in biological terms in the
notion of a creative evolution. Reality, in so far as
that which advances, that which changes in
its
own
it is
living,
is
nature, that
motion is someis moving. It
is not a mere change of position. It does not change that which is
itself moving. Life is a change in the very nature of that which
lives. In so far as we are living beings, we are not at any second
what we were the second before. If we undertake to state life in
terms of a permanent content, we have taken the whole meaning
out of life as life. There is a physical, chemical statement available, but it is applied to inanimate things. It cannot be made
into a statement of life, for our conduct is from one reality to
another in which that reality is always changing. That, Bergson says, identifies life with this inner nature which our intuition reveals to us. Life is in that sense a sort of mind. It has
the same relationship to its environment as mind has to its
world and physical organism. It is selecting, it is petrifying its
world in spatial terms in the same fashion that mind does. In an
account of the process of evolution he gives this statement of
an onward move that is creation, that is constantly changing,
producing that which was not there before, changing itself but
doing it by means of the physical world. This picture we must
get from the outside, from what biology presents. But we interpret the form from within, for reality lies in our own experience. In our own experience we are cutting things up into homogeneous elements. That is, we want to have the same science
for tomorrow that we have today. We do not wish to have to remember in detail. Therefore, we fix our world and become familiar with it.
Evolution is a process of constructing a world that is exactly
whose nature
it is
to change. In Bergson's sense,
thing that goes on in the nature of the thing that
[505]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
parallel, in Bergson's sense, to
our perception of
it.
Selection
is
going on. Processes are continued; and in this selection that
which
is
novel
is
happening, making duration possible. That
takes place in our conduct, too.
Now, Bergson
brings this over
into a grand evolution in the development of life-processes. Life-
do just what we do in sense perception.
They mobilize themselves. They maintain themselves by means
of skeletons they develop, by sense organs which are produced
by their environment, which bound it and analyze it into elements which can be regarded as relatively permanent. The organism does this sort of thing just as our perception builds up
But this very world
its field of perception and its objects.
impresses life in just the way that habit impresses our own
action. Man becomes the slave of his habits, of the exoskeletons which cover us. We can only see what we have habituated ourselves to see. We live in the world which is cut out by
our past habits. This situation is presented from the Bergsonian standpoint on the side of evolution in its relation to an environment of organisms which have picked out that which they
can eat, that which they can reach by their method of procreation, that by means of which they can avoid this danger and
that. The organism has fixed itself, and it cannot go ahead.
The man who is getting on in years loses the vital spark. Health
is gone; he has nothing left but the fixed habits of life; he can
see nothing but that which he has selected in his conduct; he
has impressed himself, and there is no further advance for him;
forms
in this fashion
he can no longer be
What I want
in a field
to leave with
of creation.
you
is
a clue for the comprehension
of Bergson's conception of the world
the parallelism of the per-
ceptual process and the living process with this metaphysical
assumption of process which he never
not show us
in
any
detail
stereotyped, nor does he
He
how
the
show how
fully worked out. He does
method does actually get
life
stereotypes
its
world.
appeals to the process of perception and refers us to that
sort of intuition
same thing
is
which
is
so difficult to get,
and assumes that the
taking place in the external world that
[506]
is
taking
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
place from the standpoint of our inner perception. It is that to
which he refers, as I have said.
Here, then, we have Bergson's solution of the problem he
took over from Boutroux and Renouvier the problem of freedom. If one accepts his statement, he has more than solved
The only reality is this duration in which that which is
it.
novel Is continually coming into being. Bergson's problem can
be presented in this way. It is true that you can never previse
what is going to happen. There is always a difference in what
takes place and what has existed in the past. You cannot determine what you are going to be later. But the question is now:
What
is
the relationship of
stating the means. Bergson
means
is
to ends?
We
are constantly
correct in his position that,
if
we
form in which it is going to be realized, or
if we state it in such form that we must stick to the account
that we give of it, then we distort the thing. There is a story of
James and Royce, who were out sight-seeing in a city. Royce
had information of where they were going and told James what
car they would take so that in the end they would get to such
and such a place. They got to a junction where they had to
state an
end
in the
cars. James got on the wrong car. Royce corrected him,
him he was on the wrong car, that the car he was on went
to another point. "Yes," said James, "that is where I wanted to
go." There he puts in acute form the present problem. Can we
state the end of our own conduct and the end of creation; can it
change
telling
be stated in exact, definite form if the world is something that is
moving on from that which is to that which is not ? If that is the
nature of reality, can the end toward which movement is to take
place be stated in a conceptual form? Certainly we can say
cannot be stated at any given time.
overlooks in his treatment of science is that
science does not undertake to make such a statement. It is
continually presenting hypotheses of the world as it is, but science is a research affair and goes forward on the basis of the fact
not only that the world will be intelligent but that it will always
that
it
What Bergson
be different from any statement that science can give of it. That
THOUGHT
is,
we
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
are looking for an opportunity to restate any statement
which we can give of the world.
That is the implication of
But that does not mean that we cannot
think in conceptual terms. It means that we are always restating our restatement of the world. The same is true of
our own ends and process in life. If a person could state to
himself everything that is going to happen, his life would
our research science.
be unbearable.
Life
is
a happening; things take place; the
novel arises; and our intelligence shows
lems.
But the
solution of problems
The
conceptual procedure.
in the fact that everything
lute.
All that
is
is
itself in solving
by means of a
prob-
definite
collapse of absolute idealism lies
is
all
accomplished
in
the Abso-
to take place has already taken place in the
an adventure. And we can be inteUigent in stating at every point the form which our conduct
should take. We show our intelligence by giving as elaborate a
Absolute.
But our
life
is
statement of the world as we can. The realization of emergence
in philosophy, the large acceptance of pluralism which you see,
is involved in the assumption that the novel can appear by saying it is an enlarging of our finite imperfect experience. But
there can be nothing novel in an Absolute.
ess of
an
infinite type,
are determined.
but
it is
You can have
You
one in which
all
can have a procthe
movements
contradictions, but they are al-
ways overcome. You have that which goes on; but
it is going on
an infinity in which the result is obtained already,
but in which it does not appear.
It is this element that Bergson insists is involved in passage.
in eternity, in
That other statement
is of a conception of the reality of the
world in which everything is fixed in advance. It is its acceptance which Bergson is fighting. When you state reality in terms
of a mechanism, it is an academic statement of nature. When
you undertake to state your ends and problems, you fix and
stereotype it. You stop advancing. Does that mean you cannot
use the intelligence that enables you to get hold of means of
stating the ends toward which you are moving? If this is true,
Bergson's doctrine is correct, and we must draw away our in-
[508]
FRENCH PHILOSOPHY
and give ourselves up to our impulses.
end in terms of your means, with a
definite recognition that that statement is one which you are
going to change, that your life is a process of adaptation, you
can have the full reign of intellectual life and the control that it
gives and still not stereotype your experience.
That brings out the problem which Bergson presented in
his philosophy. The problem is that involved in the opposition, if you like, the antimony, between a conceptualized statement of that which is going to take place, of that which we
are going to do, and of that which does arise, that which we do
do, that which takes place in nature. Is there any real duration ?
If there is, there is that in which the novel is appearing. We are
passing on constantly to that which is new, and our conceptual statement is in terms of the situation in which we find
ourselves. How can we state that which is not.'' That is the
Bergsonian problem in its simplest form. I have tried to present
it as it appears in perception, as it appears in mechanical science,
in evolution, and in terms of social progress. We are moving on,
in the very nature of the case, in a process in which the past is
moving into the present and into the future. Can we use our
intellects to get hold of and direct this movement? Bergson
tellectual control of life
But
if
you can
state your
we cannot, because in the nature of the case that toward which we are going is not here yet and, if you do not have
knowledge of the end to which you are going, you cannot travel
toward it intellectually. You must depend on the wind blowing
behind you. You cannot reach it by conceptual means. But
says that
made over against this:
way
who
finding
his
toward
a goal which he canthat the man
is
not state can make a tentative plan as he goes along; and then
he can make that better, more accurate, more complete. But he
there
is
another statement which can be
has got to be in the attitude of continually reconstructing it and
restating it. We do not know what the end of society should be,
but we are sure that disease and misery in its various forms
of. How we are going to get rid of disease
should be gotten rid
we do not know. How
the values that have rested in
it
in the
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
past, the care for the sick,
a place
where there
will
and
so on,
fit
be no suffering
are stating in our conceptual
way what
with the conception of
in
we do not know. But we
the end
is
to be,
and then
it. What Bergson denies is the
advancing by a set of hypotheses which are being
continually reconstructed if they do not hold hypotheses
which are confessedly hypothetical. We have only the statement which we can give at the time, hypotheses which are open
to unexpected happenings and which are ready for reconstruction, hypotheses that belong to a world in which things are going
on, in which there is duration. What Bergson says is that this
sort of intelligent control of our conduct and intelligent control
over our comprehension of and appreciation of nature in the di-
we
test
our steps and restate
possibility of
movements
rection of the
in society is impossible.
that because any statement that
is
made
He
refuses
would be
If we had to
at this time
an absurd statement of what is going to be later.
conduct the world by the hypotheses of the seventeenth century, we would not get along. They undertook to state the
world as they gave it in conceptual terms. But that did not interfere with a continued restatement of them. The scientist is
always ready to reconstruct, and it is by means of such refined
statement that he gets ahead. If, of course, science had underit had and rehave
been in a
would
taken to give infaUibihty to any statement that
fused to reconstruct that statement,
prison.
But a restatement
it
at every point possible
is
what
science
wants. Thus, Bergson's attack upon science represents a mis-
conception of
is
its
method and
ideal.
unnecessary.
510I
His
flight to
irrationahsm
INDEX
Abelard, Peter 9
Absolute, 124, 139, 143-44, 221, 233, 334,
416-17, 508
laws, 253
and
relative, 141
state,
See also Self
Aesthetics, 425
for Kant, 68
and
self,
Brownian movement, 156
']'^-~l3
Bureaucracy, 231
69
Burke, Edmund, 55, 57, 209, 420
90
See also Schelling
Butler, Joseph, 202
Analysis, 328, 330-32, 333, 337, 358, 366,
402-3, 502
Aristarchus, 137
Byron, George Gordon, Lord, 62
Cabanis, Pierre
Aristotle, 4, 9, 10, 88, 137, 159, 249,
67, 268, 272, 275, 340-41, 407,
51,
Boutroux, Emile, 475-80, 483, 484-90,
493. 496-97. 57
Bright, John, 192
Romanticism,
for Schiller, 66,
Biology, 159, 249, 252-53, 263, 264-66,
305-6, 309, 364, 407, 450-51, 456,
496-97, 505. See also Process, life
Bismarck, Otto von, 234
Bonald. See De Bonald
44-46
Activity, as content, 435, 440, 443-44, 466
for
Biography, 409
266-
Capital, 220, 232-33. See also
Capitalism, development
Art, 409-10
327, 328-29,
Carlyle,
Thomas,
6t 152, 205-9, 211-12^
446, 447
Hume
Carnot, Sadi, 156, 278-79
Atoms, 244, 246, 255-56, 260, 347-48
Categorical imperative, 27-30, 107
statement of, 118
Attention, 386, 388, 444
Attributes. See Relation
Categories. See
Mind
Cause:
Bacon, Francis, 261, 450
in biology,
Bebel, Ferdinand A., 233-34
386-404.
of,
cialism
352, 386-87,
391. 395. 435. 436-37. 443-44- See
Behaviorism,
chology
Wealth
179-98, 233.
See also Industrial Revolution, So-
Asquith, Herbert Henry, 228
also
G., 435
450-
454-55
Association,
J.
Calvin, John, 181
See
also
252
and conduct, 114
and effect, 269, 326
Psy-
efficient,
Being, 328, 342
final,
249
268-72
Bennett, Arnold, 208
first,
1 1
Bentham, Jeremy, 201-5, 208, 210-11,
for
4-4. 464
Bergson, Henri, 168, 292-325, 489, 496510
laws, 352-53
for science, 276-80
and
2-1
Hume, 437-38
self,
124
Berkeley, George, 32-34, 79, 326, 327,
431-32, 498
Change, 296-98, 304, 356-58, 362-63, 501
Bifurcation, 496
Chateaubriand, Francois, 430
505
[^11]
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Church. See Religion
Coleridge,
Samuel
157-61, 166, 196-97, 244-45, 252-53,
T., 58, 63,
52, 446,
262,
447
"Common-sense" philosophy, 436, 438-
270, 273, 302, 306, 309, 456
Louis Gabriel, 428-30, 434,
449, 463-64
41, 442-43, 446, 468
Communism,
Community:
262,,
De Bonald,
De Maistre, Joseph
231, 24I
and economic process, 238-39
and the individual, 248, 281, 369, 375-
Democritus, 272
77, 413-14, 415
Napoleon as symbol of, 425-26
Descartes, Rene,
De Quincy, Thomas,
47 1 > 476, 490
Concepts, 278-79, 324, 335, 500-501, 504,
507-10
Bonnot
390-92
reflex,
151, 344, 350-51, 389-9,
392-93, 396. See also Pragmatism
and
defined, 121-22
Hegel's, 128-29, 131-32, 231, 461
influences of, 149-52
and Marx, 21 5, 220-22, 232-33
and science, 132-38, 143-44
Dickens, Charles, 57
Distribution, 219, 235, 237, 258
Drake,
Sir Francis, 179
Duration, 297-302, 304, 31 1-14, 316, 5012, 503-4, 507. 509
14
pragmatism, 344-59
reality,
Dialectic:
de, 435-36
Conduct:
and behavioristic psychology, 404
and experience, 386-89
explanation for, 249-50, 316-21
freed by science, 261, 288-90
for
Louis, 435
Dewey, John,
Comte, August, 373, 449, 45^-^6, 466-67,
Conditioned
252, 306, 307, 353,
and Romanticism, 78-79, 82-83
De Tracy, Antoine
See also Society, Socialism
Condillac, Stephen
63
i, 8,
467, 471
and religion, 428-30, 463
and science, 360-61
as supreme value, 464
moral,
Marie, 428-30, 434,
449, 463-64
Duty:
505-7
Calvinistic, 182
as "self-consciousness," 372
society as basis for, 361-63, 510
defined, 108
for Fichte, 102-4, 106-10,
Consciousness:
as brain secretion, 273
and conduct, 372
Economic
120-24
process, 183, 223, 233.
See also
History
defined, 392-93, 395, 417
Economic structure of
and intelligence, 290
and knowledge, 329-30, 22,3-^
Economics:
and the community, 188, 206-7
and the French Revolution, 418-19
and science, 243-58
and socialism, 236-39
and society, 171, 178-79
non-existent for behavioristic psychology, 386-404, 473, 498-99
and problem-solving, 410
and relation, 414, 416, 482-83
states of, 327, 437-38, 443, 469, 498, 503
See also History, Socialism, Industrial
Conservation of energy, 280
Corpernicus,
6, 117, 137,
society, 192-98
Revolution
Eddington, Sir Arthur, 142
355-56
Cousin, Victor, 441, 445-49. 474-75
Education:
and Mill, 214
psychology of, 435, 469-7
Crime, 364, 368-75
Damien de Veuster, Father, 108-9
Ego. See Self
Dante,
Einstein, Albert, 38, 117, 137, 258, 324,
406, 487, 494. See also Relativity
3,
463
Darwin, Charles, 91, 117, 128, 145, 154,
512]
INDEX
Elan
vital,
and consciousness, 290
form and content of, 327-29
French interest in, 469-71
293, 304
Electricity, 243-44,
255-56
Electromagnetism, 1SS~S1
interpenetration of, 300, 308-11, 316
moral, 107
Electrons, 256, 260, 329
Embryology, 159
Emergence, 414
of the novel, 405-8
organization
Emerson, Ralph Waldo,
as a
52
and skepticism, 434-35, 437-38
social,
415
subjective
1
and objective aspects
See also Novelty
Fabian socialism, 229-30, 235, 239-40
Factory system, 173, 175, 191-95, 206-
279-80,
7,217,218,424
Fechner, Emil, 481-82
Feudalism:
Entropy, 155-56, 287
and
and
and
and
Environment, 140, 161, 168, 253, 261-62,
270, 281, 350, 372-73
8
Carlyle, 205-9, 211-12
Christianity, 429
French Revolution, 418-21
Napoleon, 426-27
Fichte,
Epistemology:
for empiricism, 436-38, 440
for Fichte, 88-93, 123-24
for Kant, 76-78
for pragmatism, 344-45
problem of, 75-76, 468-69, 472
Johann Gottlieb,
and Kant, 88-89, 91-107
and nationalism, 96-110, 422-23
See also Self
Fitzgerald contraction, 257
Force, 279, 288, 494
for
Forms. See Mind, Species
327-43
Romanticism, 79-81
of science and philosophy, 276-77, 481
See also Knowledge, Skepticism
Frederick the Great, 96, 144, 423
Ether, 254-5S, 257
Evolution, 91, 129, 142-43, 145, 147, 15368, 270, 271, 273, 288-89, 290, 294-
Free Trade, 200, 424
French Revolution,
effects of, 418-22,
425
430-34, 435-36, 44^
See also Hobbes, Kant, Locke, Napoleon, Renaissance, Rousseau, Vol-
95, 301-4, 364, 456, 55-6
philosophy
organic, 140
365-73, 378, 381-85
and antinomies, 115
for Bergson, 497-505
of,
taire
of thought, 139
See also Species
aesthetic, 410-11
13, 14, 21, 51-61, 65,
71, 147, 169, 361, 421
and forms, 154, 157-59, 451
Experience:
63, 71, 84, 85-
iio, 122, 418, 446
for realism,
social, 148-49,
of,
53-54, 439-41
of universals, 432-33
value of, 204-5
Encyclopedists, 430, 456
Epicurus,
456
for realism, 2,23-^2,
Empiricism:
and association, 326-27
and Kant, 45-50, 66-67, 76, 153
and knowledge, 436-38, 440
and mathematics, 340
and objects, 352
and self, 35, 77, 78
and universals, 433-34
268,
443
for science,
and psychology, 386-93, 467
Emotion, 396
See also James-Lange theory
Energy, 154-56, 243-46,
286-88,291,347-48
conservation of, 280
of,
problem
Galileo,
5, 6, 8,
243, 248-49, 259, 266-67
309,450-51,455
Galilean movement, 429-30
Geometry. See Mathematics
sn
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Identity:
George, Lloyd, 228
Goethe,
Green,
4, 61, 63, 65, 81,
Thomas
mathematics, 491
philosophy of, 126, 127, 496
of subject and object, 131, 477
in
187
Hill, 156
Guilds, 178, 231, 232
Images, 397-99, 401-2, 497-9^, 53
Guyau, Jean Marie, 436
Immorality, 107
Heat, 243, 278, 287
Imperative, categorical.
imperative
Hedonism, 205
Hegel, Georg W.
ImperiaHsm, 109, 418, 421
F., 84, 86-87, 106, 122,
127-52, 168, 221-24, 239,332-33,418
influence of, 150-51, 367-68, 447-48
and science, 461
See also Dialectic
See Categorical
Individuality, 405-17
Industrial Revolution, 149, 169-98, 212,
239,418,421
419-20
results of,
See also Utilitarianism
Hegel, Karl, 368
Inertia, 154, 249
Henry VIII, 429
Ingression, 336
Herbart, Johann Friedrick, 469-71
Institutions:
Herder, Johann Gottfried, 69
and change, 2^2
and the community, 361, 366-76
Hertz, Heinrich, 255
defined, 361, 366
History, I45-52, 447~48
economic, 150, 221-24, 233
Hobbes, Thomas, 14-15,
Holy Roman Empire,
French philosophy
hostile to, 468
Instrumentalism, 351
17, 18, 25
176, 178, 186-87,
Intelligence, 345-46
International, 216, 225-26
429
Homer, 274-75
Hume, David,
228-30, 424. See also
International, Labor, Nationalism
Internationalism,
5,
79, 80, 188, 202, 304,
Interpenetration, 300, 308-11, 316, 502,
305, 307, 326, 327, 431-32, 435
and causation, 33-34, 437-38
503
Introspection, 444-45, 447, 471
and Kant, 31-50
and laws of nature, 37-39, 454
and Napoleon, 427
and self, 34-35
Intuition, 124, 126-27, 303, 321, 330, 438,
467, 491, 495, 501-3
"I." See Self
James, William, 344, 387-89, 392, 394,
395, 398. See also Pragmatism
Idea, 146
James-Lange theory of emotions, 396-97
Idealism:
Kant, Immanuel, 25-50,
absolute, 95, 139, 416-17
criticism of, 508
Kant, 35
philosophy
of, 327,
332
and realism 327-28
romantic, 95, 344, 416, 418, 422-23,
446-47.481
See also Absolute,
Idealistic
and Bergson, 305, 306, 309
categorical imperative, 27-30, 107,
and conduct, 48-50, 89-90, 102, 1 1
1 1
and experience, 112
faculty of judgment, 42-48, 92-93, 112
and Fichte, 88-89, 91-107
and Hume, 31-50
laws of nature, 39-42, 49, 76-77
Mind
movements,
59, 67, 76, 157,
304-7, 316, 326-27, 337, 343, 439,
446, 469
and antinomies, 86, 95, 112-22, 129
and a priori elements, 31-50
Berkeley, 32
228, 497
Idealogues, 431, 432
Ideology, 43 ' -3-, 434-35
[S'4
INEX
Kant, Immanuel
Continued
Kant's, 153
and political revolution, 25-50, 51
and Romanticism, 66-84, 85-86
and Rousseau, 25-27, 42
and science, 37-42, 46-47, 50, 67-68,
and subject-object relationship, 35, 73See also Mind, Self
and mathematics, 340-42, 359, 491
Mill's, 460
Romantic, 154
Louis
Machine, 170, 173-74, 193. 206-7, 245,
Kepler, Johannes, 137, 243
287
Knowledge:
is
active,
Maistre. See
466
Malthus, David, 161, 193, 194-98, 215,
221, 232, 236, 237, 244-45, 252
Locke, 431
for Poincar^,
493
positive, 453-54
as relation, 438
is relative, 486
for Royer-Collard, 442-43, 446
See also Epistemology
Malthusian law. See Malthus
Man,
229, 232, 245, 253
Markets, 171-81, 189, 191-92, 220, 229
Labor party, 229-30, 234-35, 238, 239
Laissez faire, 199. See also Economic
Structure, Adam Smith
91,
127,
154,
159, 161, 166
Land, struggle
for,
as organism, 251
Manchester school, 215, 218, 220, 224,
Labor, 150-51, 194-97, 199, 206-7, ^'7"
20, 223-42, 245, 424-25. See also International, Internationalism
Lamarck, Jean Baptiste,
De Maistre
Malory, Sir Thomas, 62
and conduct, 350-51
for
XIV, 429
Lovejoy, A. O., 343
Luther, Martin, 181
418-21, 425-28
Language:
and apperceptive mass, 470
as basis for society, 375-81
as symbols, 392
LaPIace, Pierre Simon, 157, 159, 251, 252,
471
Marx, Karl, 149-50, 215-40, 253, 368,
424, 448. See also Socialism
Mass, 154-55. 243. 249. 251, 348
Materialism, 220-28, 233, 273
Mathematics:
and logic, 330^31
and Plato's philosophy, 450
and relation, 481-83, 493
theory of, 486-88, 490-96
and world-view, 337-42, 353, 354-59,
480
Matter, 113, 138, 154, 248-49, 258, 437,
439
Maxwell, James Clerk, 255, 256, 490
"Me." Seesdi
Lassalle, Ferdinand J. G., 216, 217
Leibnitz, Gottfried Wilhelm,
i,
8,
Mechanical science, 250-63, 267-81, 493,
139,
251. 330-31. 3 53-54> 357
495. 501
Mechanics, 249, 279
Liberty, 362, 445
Mechanism, 155-57, 243, 250-53, 255
Life. See Process
259, 260-64, 273, 281, 290-91
versus free will, 471-90, 496-510
Light, 253-57, 348
Linnaeus, Carl von, 456
Mercantilism, 188-90, 216
Locke, John,
Meredith, George, 211
14,
15-16, 17, 32, 34, 36,
79. 318, 326, 469-70
influence on French, 430-32
Logic:
of Aristotle and Bacon, 450-51
Hegelian, 132, 146-47
Merz, John Theodore, 251
Metaphysics. See Reality
Metternich, Prince Klemens von, 422
Michelson-Morley experiment, 257
[s^s\
THOUGHT
IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
Mill, James, 193, 208, 210, 214, 424, 464,
Nature:
control of, 261
468
laws
22, 193, 208, 212-14,
John Stuart,
Mill,
Milton, John,
249-52, 253, 258, 260, 264-91,
as objective expression, 124-26
for skepticism,
247
2, 3,
of,
329,353-54.406,474.478
217-18, 224, 424, 435, 460-61, 464,
468. See also Utilitarianism
See also
Mind.
434
Mechanism
as Absolute, 344
and activity, 466
Neo-Platonists, 139
Nervous system, 472-73
and behavior, 386-404
and body, 306-8
News, 405-9. See also Individuality, Novel
Newton, Isaac, 38, 117, 137, 154-55, 157,
forms
of, 99,
243-44, 251, 254, 256, 260, 279, 286,
102, 112, 147, 153, 326,
290, 292, 294, 305, 306, 343, 357, 476,
337. 469
for
Hume, 437-38
and
intelligence,
484-85
Novel, 410, 411-12. See also Individual-
366
Locke, 431
and matter, 497-98
relation to environment, 384
for
relation to world, 138-39, 326-27,
30.
335-37.
352-54,
439-40,
ity,
elements
of,
16-17,
405-9,
458-59, 478-79. 507, 509
329447,
requires universality, 305
and society, 381
See also Kant, Idealism, Locke
Opportunism, 230, 235-36
Organism, 251
Ostwald, Wilhelm, 246
Pavlov, Ivan Petrovich, 390-91
Perception:
Money. See Wealth
causal theory of, 352
and cognition, 158, 282, 440-41
as determining world, 142
Montaigne, Michel de, 444, 469
Montesquieu, Charles de, 16
Moral purpose, 247
Moralist, Romantic, 107
and knowledge, 333-3^, 435. 506-7
Philosophy:
French and English contrasted, 418-41
and science, 281-91, 326-59, 449-52,
Morality:
and Fichte, 93-94, 98-110, 120
and Kant, 48-50, 89-90, 118
and man, 91-92
Motion, 138, 154, 248, 251, 279-80, 357,
500, 505
480-81
Physical science. See Science
Physical world. See World
Physiocrats, 188-90, 215
Napoleon, 51-57, 60,
425-28
85, 95-97, 418, 421,
Plato, 121, 139,448,450
Pleasure-pain theory, 202, 204-5, 209-10,
213
Nationalism:
in England, 423-24
in France, 55-56, 418
in Germany, 96-97, 422-23, 428
and internationalism, 226
Pliny, 407-8
Plutarch, 409
Poincare, Henri, 324, 339, 354, 480, 48788, 489, 490-96, 497
and Napoleon, 425-28
Natural law:
contingency
News
Novelty,
Positivism:
defined, 452
and J. S. Mill, 460-61
477-90
necessity of, 477-90
See also Nature
of,
of, 452-66
and society, 461-66
weakness of, 459-61
philosophy
Natural rights, 418, 436. See also Rousseau
[5^6]
See also
Comte
INBEX
Realism, 326-44, 358
Postulates:
Kant's, 119
of science, 258-59, 265-91
Realistic
Pragmatism:
and Bergson, 502
philosophy of, 344-59
See also
movement,
151
Reality, 146, 269, 327-43, 352, 413, 467,
476-90, 495-96. 499-510
Abelard, 9
Bergson, 300, 302-4, 308, 310-11, 3I5-
Dewey
I9,
3^3^25
Christianity, 10
Process:
of entropy, 155
life, 127-28, 161-68, 252-53, 260, 263,
271. 289, 372, 377, 502-3, 505-6, 508
Descartes, 8
natural, 158, 451-52, 500
quantum theory, 117
Renaissance, 9-10
romanticism, 82-83
Epicurus,
8,
Kant, 35, 42-48
370-73, 376, 381-85
thinking, 129-30
social, 148, 363,
science, q
Production, 218-20, 223-24, 231, 232-33,
of
237. 245, 258
C{e!f, 131,'
substancc-attributt^82, 477
See also Self
Profit, 218, 220, 223, 231
Progress, 411, 509. See also Evo'.ution
Reform. See Socialism, Utilityiianism
Proletariat, 24I
Reformation, 181, 182
Psychology:
behaviorism, 387-404
heha- "orism in pragmatism, 350-52
behaviorism and society, 381-83
in Bergson's philosophy, 305-10, 31618, 322-23
conditioned reflex, 391-92
and consciousness, 387-88, 392-404
and experience, 388-404, 435
functional, 386-87
.1 philosophy, 444-45, 446-47> 466-83,
496-506
stimulus response, 389
Reid, Thomas, 438, 440, 466-68
Relation, 327, 343, 352, 386-87, 394-95,
41 4-1
cause and effect, 326-28, 437-38
as knowledge, 437, 444, 454-55
for science, 1 58, 243-44, 260, 449-50
self- not-self,
iii
35, 73-75, 81-82, 87,
97-98, 105, 130-31, 139, 163, 166-67,
339-30, 393, 438, 481-82, 593-96
subject-object relation and moral ex-
subject-object,
perience, 98
subject-object relation as process, 105,
128
structural, 386
Psycho-physical parallelism, 475-70
subject-object
Psychophysics, 481-82
Ptolemy, 117, 137,355-56
Pythagoras, 137, 339
Quantum
Queen
and Christianity,
and banking, 180-81
and economic change, 181-83
positivistic, 464-65
and romanticism, 428-30
and science, 247-49, 288-89
and society, 362-63, 41 1, 425, 463-64
modern
science, 9
theory of the state, 12-24
in
and
St.
494-95
17, 487,
Religion, 176-78, 186-87
Radiation, 346-48
Rationalism, 326, 344, 352, 437
and Aristotle, 4-5
of Christianity and science, 5-8
and mathematics, 7-8
substance-attri-
Relativity, 140-41, 256-58, 303-4, 412-
theory, 117, 254, 256
Elizabeth, 179
versus
bute, 109
substance-attribute, 105, 326
Renaissance, 1-24, 222, 248, 259, 275, 294,
450-51
_
as revolution, 12-24, 80, 137, 154
Augustine, 2
social,
[517]
215-40
THOUGHT
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
IN
Renouvier, Charles Bernard, 475, 507
and industry, 243-63
Research, 264-91. See also Science
for
Kant, 99
405-9
as news,
Revolution:
against authority, 12-13, 418, 427
breakdown
of, 51-65
England, 433
socialist, 220-24
See also French Revolution, Industrial
Revolution
in
Ricardo, David, 193, 197, 215, 221, 244-
and origin of man, 91
and philosophy, 281-91, 326-59, 44952,480-81,499
Renaissance, 1 54, 324
as research, 264-91
and society, 360-85
Scientific
45
361, 364-65, 370, 386, 405-8, 4i5-i7>
Romantic Idealism, 66-152,
167.
method, 143-44, 168, 264-66,
275, 281, 284-85, 294, 346, 352-56,
154,
163,
See also Fichte, Hegel, Kant,
SchelHng
450-51,490
Scott, Sir Walter, 62, 73
Self:
Romanticism:
background
and empiricism, 125
of, 5^--^y
characteristics of, 57-65,
147, 21 ;. 423, 425, 428
and
and
and
and
and
and
69-73,
75>
evolution, 127, 142
Fichte, 85-110
individuality of, 41
Hegel, 127-52
Kant, 66-84
reality of, 139
Spinoza, 105
of,
and romanticism, 58-65, 66-84, 85-
85-86
iio, 120-21, 125, 147, 167-68, 215,
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 12, 13,
14, 16-24,
85,421,432
criticism of, 21-24, 25
and Hobbes, 17
influence on Kant, 25-27
and poHtical revolution,
418,430, 441
and Kant, 45-46, 5, 66, T2o
and not-self, 88, 93-1 10
Schelling, 11 1-26
summary
^;i'Dression of, 374-75
and yichte, 85-110
and Frencu philosophy, 466-71
and Hume, 34-35
327,328,416
and Royer-Collard, 443-44
and Schelling, 11 1-26
and social process, 381-85, 415
See also Absolute
51,
54,
60,
Skepticism, 31, 35-36, 76, 77-78, 80, 327,
434-35
Royce, Josiah, 151
Adam, 188-91, 193, 197, 215, 217,
220, 221, 224-25, 240
Smith,
Royer-Collard, Peter Paul, 436, 439-40,
442-44, 446, 449, 467, 474
Social philosophy, 147-50
Russell, Bertrand, 337, 340, 414, 490, 493
Social-Democratic party, 225, 230, 233,
242
St. Augustine, 2
Santayana, George, 343
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm, 63, 71, 84,
86-87, 106, 1 1 1-26, 418, 446
Social evolution, 168
Social reform, 363-67. See also Socialism,
Utilitarianism
Schiller, Friedrich, 61, 63, 65, 66, 69
Socialism, 199, 215-42, 253, 424-25
Science:
Society:
and change, 202-3
507-10
and determinism, 471-90
and dogma, 258-59, 265-78, 288-91
and duty, 108-9
for Bergson, 501,
dynastic, 426-28
economic, 195-97
feudal and industrial contrasted, 169-98
French Revolution fails to reorganize,
evolutionary, 168
and the individual, 405-9
is
418,425
[5^8]
INDEX
Usher, James, 274
Society:^Continued
and the individual, 23'^y 45> 4'3> 4' 5
and positivism, 461-66
and religion, 248, 428-30
and science, 248, 250-51, 253, 261, 28081,360-85
See also
Utilitarianism, 193, 199-214, 424, 464
Value:
and action, 103
of experience, 388
human, 202-3, 412
Community
and positivism, 464-65
Sociology, 373-85
and Comte, 461-66
Vitalism, 292-325
Socrates, 121-22
Voltaire, 59, 430, 431, 432, 441, 448
Solar system, 243
175, 196, 199-200, 218-20, 223,
229, 232-34, 236-37
Wages,
Solipsism, 413
Sophists, 121-22
Watson,
Space, 256-58, 338-39, 400-401, 412, 487,
491-95, 503
Species, 157-68, 252-C3, 262-63, ^64, 274,
288-89, 365, 383, 451, 456
yc, 392
Webb,
216, 218-23, 232,
1135,
Beatrice, 235
Wetb, Sidney, 235
Spencer, Herbert, 368, 373
Spinoza, Baruch, i, 8, 74, 80-82, 105
Webi.r's law, 31
Sta 'A, 144-46, 221, 239-40, 432. See also
oScialism
Whitehead, Alfred N.,
314, 3'
5,
325,
33(>,
142, 312, 313,
7,
337, 340, 343. 415.
49
Stimulus-response, 389-90
Will:
Subsistence, 23(>
and Boutroux, 475-79
Cousin, 475
and determinism, 471-90
and Renouvier, 475
Synthesis, 328, 337
Tariffs, 200-201, 229
Teleology, 450
and science, 250-52
and mechanism, 267-72
See also Mechanical science
Wolff, Christian,
Thinking, 376, 380-81, 401-3, 432. See
also Process, thinking
Time, 250, 251, 256-58, 31
Jc'.-n,
W-alth, i88-q2,
235, 420-21
1,
412, 471, 503.
See also Duration
as art, 111-12
and
Transcendentalism, 115, 118, 153, 440,
445, 469. See also Kant, Romanticism
Wordsworth, William, 58
World:
dialectic, 137
elements of novelty
in,
16-17, 4S~9>
458-59, 507
and form, 128
identical with self, 124-25
TroUope, Anthony, 211
and perception, 142, 416
physicist's, 154-57,412-13,487,495-96
Truth, 344-50, 442-43
Twain, Mark, 63
as rational, 114, 118
and
Unions, 207-8, 236, 424-25
relation, 4I4-17, 493
romanticism, 141
structure of, 491-96, 503-10
for
Universal, 267, 275-76, 335-36, 340, 342-
43,415
See
versus particular, 135, 432-33
also
Fichte,
Kant,
Mechanism,
Relativity, Schelling, Science
Universality, 135, 405-6
and morality, 119
Zeller,
ITprintedII
JLlN
USaJ
Eduard, 448
CP
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY
Los Angeles
This hook
;Srr}c:v\
rj\
m^
Cf
f^St-'
-'"
is
DUE on the last date stamped
helow.
'^^
^f^'^C
^ qc^
i4<
m( 1 8
^^
"
Qt.
RtCDLU-URl
apRl 9189S
28
-
24139
3 1158 00164 3559
^H
ni}iu)i'ii)i)i){iu<)[yo!)i)!i
iiil