0 ratings 0% found this document useful (0 votes) 311 views 18 pages Canguilhem Ideology & Rationality 1
The document is a collection of symbols and characters with no discernible meaning or organization. It does not convey any clear ideas, concepts, or information.
AI-enhanced title and description
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here .
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
Carousel Previous Carousel Next
Save canguilhem ideology & rationality 1 For Later Ideology and Rationality in the History of the
Life Sciences
Georges Canguilhem
translated by Arthur Goldhammer
“The MIT Press
(Cambridge, Massachusets,
London, EnglandEnglish translation copyright © 1988 Massachusetts Institute of
‘Technology
(Originally published under the ttle Idéologie et rationalité dans Vistoire
des sciences de la vies Nowwelles ire et de philosophie des
sciences, copyright © 1977 Lit losophique J. Vein, Pats,
France.
[All rights reserved. No part ofthis book may be reproduced in any form
or by any electronic or mechanical means, including photocopying,
‘recording, or information storage and retrieval, without permission in
‘writing from the publisher.
“This book was typeset by Graphic Composition Inc.
and was printed and bound by Halliday Lithograph
in the United States of America.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
‘Canguithem, Georges, 1904—
Ideology and rationality in the history ofthe life sciences.
“Translation of: Idéologie et rationalité dans Uhistoire des sciences de
Iavie.
Bibliography: p.
Includes index.
1 Life sciences—History, 2 Life sciences—Philosophy. 1. Title
QH305.C2613 1988 574.09 H-610
ISBN 0-262-03137-X
Contents
‘Translator’s Preface vil
Preface ix
Introduction: The Role of Epistemology in
Contemporary History of Science 1
Scientific and Medical Ideologies in the
Nineteenth Century
‘What Is a Scientific Ideology? 7
John Brown’s System: An Example of Medical
Ideology 4
Bacteriology and the End of Nineteenth-Century
“Medical Theory” sz
‘Triumphs of Biological Rationality in the
Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries
“The Development of the Concept of Biological
Regulation in the Eighteenth and Nineteenth
‘Centuries 8r‘On the History of the Life Sciences since Darwin
The Question of Normality in the History of
Biological Thought
Sources
Index
CONTENTS
103
m5
147
149
Translator’s Preface
Georges Canguilhem was born in 1904. He studied and
began to teach philosophy but while teaching decided to
work toward a medical degree. His reasons are worth
noting:
Ie is not necessarily to learn more about mental illness that
a professor of philosophy will take an interest in medicine.
Nor is it necessarily to practice a scientific discipline. What
expected from medicine was nothing other than an intro-
duction to concrete human problems. Medicine seemed to
me then, and still seems to me now, a technique or an art
at the crossroads of several sciences more than a science in
the strict sense of the word. Two problems—that of the
relation between science and technology, and that of norms
and normality—could, I thought, be more precisely for.
mulated and more fully elucidated by someone with med-
ical training. . .. The present work {his 1943 thesis, The
Normal and the Pathological) is therefore an effort to in-
tegrate some of the methods and results of medicine into
philosophical speculation.
Canguilhem with his life's work has admirably ful-
led this statement of intention. Along with Gaston Bach-
lard he has been one of the primary influences in the
reorientation of French philosophy in recent years. It was
Bachelard who introduced the concept of an “epistemolog-
ical break,” a concept whose importance and usefulness
Canguilhem has demonstrated in his own way. But Can-
guilhem’s work also shows how philosophy can span theviii
coupure, so to speak, in order to reestablish continuity at
another level, For Canguilhem, error is the truth of the past
transcended, and he is able to show in concrete detail why
the history of science should be studied not as a steady
march toward truth but as a process of formation and re-
formation of concepts and models. His method is more
easily grasped in action than through description, and
there is perhaps no better introduction to his work than
the essay (included here) entitled “Bacteriology and the
End of Nineteenth-Century ‘Medical Theo!
In 1955 Canguilhem succeeded Bachelard as director
of the Institut d'Histoire des Sciences et des Techniques, a
position that he held until his retirement a few years ago.
Pethaps the most noted of the younger philosophers influ-
enced by his thought was the late Michel Foucault, who
wrote of his debt to Canguilhem’s pioneering work. Inter-
ested readers may wish to consult Le Normal et le patho-
logique (1966, containing the 1943 thesis and later essays
and now available in English), La Formation du concept
de réflexe (x95 5, reissued 1977), La Connaissance de la vie
(1952, 1965), Etudes d’histoire et de philosophie des sci-
ences (1968), and the volume from which the present
translation was made, Idéologie et rationalité dans I'his-
toire des sciences de la vie (1977). Canguilhem also pro-
vided a preface to a recent edition of Claude Bernard's
Lecons sur les phénomnes de la vie communs aux ani-
maux et aux végétaux (1966).
‘TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE
Preface
To err is human, to persist in error is diabolical. It is not
up to me to decide the degree of error embodied in the
texts gathered here. I am surely too old to make public
confession of my mistakes, to proclaim my allegiance to
newly instituted epistemological authorities at the cost of
renouncing methodological axioms that I borrowed some
forty years ago and subsequently exploited in my own way
and at my own tisk, not without emendation, revision, and
reorientation.
In 1967-68, under the influence of work of Michel
Foucault and Louis Althusser, I introduced the concept of
scientific ideology into my lectures. This was not simply a
mark of my interest in and acceptance of the original con-
butions of those two thinkers to the canons of scientific
history. It was also a way of refurbishing without rejecting
the lessons of a teacher whose books I read but whose lec-
tures I was never able to attend. For whatever liberties my
young colleagues may have taken with the teachings of
Gaston Bachelard, their work was inspired by and built
on his,
1 do not believe, therefore, that the reader of my first
Etudes d’bistoire et de philosophie des sciences (Studies in
the History and Philosophy of the Sciences) will find inthese essays signs of change or evolution in my thinking.*
As for the question whether my indifference to the devel-
‘opment of a history that would substitute for the distinc-
tion between science and philosophy (or, in other words,
between science and literature) a notion of their mutual
interpenetration should or should not earn me the distinc-
tion of being a “conceptualist fossil” I must admit I do not
much care. When one’s own insignificant research has led
‘one to recognize the existence of discontinuity in histo:
would be inappropriate to refuse to recognize discontinui-
ties in the history of history. To each his own discontinuity,
his own revolutions in the world of scholarship.
(On the other hand I should like very much to answer
question that has been raised by no one but myself. The
author of The Archaeology of Knowledge, whose analysis
of scientific ideology I have found quite useful, has distin-
guished several “thresholds of transformation” in the his-
tory of knowledge: a threshold of positivity, a threshold
of epistemologization, a threshold of scientificity, and a
threshold of formalization.’ In my published work I am
not sure that I have distinguished as carefully as Michel
Foucault might wish among the various thresholds crossed
by the disciplines I have studied. It seems to me in any case
that, the claims of certain geneticists notwithstanding,
none of those disciplines has yet crossed the threshold of
formalization. Unlike Foucault, however, I do not believe
that experimental medicine as practiced by Claude Bernard
and microbiology as practiced by Louis Pasteur were
adequate in their cont
ence of clinical medicine. I readily admit that I failed to
pay adequate attention to the question of thresholds of
* (Etudes d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences was published
by Librairie Vrin in 1968. The French edition of the present work
bears the subtitle Nouvelles études d'histoire et de philosophie
des sciences.—Trans,]
PREFACE
transformation. But nineteenth-century medicine and bi-
ology lend themselves less readily than, say, nineteenth-
century chemistry to dissection of the conditions that made
“progress” possible. One can irgue, I think, that Ber-
nard’s physiological medicine exhibits a case in which “ep-
istemologization,” at the hands of a Bernard himself in love
with philosophizing, raced far in “advance” even of posi-
tive empirical results. By contrast, Pasteur, a chemist rather
than a physician, was primarily interested in making a pos-
itive contribution to research and not unduly concerned
with developing a consistent epistemology.
It may be, finally, that my analyses are not sufficiently
subtle or rigorous. I leave it to the reader to decide whether
this is a question of discretion, sloth, or incapacity.
Notes
See Michel Foucault, L’Archéologie du savoir, pp. 243-247.
. Woodger, Axiomatic Method in Biology (Cambridge:
1937), and “Formalization in Biology,” Logique et analyse, new
(August 1958).
3
Cf. B. Dagognet, Méthodes et doctrine dans V'oeuvre de Pasteur
(Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1967), conclusion,
Gc.
June 1977
PREFACE,Ideology and Rationality in the History of the
Life SciencesIntroduction: The Role of Epistemology in
Contemporary History of Science
‘To anyone who would examine the relations between epis-
temology and the history of science, one fact stands out
above all others: namely, that we possess at present more
manifestoes and programs of research than we do hard
facts, Statements of intention are numerous, concrete te-
sults meager.
Compared with the history of science, a discipline
with a history of its own, epistemology at first sight seems
to find itself in a false position. Chronologically, the history
of science owes nothing to the philosophical discipline that
appears to have acquired the name epistemology in 1854,
Montucla’s Histoire des mathématiques (1758), Bailly’s
Histoire de lastronomie (1775-1782), and Kurt Sprengel
Versuch einer pragmatischen Geschichte der Areneikunde
(1792-1803) were all written without reference to any sys-
tem of critical or normative concepts. No doubt all these
works were informed, whether their authors were aware
of it or not, by a period consciousness, impersonally for-
mulated in the doctrine of infinite perfect
‘man spirit and based on an almost unbroken series of
revolutions in cosmology, mathematics, and physi
revolutions associated with the names Copernicus, G:
Descartes, Harvey, Newton, Leibniz, and Lagrounds of continuity it was therefore legitimate to believe
in further scientific progress to come. Although Sprengel
(the date being 1792) explicitly alludes to critical philoso-
phy in the introduction to his history of medicine, he men-
tions it simply as a doctrine in which certain physicians
happen to be well versed, just as certain of their predeces-
sors were well versed in dogmatic, empirical, or skeptical
philosophy, rather than as a new and effective instrument
for judging the validity of scientific methods. Hence there
is no point in reproaching cighteenth- and nineteenth-
century historians of science for not having employed any
of the epistemological concepts that today’s philosophers
are attempting to enforce as rules for writing scientific
history.
‘Among historians of science, those who dislike the
scrutiny of their discipline by epistemologists have not
been remiss in pointing out that epistemology, itself nour-
ished by the history of science, cannot presume to give
more than it has received; that is, it cannot pretend to re-
form the principles of a discipline from which it in fact
derived. The acrimony of the controversy is not unrelated,
however vaguely or loosely, to the ancient view of the re-
ines and the faculties of the soul,
according to which history corresponds to Memory. It is
hard to say whose ambition is more exorbitant, the histor-
s’ or the epistemologists’. Which is more pretentious: to
claim memory or judgment? Errors of judgment are acci-
dental, but alteration is of the essence of memory. About
reconstructions in the history of science one must make a
point that has repeatedly been made about reconstructions
in other fields of history—political, diplomatic, military,
and so on: namely, that contrary to Leopold von Ranke’s
dictum, the historian can never claim to represent things as
they really were (wie es eigentlich gewesen
jksterhuis’s comment that “the history of science
forms not only the memory of science but also its episte-
INTRODUCTION
mological laboratory” has frequently been commented
on2 Since elaboration is different from restitution, one
may conclude that epistemology’s claim to give more than
it has received is legitimate. Epistemology shifts the focus
story of science to science as seen in
the light of history. To take as one’s object of inquiry noth-
ing other than sources, inventions, influences, priorities,
simultaneities, and successions is at bottom to fail to
distinguish between science and other aspects of culture. A
history of science free of epistemological contamination
‘would inevitably reduce the state of a scientific discipline—
plant physiology in the eighteenth century, say—to a sum-
mary of chronological and logical connections among var-
ious systems of propositions pertaining to various classes
of problems or solutions, The quality of historical work
would then be measured by breadth of erudition and
shrewdness in analyzing the connections between the work
of different scientists, by skill in ferreting out si
and differences in their views. But the diverse quality of
historical works cannot conceal the fundamentally identi-
cal relation of the historian to the object whose history is
being told. A pure history of eighteenth-century botany
would consider “botanical” nothing but what botanists of
the period took to be within their scope of inquiry. Pure
historians are interested only in what scientists thought
they were doing and how they went about doing it. But a
fundamental question must be asked: Does this science of
the past constitute a past for the science of today?
“Taken in an absolute sense, the “past of a science” is
a vulgar concept. The “past” is a catchall of retrospective
inquiry, Whether the question is the shape of the earth, the
“hominization” of man, the social division of labor, or the
alcoholic delirium of a particular individual, one turns to
the “past” as required by present needs in search of more
‘or less remote antecedents to some present state of affairs.
The past, moreover, is conceived beforehand as a vessel of
larities
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGYinfinite capacity. Consider again the example of plant phys-
iology. In the broad sense just defined, its past woul
clude everything that people called botanists, phy:
chemists, horticulturists, agronomists, or econo1
might have written in regard to conjectures, observations,
or experiments with a bearing on the relation between
structure and function in objects variously termed herbs,
plants, or vegetables. An idea of the abundance of such
source material, even allowing for selection based on
chronological and political criteria, can be had by consult-
ing the very useful catalogue of the works of French bota-
nists who belonged to the Academy of Sciences compiled
by Lucien Plantefol to commemorate the group’s three
hundredth anniversary.’ But a catalogue of prior works is,
at the time it is compiled, a history of botany in the sense
that botany is itself a history, by which I mean an ordered
description, of plants. The history of a science is thus a
summary of readings in a specialized library, a repository
and conservatory of knowledge produced and expounded
from the time of the tablet and papyrus, parchment and
incunabula to that of the magnetic tape. This is, to be sure,
an ideal library, a library of the mind, which by definition
contains a record of everything ever said about the subject.
The totality of the past is represented here as an unbroken
in this expanse it is easy to locate places
from which itis possible to trace a line of progress to what-
ever one’s current object of interest happens to be. Some
historians are quite bold in locating these antecedents,
while others are more cautious. But it is simply boldness
or prudence that distinguishes their work. One can argue,
however, that the history of science is entitled to expect
from epistemology a set of ethical criteria, by which I mean
a set of criteria for judging which moves within the vast
expanse of the past are legitimate and which are not. After
much rigorous argument this is the conclusion reached by
Suzanne Bachelard in her Epistemology and History of Sci-
INTRODUCTION
ence. In her words: “The fact that the historian’s work is
retrospective establishes
powers. The historian constructs his objects in an ideal
space-time, It is up to him to make sure that this space-
time is not imaginary.”
To return to my example, the eighteenth-century bot-
anists who undertook to do research in plant physiology
looked to contemporary animal physiology for models.
Some were physicist-physiologists like Stephen Hales,
while others were chemist-physiologists like Jean Senebier
and Jan Ingenhousz. Yet simply because contemporary
plant physiology uses analytical methods from chemistry
and experimental techniques from physics, it would be au-
dacious to say the least to construct a history in which a
of intention was allowed to conceal a radical
discontinuity of object, for biochemistry and biophysics
have made substantial innovations in the nature of plant
physiology. Between the chemistry of oxidation and the
biochemistry of enzymatic reductions, plant physiology
lar physiology (and cellular theory
of course met with tremendous opposition) and then had
to tid itself of its early concepts of the
in order to study metabolism at the molecular level
remarkable History of Biochemistry Marcel
rowing Gaston Bachelard’s concept of an “epistemological
break,” shows how an enzymatic theory replaced a proto-
lasmic theory as a result of Eduard Biichner's discovery
in 1897) of noncellular fermentation, which for a long,
Pasteurian biology.
It should by now be clear why the past of a present-
day science is not the same thing as that science in the past.
In order to understand the sequence of research, experi-
mentation, and conceptualization without which it would
be impossible to comprehend the work of Gabriel Bertrand
(1897) on the necessary presence of metals in the molecules
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGYof enzymes and on the role of what he called “co-
enzymes,”’ there is no point in going all the way back to
Théodore de Saussure (1765-1845) and his work on plant
nutrition, By contrast, there is good reason to look at
the work of Saussure’s contemporary Brisseau de Mirbel
(1776~1854) and the origins of cellular theory in botany,
which can shed light on the heuristic value of the localiza-
tion within the cell of objects that figured in the early work
‘on enzymatic biochemistry. In other words, events situated
at the same point in historical time may or may not have
theoretical significance, What matters is the overall line of
scientific discourse. A particular end point may be related
to one or more conceptually homogeneous points of de-
parture, Each such trajectory has its own characteristic
nature.
Well, then, the historian of science may object, why
should the role claimed by the epistemologist not be filled
by the scientist? Who but the scientist has the competence
to say, based on his instinct about the direction of future
developments, which end points are of scientific interest
and therefore worthy of historical reconstruction? Such an
appeal to a third party can only surprise or embarrass the
epistemologist. He is well aware that there have been, and
are, scientists who, as respite from their scientific labors,
have turned to writing the history of science, and that there
have been, and are, scientists who, with the aid of episte-
mological concepts borrowed from philosophers, have
written critical histories not without constructive influence
on the subsequent course of scientific progress. Ernst
Mach’s Die Mechanik in ibrer Entwicklung (The Devel-
opment of Mechanics, 1883) is a celebrated case in point,
whose influence on the work of Einstein is well known,
‘Marie-Antoinette Tonnelat has given us a historical and
epistemological case study in her History of the Principle
of Relativity What epistemologist would not subscribe to
INTRODUCTION
her introductory statement, which dismisses a certain ap-
proach to the writing of history:
At the risk of disappointing certain specialists I shall argue
that there is no authentic and unsurpassable principle of
relativity whose earliest development tific theory it
is the job of the historian to describe. No imperfect but
proximation lurks behind the veil of ig-
ince and prejudice awaiting anointment. The very idea
. « Born in the confusion of late Aristo-
telianism, made over by contradictions inherent in the elu-
sive concept of the ether, the idea of relativity in each case
appears to have been associated more with what followed
than with what preceded? An innovative vision, it
ighted its own way and to a large extent even determined
the meandering of its path and the plumbing of its
depths.!°
is one thing to recognize the existence and value of
an epistemological history written by scientists." It is an-
other, however, to argue that the epi
therefore concede that he has no special
tory of science on the grounds that a relation can
be established between the scientist and the history of sci-
‘ence, to the great benefit of the latter. Or that the episte-
mologist must remain an outs
relation to history may appear similar to that of the scien-
tist, his motivation is fundamentally different.
Jean-Toussaint Desanti, having noticed the widening
gap between science and philosophy, questions the rele-
vance of the questions that philosophers—epistemolo-
gists—have posed to scientists concerning the ways and
means by which knowledge is produced.” Since philosoph-
ical discourse does not produce knowledge, is philosophy
disqualified from discussing the conditions of its produc-
tion? “Must one resolve to say nothing about the sciences
that the task of criticism, which is to counter internalis
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGYand mimetic accounts of the work of science, requires
adopting a standpoint within scientific utterance. That this
involves practicing science is a part, by no
means the least important part, of Gaston Bachelard’s
teaching. “One must either say nothing about science or
speak from the inside, that is, by practicing it.” But there
is practice and there is practice. If the word is used in the
sense in which Descartes said that he put his method into
practice in solving mathematical problems,'* it may seem
that productive practice of this kind is not within the phi-
losopher’s reach; if it were, he would be among those in
the vanguard of scientific progress. For the epistemologist,
practicing a science amounts to mimicking the practice of
the scientist by attempting to reconstitute the means by
which knowledge is produced through studious atten-
tion to the papers in which the producer explains his
behavior.'s
Since a scientific investigator in his theoretical work
must necessarily take an interest in the work of his or her
immediate predecessors, and since every immediate prede-
cessor also has an immediate predecessor, it must be con-
ceded that science has a natural interest in its own history,
even if that interest is not very widespread among scien-
tists. But the scientist's historical interest is part of the heu-
tistics of research; hence it does not extend to very remote
antecedents, where “remoteness” is to be construed i
conceptual rather than chronological terms. A particular
nineteenth-century mathematician may have been more in-
terested in, say, Archimedes’ work than in Descartes’,
Everyone's time is limited, moreover, and in the mind of
the scientist the importance of a theoretical advance natu-
rally bulks larger than does historical investigation.
Unlike the scientist, the epistemologist is free to in-
dulge his historical interest if not full-time then at least a
large part of the time. His is an interest of vocation rather
than avocation, for his problem is to abstract from the his-
INTRODUCTION
tory of science in the manifest sense—that is, a more or
less systematic series of pronouncements claiming to state
the truth—in order to uncover the history of science in the
latent sense—that is, the order of conceptual progress that
is visible only after the fact and of which the present notion
of scientific truth is the provisional point of culmination.
Furthermore, because the epistemologist’s historical inter-
est is primary rather than secondary, he can range more
freely than the scientist. His breadth of knowledge can
compensate for the relative inferiority of his mastery of the
latest scientfic discoveries and analytic tools. For example,
Sir Gavin de Beer, in the course of research that led to the
publication of his Notebooks on Transmutation of Species
(1960-1967), became interested in rereading Darwin. His
historical interest was motivated and illuminated by his
work as an embryologist, which enabled him to see Dar-
winian and pre-Darwinian concepts of the relation of on-
togeny to phylogeny in a new light." But when Camille
Limoges, drawing upon previously unpublished work of
Darwin collected, published, and commented on by Gavin
de Beer, challenged an assertion that had been repeated for
nearly a century to the effect that Darwin had derived from
his reading of Malthus the conceptual framework he
needed to make sense of his observations, he revealed a
quite different view of the past.” In effect, Limoges was
challenging that mainstay of traditional historiography, the
concept of influence. Using Darwin as an exampk
sought to illustrate a new way of reading the sources with-
‘out attaching any special privilege to those in which an
author believed that he was explaining his own assump-
tions. By revealing a sharp contrast between the concept of
natural selection and its predecessor, natural economy,
Limoges was able to locate the cleavage between the new
and the old natural history: the key point of contention
was the concept of adaptation, which was now understood
in a probabilistic sense and related to observations of a
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGYbiogeographical (or, as we would now say, ecological)
order."*
‘The interest of epistemology in the history of science
is not new. It is, as I have noted, a matter of vocation. In a
sense, epistemology has always been historical, When the
theory of knowledge ceased to be grounded in an ontology
incapable of accounting for the terms of reference em-
ployed in the new cosmological systems, it became neces-
sary to examine not the justifications but the methods of
science itself. Kant, in the second preface (1787) to the Cri-
tique of Pure Reason, used a brief history of the mathe-
matical and physical sciences, condensed into just a few
lines, to justify his intention to invert the existing relation-
ip between the known and the knowing (le connu et le
connaitre). Commentators on this preface have tradition-
ally stressed the pscudoreversal effected by Copernicus and
neglected, | think wrongly, the novel meaning of the terms
in which Kant defines the driving force behind what he
calls revolutions in the techniques of thinking (Denkart).
The mathematician (first exemplified by, say, Thales or
some other Greek thinker) first had to produce (hervor-
bringen) the objects that figured in his proofs. Similarly, the
physicist (modeled on Galileo or Toricelli) first had to pro-
duce (hervorbringen) the objects of his experiments, and
this production was a result of purely intellectual progress
(Vorangehen). The very fact that Kant believed he could
abstract from scientific work a definitive set of rules and
norms governing the production of knowledge tells us a
great deal about the culture of the period. When one thinks
of categories of scientific thought.
In establishing such a close connection between epis-
temology and the history of science I am of course drawing
on the inspirational teachings of Gaston Bachelard."” The
fundamental concepts of Bachelard’s epistemology are
INTRODUCTION
1
by now well known, so well known, perhaps, that they
have been disseminated and discussed, especially outside
France, in a vulgarized, not to say sanitized, form, devoid
of the polemical force of the original. Among them are the
notions of new scientific spirit, epistemological obstacle,
epistemological break (rupture), and obsolete or “official”
science. Italian, Spanish, German, and even English readers
have come to know Bachelard’s work not firsthand but
through translations of critical commentaries, particularly
that of Dominique Lecourt. To my mind, the best summary
of Bachelard’s research and teaching can be found in the
concluding pages of his last epistemological work, Le Ma-
térialisme rationnel" Here the notion of epistemological
discontinuity in scientific progress is supported by argu-
ments based on the history and teaching of science in the
twentieth century. Bachelard concludes with this state-
ment: “Contemporary science is based on the search for
true (véritable) facts and the synthesis of truthful (véri-
dique) laws.” By truthful Bachelard does not mean that
scientific laws simply tell a truth permanently inscribed in
objects or intellect. ‘Truth is simply what science speaks.
How, then, do we recognize that a statement is scientific?
By the fact that scientific truth never springs fully blown
from the head of its creator. A science is a discourse gov-
emed by critical correction. If this discourse has a history
whose course the historian believes he can reconstruct, itis
because it is a history whose meaning the epistemologist
must reactivate, “Every historian of science is necessarily a
historiographer of truth. The events of science are linked
together in a steadily growing truth. ... At various mo-
ments in the history of thought the past of thought and
experience can be seen in a new light.”2! Guided by this
new light, the historian should not make the error of think-
ing that persistent use of a particular term indicates an in-
variant underlying concept or that persistent allusion to
similar experimental observations connotes affinities of
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGYaa
method or approach. By observing these rules he will avoid
the error of, for instance, seeing Maupertuis as a prema-
ture transformist or geneticist?
There is a clear difference between retrospective criti
cal evaluation of the scientific past in the light of a present
state of knowledge (certain, precisely because it is scien-
tific, to be surpassed or rectified in the future) and system-
atic, quasi-automatic application to the past of some
standard model of scientific theory. The latter is more in
the nature of an epistemological inquisition than a histor-
ical inquiry. The von oben bis unten ot “top-down
method,” as Father Joseph T. Clark calls it, requires the
historian of science to take the analytic philosopher's word
for it that science has now achieved maturity and that in
the future new results will be produced according to the
same logical model as now: Accordingly, the work of the
historian equipped with a finished scientific theory is to ask
why past theories failed to achieve logical maturity. But, as
Ernest Nagel observed in the discussion, to use a contem-
porary model as a universal touchstone results not in pro-
jecting a powerful searchlight into the past but in
inkering our vision. To imagine how, for example, Cop-
ernicus might have overcome certain limitations of his
theory by formalizing all his assumptions is to confound
logical with historical possibility. In Nagel’s view, Clark's
thesis betrays dogmatic confidence in analytic philosophy
and its theory of knowledge.
‘Thus it is easy to distinguish between epistemological
recursion (récurrence épistémologique) and the top-down
method. It is no less easy to distinguish between what
Bachelard calls “normality”? and what Thomas Kuhn
calls “normal science.” The two epistemologies do share
certain points in common: in particular, the observation
that scientific textbooks overemphasize the continuity of
scientific research. Both stress the discontinuous nature of
progress. Nevertheless, while the fundamental concepts
INTRODUCTION
3
share a family resemblance, they do not really belong to
the same branch. This has been noted by Father Francois
Russo, who, despite reservations about the claims of su-
periority to which epistemological historians are some-
times prone, argues that Kuhn is mistaken about the nature
of scientific rationality as such.2? Though ostensibly con-
cerned to preserve Karl Popper's emphasis on the necessity
of theory and its priority over experiment, Kuhn is unable
to shake off the legacy of logical positivism and join the
rationalist camp, where his key concepts of “paradigm”
and “normal science” would seem to place him. These con-
cepts presuppose intentionality and regulation, and as such
they imply the possibility of a break with est:
and procedures. Kuhn would have them play this role
without granting them the means to do so, for he regards
them as simple cultural facts. For a him, a paradigm is the
result of a choice by its users. Normal science is defined by
the practice in a given period of a group of specialists in a
research setting. Instead of concepts of philo-
sophical critique, we are dealing with mere social psychol-
‘ogy. This accounts for the embarrassment evident in the
appendix to the second edition of the Structure of Scientific
Revolutions when it comes to answering the question of
how the truth of a theory is to be understood.
By contrast, when Bachelard speaks of a norm or
itis because in thinking of his favorite science, math-
I physics, he identifies theory with mathematics.
His rationalism is buile on a framework of mathematism.
In mathematics one speaks not of the normal but of the
normed. In contrast to orthodox logical positivists, Bach
lard holds that mathematics has epistemological content,
whether actual or potential, and that progress in mathe-
matics adds to that content. On this point he agrees with
whose critique of logical positivism has lost
vigor or rigor. Cavaillés refutes Carnap by
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGY14
showing that “mathematical reasoning is internally coher-
ent in a way that cannot be rushed. It is by nature progres-
sive.” As to the nature of this progress, he concludes,
One of the fundamental problems with the doctrine of sci-
ence is precisely that progress is in no way comparable to
increasing a given volume by adding a small additional
amount to what is already there, the old subsisting with
the new. Rather, it is perpetual revision, in which some
things are eliminated and others elaborated. What comes
after is greater than what went before, not because the
present contains or supersedes the past but because the one
necessarily emerges from the other and in its content car-
ries the mark of its superiority, which is in each case
unique.”
Nevertheless, the use of epistemological recursion as a
historical method is not universally valid. It best fits the
disciplines for the study of which it was originally devel-
oped: mathematical physics and nuclear chemistry. Of
course there is no reason why one cannot study a particu-
larly advanced speciality and then abstract rules for the
production of knowledge that may with caution be extrap-
olated to other disciplines. In this sense the method can be
not so much generalized as broadened, Yet it cannot be
extended to other areas of the history of science without a
good deal of reflection about the specific nature of the area
to be studied. Consider, for example, eighteenth-century
natural history. Before applying Bachelardian norms and
procedures to the study of this subject, one must ask when
a conceptual cleavage” occurred whose effects were as rev-
olutionary as those of the introduction of relativity and
quantum mechanics into physics. Such a cleavage is barely
perceptible in the early post-Darwin years," and to the ex-
tent that it is visible at all it is only as a result of subsequent
cataclysms: the rise of genetics and molecular biology.
Hence the recursive method must be used judiciously,
and we must learn more about the nature of epistemolog.
INTRODUCTION
15
ical breaks. Often the historian in search of a major water-
shed is tempted to follow Kant in assuming that science
begins with a flash of insight, a work of genius. Frequently
the effects of that flash are said to be all-embracing, affect-
ing the whole of a scientist’s work. But the reality is differ-
cent. Even within one man’s work we often find a series of
fundamental or partial insights rather than a single dra-
matic break. A theory is woven of many strands, some of
which may be quite new while others are borrowed from
older fabrics, The Copernican and Galilean revolutions did
not sweep away tradition in one fell swoop. Alexandre
Koyré has located what he considers to be the decisive
“mutation” in Galileo's work, the decisive change in think-
ing that made him unable to accept medieval mechanics
and astronomy.” For Koyré, the elevation of mathemat-
ics—arithmetic and geometry—to the status of key to
telligibility in physics indicated a rejection of Aristotle in
favor of Plato. Koyré’s argument is sufficiently well known
that I shall not discuss it in detail. But in painting a quite
accurate picture of Galileo as an Archimedean as much as
a Platonist, is not Koyré abusing the freedom of the recur-
sive method? And is he not somewhat overstating the
case in saying that the change in Galileo's thinking marked
a total repudiation of Aristotelianism? Is not Ludovico
Geymonat right to point out that Koyré’s interpretation
neglects all that Galileo preserved from Aristotelian tradi-
tion even as he was proposing that mathematics be used to
bolster logic?* Thus Koyré is himself challenged on the
very point on which he challenged Pierre Duhem when he
wrote, “The apparent continuity in the development of
physics from the Middle Ages to the present (a continuity
that Caverni and Duhem have so assiduously stressed) is
i ‘No matter how well the groundwork has been
ion is still a revolution? **
Parenthetically, it is worth asking why in matters of
‘THE ROLE OF EPISTEMOLOGY
You might also like Endres, T., Müller, R., & Schneider, D. - Kyoto in Davos. Intercultural Readings of The Cassirer-Heidegger Debate (2024) PDF
Endres, T., Müller, R., & Schneider, D. - Kyoto in Davos. Intercultural Readings of The Cassirer-Heidegger Debate (2024)
561 pages